SlideShare ist ein Scribd-Unternehmen logo
1 von 27
Democracy	
  and	
  Expertise:	
  Lessons	
  from	
  the	
  Debate	
  over	
  
Global	
  Warming	
  
	
  
                   Whereas	
  the	
  role	
  of	
  the	
  technical	
  expert	
  in	
  democratic	
  decision-­‐making	
  
was	
  formerly	
  seen	
  to	
  be	
  the	
  provision	
  of	
  disinterested	
  advice	
  for	
  use	
  in	
  policy	
  
formulation,	
  their	
  capacity	
  in	
  this	
  regard	
  is	
  increasingly	
  under	
  question.	
  	
  Many	
  
argue	
  that	
  expertise	
  is	
  in	
  fact	
  vulnerable	
  to	
  politicization	
  for	
  self-­‐serving	
  ends,	
  
due	
  in	
  part	
  to	
  the	
  unachievable	
  nature	
  of	
  objectivity,	
  and	
  hence	
  not	
  as	
  infallible	
  
as	
  was	
  once	
  thought.	
  	
  Science	
  is	
  now	
  often	
  viewed	
  as	
  ‘politics	
  by	
  other	
  means’.1	
  	
  
As	
  a	
  result	
  technical	
  knowledge	
  is	
  increasingly	
  being	
  contested	
  in	
  the	
  public	
  
sphere,	
  by	
  expert	
  and	
  lay	
  groups	
  alike.2	
  	
  This	
  paper	
  will	
  address	
  the	
  extent	
  to	
  
which	
  this	
  contestation	
  either	
  enhances	
  or	
  hinders	
  democratic	
  governance.	
  
	
  
                   In	
  order	
  to	
  address	
  this	
  issue	
  I	
  will	
  be	
  investigating	
  the	
  debate	
  
surrounding	
  anthropogenic	
  climate	
  change.	
  	
  Despite	
  the	
  apparent	
  consensus	
  on	
  
its	
  existence	
  and	
  human	
  causes,	
  this	
  issue,	
  and	
  the	
  adequacy	
  of	
  scientific	
  
expertise	
  surrounding	
  it,	
  has	
  been	
  hotly	
  contested	
  in	
  recent	
  years.3	
  	
  I	
  will	
  seek	
  to	
  
analyse	
  the	
  nature	
  of	
  this	
  contestation,	
  its	
  implications	
  for	
  the	
  formulation	
  of	
  
climate	
  change	
  policy,	
  and	
  for	
  the	
  conflict	
  between	
  expertise	
  and	
  democracy.	
  	
  
From	
  this	
  discussion,	
  I	
  will	
  suggest	
  ways	
  in	
  which	
  this	
  conflict	
  can	
  be	
  nullified.	
  	
  
Initially	
  though,	
  I	
  shall	
  begin	
  with	
  an	
  investigation	
  of	
  expertise	
  and	
  its	
  place	
  in	
  
democracy.	
  
	
  
Expertise	
  and	
  Democracy	
  
	
  
                   The	
  use	
  of	
  scientific	
  expertise	
  in	
  democratic	
  decision-­‐making	
  has,	
  
throughout	
  the	
  modern	
  period,	
  been	
  governed	
  by	
  the	
  ideal	
  of	
  neutrality.	
  	
  Under	
  
this	
  traditional	
  (Western)	
  model,	
  scientific	
  experts	
  are	
  presumed	
  detached	
  from	
  
	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  
1	
  Bruno	
  Latour,	
  quoted	
  in	
  Mark	
  B.	
  Brown,	
  Science	
  in	
  Democracy:	
  Expertise,	
  

Institutions,	
  and	
  Representation,	
  London,	
  MIT	
  Press,	
  2009,	
  p.	
  185.	
  
2	
  Ibid,	
  pp.	
  2-­‐3.	
  
3	
  Jacquelin	
  Burgess,	
  et	
  al.,	
  ‘Global	
  Warming	
  in	
  the	
  Public	
  Sphere,’	
  Philosophical	
  

Transactions:	
  Mathematical,	
  Physical	
  and	
  Engineering	
  Sciences,	
  Vol.	
  365,	
  No.	
  1860,	
  
2007,	
  2751.	
  


	
                                                                                                                                                                                                                       1	
  
the	
  political,	
  social	
  and	
  cultural	
  processes	
  underlying	
  the	
  societies	
  which	
  they	
  
inhabit	
  such	
  that	
  they	
  may	
  provide	
  objective	
  and	
  value	
  neutral	
  advice	
  to	
  political	
  
representatives.	
  	
