SlideShare ist ein Scribd-Unternehmen logo
1 von 21
Term Paper for the requirement of 
Mphil Degree 
Topic: Presupposition 
Supervised by: Dr. Iqbal Butt 
Name: Ijaz Ahmed 
Discipline: Mphil in Linguistics 
Institution: NCBA&E Gujrat Campus
Abbstract 
In this paper presupposition had been discussed in detail its types and its triggers. And 
data had been taken from short story Button, Button written by Richard Mathson. And 
quantitative research methodology had been applied for this research.
Acknowledgement 
I would like to express my special appreciation and thanks to my advisor Professor Dr. 
Iqbal Butt you have been a tremendous mentor for me. I would like to thank you for encouraging 
my research and for allowing me to grow as a research scientist. Your advice on both research as 
well as on my career have been priceless.. I also want to thank you for letting my defense be an 
enjoyable moment, and for your brilliant comments and suggestions, thanks to you..A special 
thanks to my family. Words cannot express how grateful I am to my mother-in law, father-in-law, 
my mother, and father for all of the sacrifices that you’ve made on my behalf. Your prayer 
for me was what sustained me thus far. I would also like to thank all of my friends who 
supported me in writing, and incented me to strive towards my goal. At the end I would like to 
thank my Allah Who blessed me with His blessings a lot.
Table of content 
Chapter 1 …………………………………………. 
Introduction 
Chapter 2…………………………………………… 
Literature Review 
Chapter 3 …………………………………………… 
Data Analysis 
Chapter 4…………………………………………… 
Conclusion
Chapter 1 
Introduction: 
In the branch of linguistics known as pragmatics, a presupposition (or ps) is an implicit 
assumption about the world or background belief relating to an utterance whose truth is taken for 
granted in discourse. Examples of presuppositions include: 
 Jane no longer writes fiction. 
 Presupposition: Jane once wrote fiction. 
 Have you stopped eating meat? 
 Presupposition: you had once eaten meat. 
 Have you talked to Hans? 
 Presupposition: Hans exists. 
A presupposition must be mutually known or assumed by the speaker and addressee for 
the utterance to be considered appropriate in context. It will generally remain a necessary 
assumption whether the utterance is placed in the form of an assertion, denial, or question, and 
can be associated with a specific lexical item or grammatical feature (presupposition trigger) in 
the utterance.
Crucially, negation of an expression does not change its presuppositions: I want to do it 
again and I don't want to do it again both presuppose that the subject has done it already one or 
more times; My wife is pregnant and My wife is not pregnant both presuppose that the subject 
has a wife. In this respect, presupposition is distinguished from entailmentand implicature. For 
example, The president was assassinated entails that The president is dead, but if the expression 
is negated, the entailment is not necessarily true. 
Negation of sentence containing a Presupposition 
Presuppositions of a sentence are not consistent with the actual state of affairs, then one of 
two approaches can be taken. Given the sentences My wife is pregnant and My wife is not 
pregnant when one has no wife, then either: 
1. Both the sentence and its negation are false; or 
2. Strawson's approach: Both "my wife is pregnant" and "my wife is not pregnant" use a 
wrong presupposition (i.e. that there exists a referent which can be described with the 
noun phrase my wife) and therefore can not be assigned truth values. 
Bertrand Russell tries to solve this dilemma with two interpretations of the negated sentence: 
1. "There exists exactly one person, who is my wife and who is not pregnant" 
2. "There does not exist exactly one person, who is my wife and who is pregnant."
For the first phrase, Russell would claim that it is false, whereas the second would be true 
according to him. 
Presupposition Triggers 
A presupposition trigger is a lexical item or linguistic construction which is responsible for the 
presupposition.[2] The following is a selection of presuppositional triggers following Stephen C. Levinson 
classic textbook on Pragmatics, which in turn draws on a list produced by Lauri Karttunen. As is customary, 
the presuppositional triggers themselves are italicized, and the symbol » stands for 'presupposes' 
Definite descriptions 
Definite descriptions are phrases of the form "the X" where X is a noun phrase. The description is said to 
be properwhen the phrase applies to exactly one object, and conversely, it is said to be improper when either 
there exist more than one potential referents, as in "the senator from Ohio", or none at all, as in "the king of 
France". In conventional speech, definite descriptions are implicitly assumed to be proper, hence such phrases 
trigger the presupposition that the referent is unique and existent. 
 John saw the man with two heads. 
»there exists a man with two heads. 
Factive verbs 
In Western epistemology, there is a tradition originating with Plato of defining knowledge as justified 
true belief. On this definition, for someone to know X, it is required that X be true. A linguistic question thus
arises regarding the usage of such phrases: does a person who states "John knows X" implicitly claim the truth 
of X? Steven Pinkerexplored this question in a popular science format in a 2007 book on language and 
cognition, using a widely publicized example from a speech by a U.S. president.[4] A 2003 speech by George 
W. Bush included the line, "British Intelligence has learned that Saddam Hussein recently sought significant 
quantities of uranium from Africa."[5] Over the next few years, it became apparent that this intelligence lead 
was incorrect. But the way the speech was phrased, using a factive verb, implicitly framed the lead as truth 
rather than hypothesis. The factivity thesis, the proposition that relational predicates having to do with 
knowledge, such as knows, learn, remembers, and realized, presuppose the factual truth of their object, 
however, was subject to notable criticism by Allan Hazlett.[6] 
 Martha regrets drinking John's home brew. 
»Martha drank John's home brew. 
 Frankenstein was aware that Dracula was there. 
»Dracula was there. 
 John realized that he was in debt. 
»John was in debt. 
 It was odd how proud he was. 
»He was proud. 
Implicative verbs 
 John managed to open the door. 
»John tried to open the door. 
 John forgot to lock the door. 
»John ought to have locked, or intended to lock, the door. 
Some further implicative predicates: X happened to V»X didn't plan or intend to V; X avoided Ving»X was 
expected to, or usually did, or ought to V, etc.
Change of state verbs 
 John stopped teasing his wife. 
»John had been teasing his wife. 
 Joan began teasing her husband. 
»Joan hadn't been teasing her husband. 