  Consequently,	
  while	
  part	
  of	
  the	
  political	
  process,	
  experts	
  and	
  
expert	
  advice	
  are	
  deemed	
  apolitical.4	
  	
  The	
  authority	
  of	
  their	
  advice,	
  and	
  hence	
  
their	
  legitimacy	
  within	
  the	
  democratic	
  system,	
  is	
  premised	
  on	
  the	
  supposed	
  
attainability	
  of	
  scientific	
  certainty	
  through	
  the	
  use	
  of	
  the	
  scientific	
  method.5	
  	
  This	
  
image	
  of	
  the	
  expert	
  as	
  the	
  disinterested	
  and	
  authoritative	
  arbiter	
  has,	
  however,	
  
been	
  challenged	
  since	
  the	
  mid	
  twentieth-­‐century	
  by	
  the	
  growing	
  awareness	
  of	
  
limits	
  to	
  expert	
  knowledge,	
  and	
  the	
  perception	
  that	
  bias	
  and	
  special	
  interests	
  are	
  
influencing	
  the	
  conduct	
  of	
  scientific	
  knowledge	
  generation.6	
  	
  The	
  very	
  public	
  
nature	
  of	
  contestation	
  and	
  controversy	
  in	
  scientific	
  discourse,	
  such	
  as	
  that	
  
witnessed	
  during	
  the	
  global	
  warming	
  debate	
  is,	
  at	
  least	
  in	
  part,	
  responsible	
  for	
  
this	
  reformulation.	
  	
  For	
  rather	
  than	
  expertise	
  ‘speaking	
  truth	
  to	
  power’,	
  scientific	
  
experts	
  are	
  often	
  viewed	
  as	
  an	
  interest	
  group	
  like	
  any	
  other.7	
  
	
  
                   It	
  is	
  indeed	
  the	
  case	
  that	
  research,	
  from	
  which	
  expert	
  knowledge	
  and	
  
advice	
  is	
  generated,	
  is	
  to	
  a	
  large	
  degree	
  directed	
  by	
  government	
  and	
  commercial	
  
funding.	
  	
  Often	
  dependent	
  upon	
  external	
  sources	
  for	
  funding	
  streams,	
  expert	
  
bodies	
  are	
  rarely	
  in	
  total	
  control	
  of	
  their	
  research	
  programs.8	
  	
  For	
  example,	
  the	
  
use	
  by	
  Western	
  governments	
  of	
  mechanisms	
  such	
  as	
  tax	
  credits	
  and	
  favourable	
  

	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  
4	
  Brown,	
  Science	
  in	
  Democracy,	
  pp.	
  9-­‐10.	
  
5	
  I	
  take	
  ‘scientific	
  method’	
  to	
  indicate	
  inquiry	
  based	
  upon	
  the	
  gathering	
  of	
  

empirical	
  data	
  and	
  testing	
  of	
  hypotheses,	
  both	
  through	
  the	
  use	
  of	
  reason	
  and	
  
instrumental	
  rationality.	
  	
  Raphael	
  Sassower,	
  Knowledge	
  without	
  Expertise:	
  On	
  the	
  
Status	
  of	
  Scientists,	
  Albany,	
  State	
  University	
  of	
  New	
  York	
  Press,	
  1993,	
  p.	
  69.	
  
6	
  Brian	
  Martin	
  and	
  Eveleen	
  Richards,	
  ‘Scientific	
  Knowledge,	
  Controversy,	
  and	
  

Public	
  Decision	
  Making,’	
  in	
  Sheila	
  Jasanoff	
  et	
  al.	
  (eds.),	
  Handbook	
  of	
  Science	
  and	
  
Technology	
  Studies,	
  Thousand	
  Oaks,	
  SAGE	
  Publications,	
  1995,	
  pp.	
  506-­‐507.	
  
7	
  Clark	
  A.	
  Miller,	
  ‘Challenges	
  in	
  the	
  Application	
  of	
  Science	
  to	
  Global	
  Affairs:	
  

Contingency,	
  Trust,	
  and	
  Moral	
  Order,’	
  in	
  Paul	
  N.	
  Edwards	
  and	
  Clark	
  A.	
  Miller	
  
(eds.),	
  Changing	
  the	
  Atmosphere:	
  Expert	
  Knowledge	
  and	
  Environmental	
  
Governance,	
  Cambridge,	
  MIT	
  Press,	
  2001,	
  p.	
  278.	
  	
  For	
  an	
  example	
  of	
  this	
  line	
  of	
  
argument	
  see	
  S.	
  A.	
  Boehmer-­‐Christiansen,	
  ‘Britain	
  and	
  the	
  International	
  Panel	
  on	
  
Climate	
  Change:	
  The	
  Impacts	
  of	
  Scientific	
  Advice	
  on	
  Global	
  Warming	
  Part	
  1:	
  
Integrated	
  Policy	
  Analysis	
  and	
  the	
  Global	
  Dimension’,	
  Environmental	
  Politics,	
  Vol.	
  
4,	
  No.	
  1,	
  1995,	
  pp.	
  15-­‐16.	
  
8	
  Roy	
  Macleod,	
  ‘Science	
  and	
  Democracy:	
  Historical	
  Reflections	
  on	
  Present	
  

Discontents,’	
  Minerva,	
  Vol.	
  35,	
  1997,	
  p.	
  374.	
  


	
                                                                                                                                                                                                                         2	
  
patent	
  policies,	
  coupled	
  with	
  commercial	
  sector	
  funding	
  of	
  industrial	
  labs,	
  has	
  
helped	
  guide	
  scientific	
  research	
  towards	
  profit-­‐orientated	
  applications.9	
  	
  Experts,	
  
moreover,	
  are	
  now	
  often	
  in	
  the	
  employ	
  of	
  governments,	
  advocacy	
  groups,	
  NGOs,	
  
and	
  commercial	
  entities,	
  which	
  seek	
  to	
  use	
  the	
  authority	
  of	
  expertise	
  to	
  garner	
  
support	
  for	
  their	
  particular	
  policy	
  goals.10	
  	
  Such	
  activity	
  undermines	
  the	
  ‘truth	
  to	
  
power’	
  model,	
  and	
  its	
  assumption	
  of	
  a	
  linear	
  relationship	
  between	
  neutral	
  
scientific	
  knowledge	
  and	
  its	
  subsequent	
  use	
  in	
  policy	
  formulation,	
  by	
  appearing	
  
to	
  align	
  expertise	
  with	
  particular	
  interest	
  groups.11	
  	
  	
  
	
  
                   This	
  realisation	
  of	
  the	
  political	
  usage	
  of	
  scientific	
  expertise	
  has	
  been	
  
accompanied	
  by	
  an	
  appreciation	
  of	
  the	
  political	
  nature	
  of	
  scientific	
  knowledge	
  
itself.	
  	
  Instead	
  of	
  such	
  knowledge	
  being	
  seen	
  as	
  an	
  objective	
  representation	
  of	
  
nature,	
  or	
  verifiable	
  truth,	
  it	
  is	
  now	
  widely	
  understood	
  to	
  involve	
  the	
  negotiated	
  
outcome	
  of	
  interactions	
  between	
  experts	
  and	
  the	
  outside	
  world.12	
  	
  These	
  
interactions	
  are	
  necessarily	
  affected	
  by	
  social,	
  cultural,	
  and	
  political	
  concerns,	
  
which	
  in	
  turn	
  influence	
  the	
  content	
  of	
  those	
  engagements.13	
  	
  Manifested	
  in	
  the	
  
laying	
  down	
  of	
  assumptions,	
  and	
  the	
  interpretation	
  of	
  uncertainties,	
  these	
  
interactions	
  can	
  result	
  in	
  very	
  different	
  representations	
  of	
  nature,	
  in	
  what	
  is	
  
ultimately	
  a	
  human	
  and	
  constrained	
  exercise.14	
  	
  Nonetheless,	
  the	
  authority	
  
granted	
  to	
  scientific	
  expertise	
  in	
  contemporary	
  democratic	
  decision-­‐making	
  
continues	
  to	
  be	
  grounded	
  in	
  ideals	
  of	
  ethical	
  and	
  value	
  neutrality.15	
  	
  Scientists	
  
are	
  thus	
  expected	
  to	
  be	
  infallible,	
  removed	
  from	
  the	
  sphere	
  of	
  moral	
  or	
  political	
  

	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  
9	
  Brown,	
  Science	
  in	
  Democracy,	
  pp.	
  10-­‐11.	
  