Some further change of state verbs: start; finish; carry on; cease; take (as in X took Y from Z » Y was 
at/in/with Z);leave; enter; come; go; arrive; etc. 
Iteratives 
 The flying saucer came again. 
»The flying saucer came before. 
 You can't get gobstoppers anymore. 
»You once could get gobstoppers. 
 Carter returned to power. 
»Carter held power before. 
Further iteratives: another time; to come back; restore; repeat; for the nth time. 
Temporal clauses 
 Before Strawson was even born, Frege noticed presuppositions. 
»Strawson was born. 
 While Chomsky was revolutionizing linguistics, the rest of social science was asleep. 
»Chomsky was revolutionizing linguistics.
 Since Churchill died, we've lacked a leader. 
»Churchill died. 
Further temporal clause constructors: after; during; whenever; as (as in As John was getting up, he slipped). 
Cleft sentences 
 Cleft construction: It was Henry that kissed Rosie. 
»Someone kissed Rosie. 
 Pseudo-cleft construction: What John lost was his wallet. 
»John lost something. 
Comparisons and contrasts 
Comparisons and contrasts may be marked by stress (or by other prosodic means), by particles like 
"too", or by comparatives constructions. 
 Marianne called Adolph a male chauvinist, and then HE insulted HER. 
»For Marianne to call Adolph a male chauvinist would be to insult him. 
 Carol is a better linguist than Barbara. 
»Barbara is a linguist. 
Counterfactual conditionals 
 If the notice had only said 'mine-field' in Welsh as well as in English, we would never have lost poor 
Llewellyn. 
»The notice didn't say 'mine-field' in Welsh.
Questions 
Presuppose a seeking for what is sought. 
Possessive case 
 John's children are very noisy. 
»John has children.
Chapter 2 
Literature Review: 
The idea that there are CONTEXTUALPR ESUPPOSITIONS over and above 
SEMANTIC PRESUPPOSITIONS has been gaining in popularity in both linguistics and 
philosophy. Some linguists and philosophers even argue that the semantic notion of presupposi-tion 
should be abandoned in favor of the contextual one. The notion of semantic presupposition 
enters contemporary philosophy of language and linguistics from the work of the logician and 
philosopher Frege (1892), who was primarily interested in developing an account of the logical 
form of sentences in which meaningfulness was not a suffi-cient condition for statementhood. 
For him, the condition under which declarative sentences make a statement (bear a truth value) 
was that each of their referring expressions should succeed in referring to an appropriate object 
or objects. In Frege's view, the content of such presuppositions (i.e. what properties of an object 
or objects make them 'appropriate', or what the requirement for success is) was something that 
depended on the grammatical structure of sentences. A contextual presupposition differs from a 
semantic one in that the content of the latter condition is determined by the grammatical structure 
of a sentence type, whereas the content of the former condition is determined also by features of 
the context in which a sentence token occurs. Contextual presupposition naturally applies to 
utterances, while semantic presupposition naturally applies to sentences of a language. 
Moreover, this difference should not be obscured by the fact that both kinds of presupposition 
are conditions whose satisfaction normally requires a relation between something linguistic and 
the world. Those who first developed a semantic theory within the theory of TG grammar
characterized the level of semantic representation as consisting of formal structures from which 
the semantic properties and relations of sentences can be determined. 1 See, for example, Green 
1968, Lakoff 1971, Horn 1972, Morgan 1973, and Stalnaker 1974. 2 See also Karttunen 1974, 
MS. 
Thus the optimal semantic representation of a sentence in a grammar is whatever formal 
structure provides the simplest basis for predicting whether it is meaningful, ambiguous, 
analytic, synonymous with such-and-such other sentences, etc. (Katz 1972, ch. I). The 
specification of such semantic properties and relations was left open-ended, in order to 
accommodate further cases that might turn out to be pre-dictable from the semantic 
representations developed to predict meaningfulness, ambiguity, analyticity etc. Presupposition 
was incorporated into semantic theory on the hypothesis that it is one of these further cases (Katz 
1965:597-8, 1966: 211-20). Introducing presupposition as one of the semantic properties and 
relations that must be predicted from an optimal semantic representation raises questions both 
about the interpretation of this notion-e.g. whether it should be interpreted logically, 
situationally, or in some other manner-and about the proper formal devices to use in constructing 
semantic representations. Both these questions have been discussed (Katz 1972:127-50). A 
contribution to these discussions was made by Langendoen & Savin (1971), who saw clearly that 
the formal devices required for constructing semantic representations from which 
presuppositions could be predicted would have to be part of the same machinery that provides a 
composi-tional analysis of the meaning of a sentence. Their empirical survey of the facts about 
how the presuppositions of the components of a complex sentence are related to the 
presupposition of the complex sentence as a whole led them to formulate the following
hypothesis: (1) Each of the presuppositions of a component sentence in a complex sentence is a 
presupposition of the entire complex sentence. But counter-examples were soon pointed out. 
Morgan 1969 observes that 1 fails for sentences like: (2) If Jack has children, then all of Jack's 
children are bald. As Austin 1963 points out, sentence 3, the consequent clause of 2, by itself 
pre-supposes the existence of people who are children of Jack: (3) All of Jack's children are bald. 
Austin writes (p. 17): 'Not only [3] but equally "[Jack's] children are not bald", presupposes that 
[Jack] has children. To talk about those children, or to refer to them, presupposes that they exist.' 
Yet as Morgan observes, 2 presupposes nothing beyond the existence of Jack; so here the 
presupposition of a component sentence of a complex sentence is not a presupposition of the 
entire sentence. Further, as Katz 1972 and Karttunen 1973 observe, the presuppositions 
associated with an expression in a sentence are not, in general, associated with the complex 
sentences in which such a sentence appears as a verbal complement, because referentially opaque 
verbs remove such presupposi-tions. Thus, in a sentence like 4, there is no presupposition that 
Santa Claus exists: (4) Bob believes that Santa Claus came last night. As Karttunen (1973:173) 
puts it, one must distinguish between HOLES, PLUGS, and FILTERS-i.e., positions that let the 
presuppositions associated with the expressions appearing in them become presuppositions of the 