10	
  Alan	
  Irwin,	
  Citizen	
  Science:	
  A	
  Study	
  of	
  People,	
  Expertise,	
  and	
  Sustainable	
  

Development,	
  London,	
  Routledge,	
  1995,	
  p.	
  9.	
  
11	
  Esther	
  Turnhout,	
  ‘Heads	
  in	
  the	
  Clouds:	
  Knowledge	
  Democracy	
  as	
  a	
  Utopian	
  

Dream,’	
  in	
  Roeland	
  J.	
  in	
  ‘t	
  Veld	
  (ed.)	
  Knowledge	
  Democracy:	
  Consequences	
  for	
  
Science,	
  Politics,	
  and	
  Media,	
  Heidelberg,	
  Springer,	
  2010,	
  pp.	
  25-­‐26.	
  
12	
  Susan	
  E.	
  Cozzens	
  and	
  Edward	
  J.	
  Woodhouse,	
  ‘Science,	
  Government,	
  and	
  the	
  

Politics	
  of	
  Knowledge,’	
  in	
  Sheila	
  Jasanoff	
  et	
  al.	
  (eds.),	
  Handbook	
  of	
  Science	
  and	
  
Technology	
  Studies,	
  Thousand	
  Oaks,	
  SAGE	
  Publications,	
  1995,	
  pp.	
  533-­‐534.	
  
13	
  This	
  process	
  is	
  similar	
  in	
  operation	
  to	
  democratic	
  representation,	
  which	
  rather	
  

than	
  being	
  a	
  mirror	
  for	
  the	
  pre-­‐existing	
  reality	
  of	
  popular	
  will,	
  is	
  a	
  negotiated	
  
outcome	
  conducted	
  by	
  correspondence.	
  	
  Brown,	
  Science	
  in	
  Democracy,	
  p.	
  5-­‐8.	
  
14	
  Irwin,	
  Citizen	
  Science,	
  p.	
  49.	
  Brown	
  5-­‐7	
  
15	
  Frank	
  Fischer,	
  Technocracy	
  and	
  the	
  Politics	
  of	
  Expertise,	
  Newbury	
  Park,	
  SAGE	
  

Publications,	
  1990,	
  p.	
  146.	
  


	
                                                                                                                                                                                                                         3	
  
judgement.16	
  	
  This	
  is	
  even	
  the	
  case	
  when	
  the	
  area	
  under	
  investigation	
  is	
  one	
  of	
  
vital	
  human	
  interest,	
  as	
  it	
  is	
  with	
  the	
  threat	
  of	
  global	
  warming.	
  	
  Unwilling	
  to	
  
‘confront	
  the	
  politics	
  of	
  knowledge’,	
  the	
  ideal	
  of	
  value	
  neutral	
  scientific	
  expertise	
  
stubbornly	
  persists	
  in	
  Western	
  democracies.17	
  
	
  
                   This	
  is	
  perhaps	
  not	
  surprising,	
  given	
  that	
  the	
  ideal	
  itself	
  is	
  deeply	
  
grounded	
  in	
  the	
  modernist	
  project.	
  	
  From	
  the	
  sixteenth	
  to	
  the	
  nineteenth	
  
centuries,	
  our	
  social	
  and	
  political	
  processes	
  were	
  moulded	
  by	
  the	
  
institutionalization	
  of	
  what	
  Max	
  Weber	
  identified	
  as	
  the	
  application	
  of	
  reason	
  
and	
  instrumental	
  rationality	
  to	
  everyday	
  society	
  by	
  way	
  of	
  the	
  scientific	
  method.	
  	
  
The	
  very	
  functioning	
  of	
  democratic	
  forms	
  of	
  governance	
  was	
  justified	
  upon	
  the	
  
use	
  of	
  this	
  ‘higher’	
  form	
  of	
  knowledge.18	
  	
  Yet	
  as	
  science	
  shifted	
  out	
  of	
  the	
  private	
  
sphere	
  and	
  into	
  the	
  public	
  and	
  institutional	
  during	
  the	
  nineteenth-­‐century,	
  the	
  
professionalization	
  and	
  standardization	
  of	
  scientific	
  practice	
  led	
  to	
  a	
  necessary	
  
restriction	
  of	
  access	
  to	
  knowledge	
  generation.	
  	
  The	
  ‘scientist’	
  progressively	
  
moved	
  away	
  from	
  the	
  Enlightenment	
  ideal	
  of	
  the	
  ‘cultivated	
  scholar’,	
  and	
  
towards	
  the	
  emerging	
  specialized	
  expert.19	
  	
  With	
  forms	
  of	
  knowing	
  grounded	
  in	
  
scientific	
  method	
  already	
  privileged	
  over	
  all	
  other	
  forms,	
  this	
  process	
  created	
  an	
  
implicit	
  elitism	
  within	
  supposedly	
  democratic	
  systems.20	
  	
  As	
  access	
  to	
  expertise	
  
receded	
  further	
  with	
  the	
  emergence	
  of	
  formalized	
  communication	
  systems	
  and	
  
the	
  use	
  of	
  esoteric	
  language,	
  claims	
  to	
  objectivity	
  and	
  neutrality	
  allowed	
  experts	
  
a	
  certain	
  level	
  of	
  cultural	
  and	
  social	
  authority.21	
  	
  This	
  process	
  above	
  all	
  ran	
  

	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  
16	
  Jean-­‐Jacques	
  Salomon,	
  ‘Science,	
  Technology	
  and	
  Democracy,’	
  Minerva,	
  Vol.	
  38,	
  

2000,	
  p.	
  37.	
  
17	
  Robert	
  Proctor,	
  Value-­‐free	
  Science?:	
  Purity	
  and	
  Power	
  in	
  Modern	
  Knowledge,	
  

Cambridge,	
  Harvard	
  University	
  Press,	
  1991,	
  p.	
  267.	
  
18	
  Fischer,	
  Technocracy	
  and	
  the	
  Politics	
  of	
  Expertise,	
  pp.	
  61-­‐63.	
  
19	
  Proctor,	
  Value-­‐free	
  Science?,	
  p.	
  264.	
  
20	
  Indeed,	
  the	
  outward	
  commitment	
  to	
  universal	
  education	
  did	
  little	
  to	
  the	
  

growth	
  of	
  elitism,	
  as	
  increased	
  specialization	
  dimmed	
  the	
  utopian	
  dream	
  of	
  a	
  
fully	
  informed	
  polity.	
  	
  Macleod,	
  ‘Science	
  and	
  Democracy’,	
  pp.	
  372-­‐374.	
  	
  	
  
21	
  Of	
  course,	
  boundaries	
  of	
  this	
  kind	
  are	
  constructed	
  partly	
  to	
  secure	
  scientific	
  

knowledge	
  against	
  degradation	
  by	
  inferior	
  forms,	
  but	
  also	
  to	
  secure	
  authority	
  in	
  
the	
  wider	
  social	
  realm,	
  legitimating	
  claims	
  to	
  it	
  within	
  the	
  system.	
  	
  Julia	
  Evetts,	
  
‘Professionalization,	
  Scientific	
  Expertise,	
  and	
  Elitism:	
  A	
  Sociological	
  Perspective,’	
  
in	
  Neil	
  Charness	
  et	
  al.	
  (eds.),	
  The	
  Cambridge	
  Handbook	
  of	
  Expertise	
  and	
  Expert	
  
Performance,	
  Cambridge,	
  Cambridge	
  University	
  Press,	
  2006,	
  p.	
  115.	
  


	
                                                                                                                                                                                                                          4	
  
counter	
  to	
  the	
  democratic	
  ideals	
  of	
  inclusion	
  and	
  equal	
  rights,	
  narrowing	
  the	
  
scope	
  for	
  public	
  participation,	
  and	
  undermining	
  the	
  democratic	
  governance	
  
scientific	
  knowledge	
  was	
  presumed	
  to	
  maintain.	
  
	
  
                   Despite	
  this	
  apparent	
  conflict	
  between	
  scientific	
  expertise	
  and	
  democracy,	
  
the	
  former’s	
  institutionalization	
  within	
  decision-­‐making	
  grew	
  exponentially	
  
during	
  the	
  twentieth-­‐century.	
  	
  Partly	
  this	
  can	
  be	
  seen	
  as	
  a	
  reaction	
  to	
  the	
  
ostensible	
  success	
  of	
  applied	
  science	
  during	
  the	
  destruction	
  of	
  World	
  War	
  I	
  and	
  
II,	
  which	
  seemed	
  to	
  show	
  that	
  democracy	
  without	
  science	
  is	
  both	
  ‘inefficient	
  and	
  
vulnerable’	
  in	
  the	
  face	
  of	
  encroachment	
  by	
  aggressive	
  authoritarianism.22	
  	
  Of	
  no	
  
less	
  importance,	
  however,	
  was	
  the	
  desire	
  to	
  usurp	
  the	
  influence	
  of	
  patronage	
  
politics;	
  through	
  the	
  use	
  of	
  disinterested	
  policies	
  based	
  upon	
  scientific	
  method	
  
and	
  rationality	
  such	
  political	
  expediency	
  would	
  be	
  undermined.	
  	