entire sentence, positions that do not let them, and positions that sometimes do and sometimes do 
not.3 To avoid such counter-examples, we might restate the Langendoen-Savin hypothesis as 
follows: (5) Each of the presuppositions of a component sentence in a complex sentence is a 
presupposition of the entire complex sentence just in case it is associated with an expression that 
appears in a hole. But 5 amounts to no more than a triviality, since holes have been characterized 
so far as positions that let the presupposition of the expression occupying them become 
presuppositions of the entire sentence. Thus the problem is twofold: an adequate semantic theory
must also set up machinery to explicate formally these metaphorical notions of holes, plugs, and 
filters. That is, it must provide, in terms of such machinery, the projection mechanism that 
explains 5 and 6, and tells us when the filters are open and closed: (6) No presuppositions of a 
component sentence in a complex sentence are presuppositions of the entire complex sentence if 
they are associated with expressions that appear in a plug. This is done by Katz (1972, MS) as 
part of the formal theory of compositional semantic interpretation. In the next section, we briefly 
sketch how that machinery works. Katz (1972:167) proposes that the referential positions in 
propositions (senses of sentences) be formally represented by the notation of enclosure within 
heavy parentheses, to distinguish them from non-referential positions. Besides non-referential 
positions created by verbs of propositional attitude, such as believes in 4, the subject of exists is 
non-referential in our sense. The position occupied by poisonous mushrooms in 7 is non-referential, 
but its position in 8 is referential: (7) Poisonous mushrooms exist. (8) Poisonous 
mushrooms killed the elephant. Since 7 asserts that there are poisonous mushrooms, it cannot be 
represented as presupposing the existence of poisonous mushrooms. If it were so represented, it 
would be described as having its truth condition included in its condition of statementhood, and 
it would be mistakenly marked as analytic (Katz 1972: 172-8). The sense of 'referential' 
represented by a pair of heavy parentheses is different from the standard one in terms of 
substitutivity of identicals (Katz 1972:141)- since, supposing that toadstools is coreferential with 
poisonous mushrooms, we can substitute the former for the latter in 7 as well as 8, preserving 
truth. Yet, as we have just seen, we cannot regard the term position of 7 as referential in the 
sense of presuppositional reference. Thus the interpretation of heavy parentheses in a reading is 
simply this: a necessary condition on the (assertive) proposition repre-sented by the reading 
being a statement (i.e. either true or false) is that the reading
Chapter 3 
Data Analysis: 
The data has been taken from the short story Button, Button written by Richard Mathson. 
And the methodology which has been applied for this data analysis is quantitative. Through data 
analysis diffferrent kinds of presupposition will be hilighted. 
Sentence Presupposition Kind of Presupposition 
"I'm Mr. Steward." 
Mr.Steward exixts 
Existential 
She was sure now it was a 
sales pitch. 
She was not suie before lexical 
"May I come in?" asked Mr. 
Steward. 
He was not 
in 
lexical 
" Don't you want to know what 
it is?" 
She does not know about it Structural 
I don't think so." she 
replied. 
She thinks factive 
"It could prove very valuable," It is valuable lexical
he told her. 
. 
. "What are you 
trying to sell?" she asked. 
He is selling something Structural 
"I'm not selling anything," he 
answered. 
He is doing something else 
instead of selling 
lexical 
"Oh, the __________" Arthur 
pointed toward the living room 
Living room exixts exixtenttial 
. "What is that gadget, 
anyway?" 
Gadget exixts Exixtential 
"If you are selling something 
_______" Arthur said. 
Mr. Steward shook his head. 
"I'm not" 
He is not selling anything Counterfactual 
. He reached into an inside 
coat pocket and withdrew a 
small 
sealed envelope 
Coat pocket and envelope 
exixt 
exixtential
"The bell is connected to 
our office 
Bell exixts exixtential 
"If you push the button," Mr. 
Steward told him, 
"somewhere in 
the world someone you don't 
know will die 
He does not push the button 
before 
counterfactural 
In return for which you 
will receive a payment of 
$50,000." 
Dollar exixts exixtential 
Norma stared at the small 
man. He was smiling. 
Small man exixts Exixtentail 
"What are you talking about?" 
Arthur asked him. 
He is talking Structural 
"But I've just explained," he 
said 
He has explained earlier lexical 
"Is this a practical joke?" 
asked Arthur. 
This is a joke structural 
"Not at all. The offer is 
completely genuine." 
It is an offere Lexical
"Who do you represent?" 
demanded Norma 
He represents structural 
"However, I assure you, the 
organization is of international 
scope." 
Organization exixts Exixtenntial 
"And take your button unit 
with you." 
Button exixts exixtential
Chapter 4 
Conclusion: 
At the end it can be concluded that presupposition play an important role between speaker 
and adressee commun A presupposition must be equally known or understood by the presenter 
and receiver for the statement to be measured suitable in context. It will generally remain a 
necessary assumption whether the utterance is placed in the form of an assertion, denial, or 
question, and can be associated with a specific lexical item or grammatical feature 
(presupposition trigger) in the utterance. It is also noticed that negation does not change 
presupposition.
Bibliography 
FREGE,G . 1892. Uber Sinn und Bedeutung. Zeitschriftf ur Philosophie und Philoso-phische 
Kritik 100.25-50. [In Translations from the philosophical writings of Gottlob Frege, ed. by P. T. 
Geach & M. Black, 68-74. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1952.] 
KATZ, J. J. 1965. The relevance of linguistics to philosophy. Journal of Philosophy 62.590-601. 
--. 1966. The philosophy of language. New York: Harper & Row. --. 1972. Semantic theory. 
SEARLE, J. R. 1969. Speech acts. Cambridge: University Press. STALNAKER, R. 1974. 
Pragmatic presuppositions. Semantics and philosophy, ed. by M. K. Munitz and P. K. Unger, 
197-214. New York: NYU Press 
HORN, L. 1972. On the semantic properties of logical operators in English. UCLA dissertation 
KARTTUNEN, L. 1973. Presuppositionso f compound sentences. Linguistic Inquiry 4. 169-93. 
HARNISH, M. MS.L ogicalf orm and implicature.T o appeari n Bever,K atz & Langendoen. 
FREGE,G . 1892. Uber Sinn und Bedeutung. Zeitschriftf ur Philosophie und Philoso-phische 
Kritik 100.25-50. [In Translations from the philosophical writings of Gottlob Frege, ed. by P. T. 
Geach & M. Black, 68-74. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1952.]

Weitere ähnliche Inhalte

Was ist angesagt?

03 reference and inference
03 reference and inference03 reference and inference
03 reference and inferencegadis pratiwi
 
The role of context in interpretation
The role of context in interpretationThe role of context in interpretation
The role of context in interpretationH. R. Marasabessy
 
Cooperative principles and implicatures
Cooperative principles and implicaturesCooperative principles and implicatures
Cooperative principles and implicaturesAhmed Qadoury Abed
 
Aya sentence relation and truth
Aya sentence relation and truthAya sentence relation and truth
Aya sentence relation and truthMYlove99
 
Deixis presentation
Deixis presentationDeixis presentation
Deixis presentationIjaz Ahmed
 
Aspects of Semantic Knowledge_Sentences-Utterances-Propositions
Aspects of Semantic Knowledge_Sentences-Utterances-PropositionsAspects of Semantic Knowledge_Sentences-Utterances-Propositions
Aspects of Semantic Knowledge_Sentences-Utterances-PropositionsMelati Akmilia
 
Lecture 3 implicature
Lecture  3 implicatureLecture  3 implicature
Lecture 3 implicatureAdel Thamery
 
Reference And Inference By Dr.Shadia.Pptx
Reference And Inference  By Dr.Shadia.PptxReference And Inference  By Dr.Shadia.Pptx
Reference And Inference By Dr.Shadia.PptxDr. Shadia Banjar
 
Presupposition and entailment
Presupposition and entailmentPresupposition and entailment
Presupposition and entailmentAnna Shelley
 
deixis-and-distance
deixis-and-distancedeixis-and-distance
deixis-and-distanceSeemab Abbas
 

Was ist angesagt? (20)

03 reference and inference
03 reference and inference03 reference and inference
03 reference and inference
 
Presupposition
PresuppositionPresupposition
Presupposition
 
Pragmatics: Deixis
Pragmatics: DeixisPragmatics: Deixis
Pragmatics: Deixis
 
The role of context in interpretation
The role of context in interpretationThe role of context in interpretation
The role of context in interpretation
 
Reference and inference
Reference and inferenceReference and inference
Reference and inference
 
Cooperative principles and implicatures
Cooperative principles and implicaturesCooperative principles and implicatures
Cooperative principles and implicatures
 
Aya sentence relation and truth
Aya sentence relation and truthAya sentence relation and truth
Aya sentence relation and truth
 
Deixis presentation
Deixis presentationDeixis presentation
Deixis presentation
 
Pragmatics (Speech Acts)
Pragmatics (Speech Acts)Pragmatics (Speech Acts)
Pragmatics (Speech Acts)
 
Aspects of Semantic Knowledge_Sentences-Utterances-Propositions
Aspects of Semantic Knowledge_Sentences-Utterances-PropositionsAspects of Semantic Knowledge_Sentences-Utterances-Propositions
Aspects of Semantic Knowledge_Sentences-Utterances-Propositions
 
Lecture 3 implicature
Lecture  3 implicatureLecture  3 implicature
Lecture 3 implicature
 
3 the referential-theory2
3 the referential-theory23 the referential-theory2
3 the referential-theory2
 
Reference And Inference By Dr.Shadia.Pptx
Reference And Inference  By Dr.Shadia.PptxReference And Inference  By Dr.Shadia.Pptx
Reference And Inference By Dr.Shadia.Pptx
 
Presupposition and entailment
Presupposition and entailmentPresupposition and entailment
Presupposition and entailment
 
Deixis
Deixis Deixis
Deixis
 
Generalized conversational
Generalized conversationalGeneralized conversational
Generalized conversational
 
X bar ppt
X bar pptX bar ppt
X bar ppt
 
Logic
LogicLogic
Logic
 
PRAGMATICS: CONCEPT OF IMPLICATURE
PRAGMATICS: CONCEPT OF IMPLICATUREPRAGMATICS: CONCEPT OF IMPLICATURE
PRAGMATICS: CONCEPT OF IMPLICATURE
 
deixis-and-distance
deixis-and-distancedeixis-and-distance
deixis-and-distance
 

Andere mochten auch

Presupposition and-entailment
Presupposition and-entailmentPresupposition and-entailment
Presupposition and-entailmentRadia Ali
 