  The	
  emergence	
  
of	
  ‘think	
  tanks’	
  and	
  their	
  ever-­‐increasing	
  influence	
  within	
  policy	
  formulation	
  is	
  
indicative	
  of	
  this	
  trend	
  towards	
  the	
  ‘scientization’	
  of	
  politics.23	
  	
  
	
  
                   Nico	
  Stehr	
  argues	
  that	
  the	
  growth	
  of	
  expert	
  influence	
  in	
  political	
  systems,	
  
and	
  the	
  ‘scientization’	
  of	
  politics,	
  can	
  be	
  seen	
  as	
  part	
  of	
  the	
  emergence	
  of	
  the	
  
‘knowledge	
  society’.	
  	
  Manifested	
  in	
  the	
  penetration	
  of	
  scientific	
  and	
  technical	
  
understanding	
  into	
  the	
  core	
  of	
  the	
  economy,	
  social	
  action,	
  and	
  politics	
  itself,	
  this	
  
‘post-­‐industrial	
  society’	
  ascribes	
  value	
  and	
  power	
  to	
  the	
  guardianship	
  of	
  
knowledge.24	
  	
  As	
  a	
  result	
  of	
  this	
  shift	
  from	
  material	
  to	
  information	
  value,	
  the	
  old	
  
interest-­‐based	
  politics	
  is	
  replaced	
  by	
  governance	
  systems	
  directed	
  towards	
  the	
  
	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  
22	
  Macleod,	
  ‘Science	
  and	
  Democracy’,	
  pp.	
  375-­‐377.	
  
23	
  Arguably	
  though,	
  policy	
  choice	
  is	
  no	
  clearer	
  than	
  before,	
  largely	
  due	
  to	
  the	
  

plethora	
  of	
  (often	
  contradictory)	
  studies	
  advocating	
  every	
  position	
  on	
  every	
  
conceivable	
  issue,	
  all	
  backed	
  by	
  scientific	
  expertise.	
  	
  Andrew	
  M.	
  Rich,	
  Think	
  
Tanks,	
  Public	
  Policy,	
  and	
  the	
  Politics	
  of	
  Expertise,	
  Cambridge,	
  Cambridge	
  
University	
  Press,	
  2004,	
  pp.	
  2-­‐4.	
  	
  The	
  public,	
  moreover,	
  has	
  rightly	
  come	
  to	
  view	
  
think	
  tanks	
  as	
  bastions	
  of	
  ideology	
  rather	
  than	
  disinterested	
  fact,	
  a	
  belief	
  that	
  
seriously	
  undermines	
  trust	
  in	
  their	
  ‘expert’	
  advice	
  amongst	
  lay	
  audiences.	
  	
  Ibid,	
  
pp.	
  25-­‐6.	
  
24	
  Nico	
  Stehr,	
  Knowledge	
  Societies,	
  London,	
  SAGE	
  Publications,	
  1994,	
  pp.	
  1-­‐15.	
  	
  

This	
  is	
  not	
  to	
  say,	
  however,	
  that	
  experts	
  can	
  be	
  thought	
  of	
  as	
  a	
  social	
  class,	
  being	
  
merely	
  members	
  of	
  loose	
  associations.	
  	
  Indeed,	
  while	
  they	
  have	
  power	
  in	
  the	
  
elite	
  institutions	
  that	
  generate	
  knowledge,	
  they	
  have	
  only	
  influence	
  outside	
  of	
  
them.	
  	
  Ibid,	
  pp.	
  167-­‐168.	
  


	
                                                                                                                                                                                                                            5	
  
identification	
  of	
  social	
  policy	
  ‘problems’,	
  with	
  feasibility	
  studies	
  and	
  apolitical	
  
decision-­‐making	
  determining	
  the	
  scope	
  of	
  policy	
  choice.	
  	