Types of Presupposition
Types of PresuppositionTypes of Presupposition
Types of Presuppositionsheroz_ramzan
 
SEMANTICS AND PRAGMATICS - PRESUPPOSITIONS AND ENTAILMENTS
SEMANTICS AND PRAGMATICS - PRESUPPOSITIONS AND ENTAILMENTSSEMANTICS AND PRAGMATICS - PRESUPPOSITIONS AND ENTAILMENTS
SEMANTICS AND PRAGMATICS - PRESUPPOSITIONS AND ENTAILMENTSMusfera Nara Vadia
 
Pragmatics (Linguistics)
Pragmatics (Linguistics)Pragmatics (Linguistics)
Pragmatics (Linguistics)Coltz Mejia
 
Pragmatics: Deixis And Distance By Dr.Shadia.Pptx
Pragmatics:  Deixis And Distance By Dr.Shadia.PptxPragmatics:  Deixis And Distance By Dr.Shadia.Pptx
Pragmatics: Deixis And Distance By Dr.Shadia.PptxDr. Shadia Banjar
 
Presentation on deixis and distance
Presentation on deixis and distancePresentation on deixis and distance
Presentation on deixis and distanceTaiba Arooj
 
Pragmatics - George Yule
Pragmatics - George YulePragmatics - George Yule
Pragmatics - George YuleAnthony Salinas
 

Andere mochten auch (10)

Presupposition and-entailment
Presupposition and-entailmentPresupposition and-entailment
Presupposition and-entailment
 
Presupposition
PresuppositionPresupposition
Presupposition
 
Types of Presupposition
Types of PresuppositionTypes of Presupposition
Types of Presupposition
 
SEMANTICS AND PRAGMATICS - PRESUPPOSITIONS AND ENTAILMENTS
SEMANTICS AND PRAGMATICS - PRESUPPOSITIONS AND ENTAILMENTSSEMANTICS AND PRAGMATICS - PRESUPPOSITIONS AND ENTAILMENTS
SEMANTICS AND PRAGMATICS - PRESUPPOSITIONS AND ENTAILMENTS
 
Pragmatics
PragmaticsPragmatics
Pragmatics
 
What is pragmatics
What is pragmaticsWhat is pragmatics
What is pragmatics
 
Pragmatics (Linguistics)
Pragmatics (Linguistics)Pragmatics (Linguistics)
Pragmatics (Linguistics)
 
Pragmatics: Deixis And Distance By Dr.Shadia.Pptx
Pragmatics:  Deixis And Distance By Dr.Shadia.PptxPragmatics:  Deixis And Distance By Dr.Shadia.Pptx
Pragmatics: Deixis And Distance By Dr.Shadia.Pptx
 
Presentation on deixis and distance
Presentation on deixis and distancePresentation on deixis and distance
Presentation on deixis and distance
 
Pragmatics - George Yule
Pragmatics - George YulePragmatics - George Yule
Pragmatics - George Yule
 

Ähnlich wie Term paper of pragmatics presupposition

Ähnlich wie Term paper of pragmatics presupposition (12)

Language and the body
Language and the bodyLanguage and the body
Language and the body
 
Religious language
Religious languageReligious language
Religious language
 
Voice 100916102926-phpapp01
Voice 100916102926-phpapp01Voice 100916102926-phpapp01
Voice 100916102926-phpapp01
 
Rebuttal of Innatism
Rebuttal of Innatism Rebuttal of Innatism
Rebuttal of Innatism
 
Teheran 2Please revise your Reflection Paper #1 according to m.docx
Teheran 2Please revise your Reflection Paper #1 according to m.docxTeheran 2Please revise your Reflection Paper #1 according to m.docx
Teheran 2Please revise your Reflection Paper #1 according to m.docx
 
Comparison Essay Topics For College.pdf
Comparison Essay Topics For College.pdfComparison Essay Topics For College.pdf
Comparison Essay Topics For College.pdf
 
Voice
VoiceVoice
Voice
 
550ExistenceII.ppt
550ExistenceII.ppt550ExistenceII.ppt
550ExistenceII.ppt
 
Purposes, Means and Convictionsin DaoismA Berlin Symposi.docx
Purposes, Means and Convictionsin DaoismA Berlin Symposi.docxPurposes, Means and Convictionsin DaoismA Berlin Symposi.docx
Purposes, Means and Convictionsin DaoismA Berlin Symposi.docx
 
Elements Of Epistemology ~ Chapter 2
Elements Of Epistemology ~ Chapter 2Elements Of Epistemology ~ Chapter 2
Elements Of Epistemology ~ Chapter 2
 
Theory, text and context
Theory, text and contextTheory, text and context
Theory, text and context
 
Chapter 6
Chapter 6Chapter 6
Chapter 6
 

Mehr von Muhammad Sajjad Raja

Mehr von Muhammad Sajjad Raja (6)

Presentation error analysis
Presentation error analysisPresentation error analysis
Presentation error analysis
 
Pragmaticspresentation 140705125246-phpapp02
Pragmaticspresentation 140705125246-phpapp02Pragmaticspresentation 140705125246-phpapp02
Pragmaticspresentation 140705125246-phpapp02
 
Pragmatics 1225480010541171-9
Pragmatics 1225480010541171-9Pragmatics 1225480010541171-9
Pragmatics 1225480010541171-9
 
What is pragmatics ppt final
What is pragmatics ppt finalWhat is pragmatics ppt final
What is pragmatics ppt final
 
Tt sociolinguistics
Tt   sociolinguisticsTt   sociolinguistics
Tt sociolinguistics
 
Ppt of-interlanguage-chapter-3
Ppt of-interlanguage-chapter-3Ppt of-interlanguage-chapter-3
Ppt of-interlanguage-chapter-3
 

Term paper of pragmatics presupposition

  • 1. Term Paper for the requirement of Mphil Degree Topic: Presupposition Supervised by: Dr. Iqbal Butt Name: Ijaz Ahmed Discipline: Mphil in Linguistics Institution: NCBA&E Gujrat Campus
  • 2. Abbstract In this paper presupposition had been discussed in detail its types and its triggers. And data had been taken from short story Button, Button written by Richard Mathson. And quantitative research methodology had been applied for this research.
  • 3. Acknowledgement I would like to express my special appreciation and thanks to my advisor Professor Dr. Iqbal Butt you have been a tremendous mentor for me. I would like to thank you for encouraging my research and for allowing me to grow as a research scientist. Your advice on both research as well as on my career have been priceless.. I also want to thank you for letting my defense be an enjoyable moment, and for your brilliant comments and suggestions, thanks to you..A special thanks to my family. Words cannot express how grateful I am to my mother-in law, father-in-law, my mother, and father for all of the sacrifices that you’ve made on my behalf. Your prayer for me was what sustained me thus far. I would also like to thank all of my friends who supported me in writing, and incented me to strive towards my goal. At the end I would like to thank my Allah Who blessed me with His blessings a lot.
  • 4. Table of content Chapter 1 …………………………………………. Introduction Chapter 2…………………………………………… Literature Review Chapter 3 …………………………………………… Data Analysis Chapter 4…………………………………………… Conclusion
  • 5. Chapter 1 Introduction: In the branch of linguistics known as pragmatics, a presupposition (or ps) is an implicit assumption about the world or background belief relating to an utterance whose truth is taken for granted in discourse. Examples of presuppositions include:  Jane no longer writes fiction.  Presupposition: Jane once wrote fiction.  Have you stopped eating meat?  Presupposition: you had once eaten meat.  Have you talked to Hans?  Presupposition: Hans exists. A presupposition must be mutually known or assumed by the speaker and addressee for the utterance to be considered appropriate in context. It will generally remain a necessary assumption whether the utterance is placed in the form of an assertion, denial, or question, and can be associated with a specific lexical item or grammatical feature (presupposition trigger) in the utterance.
  • 6. Crucially, negation of an expression does not change its presuppositions: I want to do it again and I don't want to do it again both presuppose that the subject has done it already one or more times; My wife is pregnant and My wife is not pregnant both presuppose that the subject has a wife. In this respect, presupposition is distinguished from entailmentand implicature. For example, The president was assassinated entails that The president is dead, but if the expression is negated, the entailment is not necessarily true. Negation of sentence containing a Presupposition Presuppositions of a sentence are not consistent with the actual state of affairs, then one of two approaches can be taken. Given the sentences My wife is pregnant and My wife is not pregnant when one has no wife, then either: 1. Both the sentence and its negation are false; or 2. Strawson's approach: Both "my wife is pregnant" and "my wife is not pregnant" use a wrong presupposition (i.e. that there exists a referent which can be described with the noun phrase my wife) and therefore can not be assigned truth values. Bertrand Russell tries to solve this dilemma with two interpretations of the negated sentence: 1. "There exists exactly one person, who is my wife and who is not pregnant" 2. "There does not exist exactly one person, who is my wife and who is pregnant."
  • 7. For the first phrase, Russell would claim that it is false, whereas the second would be true according to him. Presupposition Triggers A presupposition trigger is a lexical item or linguistic construction which is responsible for the presupposition.[2] The following is a selection of presuppositional triggers following Stephen C. Levinson classic textbook on Pragmatics, which in turn draws on a list produced by Lauri Karttunen. As is customary, the presuppositional triggers themselves are italicized, and the symbol » stands for 'presupposes' Definite descriptions Definite descriptions are phrases of the form "the X" where X is a noun phrase. The description is said to be properwhen the phrase applies to exactly one object, and conversely, it is said to be improper when either there exist more than one potential referents, as in "the senator from Ohio", or none at all, as in "the king of France". In conventional speech, definite descriptions are implicitly assumed to be proper, hence such phrases trigger the presupposition that the referent is unique and existent.  John saw the man with two heads. »there exists a man with two heads. Factive verbs In Western epistemology, there is a tradition originating with Plato of defining knowledge as justified true belief. On this definition, for someone to know X, it is required that X be true. A linguistic question thus
  • 8. arises regarding the usage of such phrases: does a person who states "John knows X" implicitly claim the truth of X? Steven Pinkerexplored this question in a popular science format in a 2007 book on language and cognition, using a widely publicized example from a speech by a U.S. president.[4] A 2003 speech by George W. Bush included the line, "British Intelligence has learned that Saddam Hussein recently sought significant quantities of uranium from Africa."[5] Over the next few years, it became apparent that this intelligence lead was incorrect. But the way the speech was phrased, using a factive verb, implicitly framed the lead as truth rather than hypothesis. The factivity thesis, the proposition that relational predicates having to do with knowledge, such as knows, learn, remembers, and realized, presuppose the factual truth of their object, however, was subject to notable criticism by Allan Hazlett.[6]  Martha regrets drinking John's home brew. »Martha drank John's home brew.  Frankenstein was aware that Dracula was there. »Dracula was there.  John realized that he was in debt. »John was in debt.  It was odd how proud he was. »He was proud. Implicative verbs  John managed to open the door. »John tried to open the door.  John forgot to lock the door. »John ought to have locked, or intended to lock, the door. Some further implicative predicates: X happened to V»X didn't plan or intend to V; X avoided Ving»X was expected to, or usually did, or ought to V, etc.
  • 9. Change of state verbs  John stopped teasing his wife. »John had been teasing his wife.  Joan began teasing her husband. »Joan hadn't been teasing her husband. Some further change of state verbs: start; finish; carry on; cease; take (as in X took Y from Z » Y was at/in/with Z);leave; enter; come; go; arrive; etc. Iteratives  The flying saucer came again. »The flying saucer came before.  You can't get gobstoppers anymore. »You once could get gobstoppers.  Carter returned to power. »Carter held power before. Further iteratives: another time; to come back; restore; repeat; for the nth time. Temporal clauses  Before Strawson was even born, Frege noticed presuppositions. »Strawson was born.  While Chomsky was revolutionizing linguistics, the rest of social science was asleep. »Chomsky was revolutionizing linguistics.
  • 10.  Since Churchill died, we've lacked a leader. »Churchill died. Further temporal clause constructors: after; during; whenever; as (as in As John was getting up, he slipped). Cleft sentences  Cleft construction: It was Henry that kissed Rosie. »Someone kissed Rosie.  Pseudo-cleft construction: What John lost was his wallet. »John lost something. Comparisons and contrasts Comparisons and contrasts may be marked by stress (or by other prosodic means), by particles like "too", or by comparatives constructions.  Marianne called Adolph a male chauvinist, and then HE insulted HER. »For Marianne to call Adolph a male chauvinist would be to insult him.  Carol is a better linguist than Barbara. »Barbara is a linguist. Counterfactual conditionals  If the notice had only said 'mine-field' in Welsh as well as in English, we would never have lost poor Llewellyn. »The notice didn't say 'mine-field' in Welsh.
  • 11. Questions Presuppose a seeking for what is sought. Possessive case  John's children are very noisy. »John has children.
  • 12. Chapter 2 Literature Review: The idea that there are CONTEXTUALPR ESUPPOSITIONS over and above SEMANTIC PRESUPPOSITIONS has been gaining in popularity in both linguistics and philosophy. Some linguists and philosophers even argue that the semantic notion of presupposi-tion should be abandoned in favor of the contextual one. The notion of semantic presupposition enters contemporary philosophy of language and linguistics from the work of the logician and philosopher Frege (1892), who was primarily interested in developing an account of the logical form of sentences in which meaningfulness was not a suffi-cient condition for statementhood. For him, the condition under which declarative sentences make a statement (bear a truth value) was that each of their referring expressions should succeed in referring to an appropriate object or objects. In Frege's view, the content of such presuppositions (i.e. what properties of an object or objects make them 'appropriate', or what the requirement for success is) was something that depended on the grammatical structure of sentences. A contextual presupposition differs from a semantic one in that the content of the latter condition is determined by the grammatical structure of a sentence type, whereas the content of the former condition is determined also by features of the context in which a sentence token occurs. Contextual presupposition naturally applies to utterances, while semantic presupposition naturally applies to sentences of a language. Moreover, this difference should not be obscured by the fact that both kinds of presupposition are conditions whose satisfaction normally requires a relation between something linguistic and the world. Those who first developed a semantic theory within the theory of TG grammar
  • 13. characterized the level of semantic representation as consisting of formal structures from which the semantic properties and relations of sentences can be determined. 1 See, for example, Green 1968, Lakoff 1971, Horn 1972, Morgan 1973, and Stalnaker 1974. 2 See also Karttunen 1974, MS. Thus the optimal semantic representation of a sentence in a grammar is whatever formal structure provides the simplest basis for predicting whether it is meaningful, ambiguous, analytic, synonymous with such-and-such other sentences, etc. (Katz 1972, ch. I). The specification of such semantic properties and relations was left open-ended, in order to accommodate further cases that might turn out to be pre-dictable from the semantic representations developed to predict meaningfulness, ambiguity, analyticity etc. Presupposition was incorporated into semantic theory on the hypothesis that it is one of these further cases (Katz 1965:597-8, 1966: 211-20). Introducing presupposition as one of the semantic properties and relations that must be predicted from an optimal semantic representation raises questions both about the interpretation of this notion-e.g. whether it should be interpreted logically, situationally, or in some other manner-and about the proper formal devices to use in constructing semantic representations. Both these questions have been discussed (Katz 1972:127-50). A contribution to these discussions was made by Langendoen & Savin (1971), who saw clearly that the formal devices required for constructing semantic representations from which presuppositions could be predicted would have to be part of the same machinery that provides a composi-tional analysis of the meaning of a sentence. Their empirical survey of the facts about how the presuppositions of the components of a complex sentence are related to the presupposition of the complex sentence as a whole led them to formulate the following
  • 14. hypothesis: (1) Each of the presuppositions of a component sentence in a complex sentence is a presupposition of the entire complex sentence. But counter-examples were soon pointed out. Morgan 1969 observes that 1 fails for sentences like: (2) If Jack has children, then all of Jack's children are bald. As Austin 1963 points out, sentence 3, the consequent clause of 2, by itself pre-supposes the existence of people who are children of Jack: (3) All of Jack's children are bald. Austin writes (p. 17): 'Not only [3] but equally "[Jack's] children are not bald", presupposes that [Jack] has children. To talk about those children, or to refer to them, presupposes that they exist.' Yet as Morgan observes, 2 presupposes nothing beyond the existence of Jack; so here the presupposition of a component sentence of a complex sentence is not a presupposition of the entire sentence. Further, as Katz 1972 and Karttunen 1973 observe, the presuppositions associated with an expression in a sentence are not, in general, associated with the complex sentences in which such a sentence appears as a verbal complement, because referentially opaque verbs remove such presupposi-tions. Thus, in a sentence like 4, there is no presupposition that Santa Claus exists: (4) Bob believes that Santa Claus came last night. As Karttunen (1973:173) puts it, one must distinguish between HOLES, PLUGS, and FILTERS-i.e., positions that let the presuppositions associated with the expressions appearing in them become presuppositions of the entire sentence, positions that do not let them, and positions that sometimes do and sometimes do not.3 To avoid such counter-examples, we might restate the Langendoen-Savin hypothesis as follows: (5) Each of the presuppositions of a component sentence in a complex sentence is a presupposition of the entire complex sentence just in case it is associated with an expression that appears in a hole. But 5 amounts to no more than a triviality, since holes have been characterized so far as positions that let the presupposition of the expression occupying them become presuppositions of the entire sentence. Thus the problem is twofold: an adequate semantic theory
  • 15. must also set up machinery to explicate formally these metaphorical notions of holes, plugs, and filters. That is, it must provide, in terms of such machinery, the projection mechanism that explains 5 and 6, and tells us when the filters are open and closed: (6) No presuppositions of a component sentence in a complex sentence are presuppositions of the entire complex sentence if they are associated with expressions that appear in a plug. This is done by Katz (1972, MS) as part of the formal theory of compositional semantic interpretation. In the next section, we briefly sketch how that machinery works. Katz (1972:167) proposes that the referential positions in propositions (senses of sentences) be formally represented by the notation of enclosure within heavy parentheses, to distinguish them from non-referential positions. Besides non-referential positions created by verbs of propositional attitude, such as believes in 4, the subject of exists is non-referential in our sense. The position occupied by poisonous mushrooms in 7 is non-referential, but its position in 8 is referential: (7) Poisonous mushrooms exist. (8) Poisonous mushrooms killed the elephant. Since 7 asserts that there are poisonous mushrooms, it cannot be represented as presupposing the existence of poisonous mushrooms. If it were so represented, it would be described as having its truth condition included in its condition of statementhood, and it would be mistakenly marked as analytic (Katz 1972: 172-8). The sense of 'referential' represented by a pair of heavy parentheses is different from the standard one in terms of substitutivity of identicals (Katz 1972:141)- since, supposing that toadstools is coreferential with poisonous mushrooms, we can substitute the former for the latter in 7 as well as 8, preserving truth. Yet, as we have just seen, we cannot regard the term position of 7 as referential in the sense of presuppositional reference. Thus the interpretation of heavy parentheses in a reading is simply this: a necessary condition on the (assertive) proposition repre-sented by the reading being a statement (i.e. either true or false) is that the reading
  • 16. Chapter 3 Data Analysis: The data has been taken from the short story Button, Button written by Richard Mathson. And the methodology which has been applied for this data analysis is quantitative. Through data analysis diffferrent kinds of presupposition will be hilighted. Sentence Presupposition Kind of Presupposition "I'm Mr. Steward." Mr.Steward exixts Existential She was sure now it was a sales pitch. She was not suie before lexical "May I come in?" asked Mr. Steward. He was not in lexical " Don't you want to know what it is?" She does not know about it Structural I don't think so." she replied. She thinks factive "It could prove very valuable," It is valuable lexical
  • 17. he told her. . . "What are you trying to sell?" she asked. He is selling something Structural "I'm not selling anything," he answered. He is doing something else instead of selling lexical "Oh, the __________" Arthur pointed toward the living room Living room exixts exixtenttial . "What is that gadget, anyway?" Gadget exixts Exixtential "If you are selling something _______" Arthur said. Mr. Steward shook his head. "I'm not" He is not selling anything Counterfactual . He reached into an inside coat pocket and withdrew a small sealed envelope Coat pocket and envelope exixt exixtential
  • 18. "The bell is connected to our office Bell exixts exixtential "If you push the button," Mr. Steward told him, "somewhere in the world someone you don't know will die He does not push the button before counterfactural In return for which you will receive a payment of $50,000." Dollar exixts exixtential Norma stared at the small man. He was smiling. Small man exixts Exixtentail "What are you talking about?" Arthur asked him. He is talking Structural "But I've just explained," he said He has explained earlier lexical "Is this a practical joke?" asked Arthur. This is a joke structural "Not at all. The offer is completely genuine." It is an offere Lexical
  • 19. "Who do you represent?" demanded Norma He represents structural "However, I assure you, the organization is of international scope." Organization exixts Exixtenntial "And take your button unit with you." Button exixts exixtential
  • 20. Chapter 4 Conclusion: At the end it can be concluded that presupposition play an important role between speaker and adressee commun A presupposition must be equally known or understood by the presenter and receiver for the statement to be measured suitable in context. It will generally remain a necessary assumption whether the utterance is placed in the form of an assertion, denial, or question, and can be associated with a specific lexical item or grammatical feature (presupposition trigger) in the utterance. It is also noticed that negation does not change presupposition.
  • 21. Bibliography FREGE,G . 1892. Uber Sinn und Bedeutung. Zeitschriftf ur Philosophie und Philoso-phische Kritik 100.25-50. [In Translations from the philosophical writings of Gottlob Frege, ed. by P. T. Geach & M. Black, 68-74. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1952.] KATZ, J. J. 1965. The relevance of linguistics to philosophy. Journal of Philosophy 62.590-601. --. 1966. The philosophy of language. New York: Harper & Row. --. 1972. Semantic theory. SEARLE, J. R. 1969. Speech acts. Cambridge: University Press. STALNAKER, R. 1974. Pragmatic presuppositions. Semantics and philosophy, ed. by M. K. Munitz and P. K. Unger, 197-214. New York: NYU Press HORN, L. 1972. On the semantic properties of logical operators in English. UCLA dissertation KARTTUNEN, L. 1973. Presuppositionso f compound sentences. Linguistic Inquiry 4. 169-93. HARNISH, M. MS.L ogicalf orm and implicature.T o appeari n Bever,K atz & Langendoen. FREGE,G . 1892. Uber Sinn und Bedeutung. Zeitschriftf ur Philosophie und Philoso-phische Kritik 100.25-50. [In Translations from the philosophical writings of Gottlob Frege, ed. by P. T. Geach & M. Black, 68-74. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1952.]