  Little	
  room	
  is	
  left	
  for	
  
public	
  opinion	
  and	
  citizen	
  participation,	
  both	
  of	
  which	
  are	
  viewed	
  as	
  inferior,	
  
even	
  irrational,	
  forms	
  of	
  policy	
  input.25	
  	
  
	
  
                    There	
  has	
  certainly	
  been	
  an	
  identifiable	
  shift	
  towards	
  ‘scientific’	
  decision-­‐
making	
  in	
  Western	
  democracies	
  over	
  the	
  course	
  of	
  the	
  last	
  century.	
  	
  Responding	
  
to	
  concerns	
  that	
  policymaking	
  is	
  being	
  negatively	
  affected	
  by	
  the	
  vagaries	
  of	
  an	
  
irrational	
  political	
  process,	
  political	
  and	
  administrative	
  leaders	
  have	
  
progressively	
  institutionalized	
  technocracies	
  in	
  supposedly	
  democratic	
  
countries.26	
  	
  	
  Following	
  Frank	
  Fisher,	
  this	
  system	
  of	
  governance	
  can	
  be	
  defined	
  
as	
  one	
  in	
  which	
  ‘technically	
  trained	
  experts	
  rule	
  by	
  virtue	
  of	
  their	
  specialized	
  
knowledge	
  and	
  position	
  in	
  dominant	
  political	
  and	
  economic	
  institutions’.27	
  	
  As	
  
Jürgen	
  Habermas	
  has	
  argued	
  elsewhere,	
  this	
  reduction	
  of	
  political	
  power	
  into	
  
rational	
  administration	
  can	
  occur	
  only	
  at	
  the	
  expense	
  of	
  democracy	
  itself.28	
  	
  For	
  
not	
  only	
  are	
  the	
  public	
  excluded	
  from	
  decision-­‐making,	
  but	
  the	
  traditional	
  role	
  of	
  
their	
  political	
  representatives	
  in	
  democratic	
  systems	
  is	
  given	
  over	
  to	
  
‘administratively	
  based	
  cadres	
  of	
  policy	
  experts’,	
  who	
  determine	
  the	
  direction	
  of	
  
economic	
  and	
  social	
  policy.29	
  	
  
	
  
                    At	
  the	
  same	
  time	
  we	
  have	
  become	
  reliant	
  on	
  scientific	
  expertise.	
  	
  For	
  
despite	
  growing	
  evidence	
  of	
  lay	
  disenchantment	
  with	
  the	
  functioning	
  of	
  
expertise	
  in	
  democratic	
  governance,	
  society	
  must	
  still	
  defer	
  to	
  expert	
  authority	
  
on	
  issues	
  ranging	
  from	
  the	
  mundane	
  to	
  the	
  infinitely	
  complex.30	
  	
  As	
  Dietrich	
  
Rueschemeyer	
  argues	
  in	
  relation	
  to	
  experts:	
  
	
  



	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  
25	
  Fischer,	
  Technocracy	
  and	
  the	
  Politics	
  of	
  Expertise,	
  pp.	
  15-­‐16.	
  
26	
  Ibid,	
  p.	
  21.	
  
27	
  Ibid,	
  p.	
  17.	
  
28	
  Jürgen	
  Habermas,	
  Toward	
  a	
  Rational	
  Society:	
  Student	
  Protest,	
  Science,	
  and	
  

Politics,	
  London,	
  Heinemann	
  Educational,	
  1971,	
  p.	
  68.	
  
29	
  Fischer,	
  Technocracy	
  and	
  the	
  Politics	
  of	
  Expertise,	
  pp.	
  18-­‐19.	
  
30	
  Stehr,	
  Knowledge	
  Societies,	
  pp.	
  163-­‐165.	
  




	
                                                                                                                                                                                                                                 6	
  
[T]hey	
  define	
  the	
  situation	
  for	
  the	
  untutored,	
  they	
  suggest	
  priorities,	
  they	
  
                    shape	
  people’s	
  outlook	
  on	
  their	
  life	
  and	
  world,	
  and	
  they	
  establish	
  
                    standards	
  of	
  judgement	
  in	
  the	
  different	
  areas	
  of	
  expertise.31	
  
	
  
Simply	
  put,	
  experts	
  are	
  those	
  adjudged	
  the	
  most	
  competent	
  in	
  answering	
  
questions	
  related	
  to	
  their	
  specific	
  area	
  of	
  expertise.	
  	
  Non-­‐experts,	
  or	
  the	
  lay	
  
public,	
  are	
  at	
  best	
  unqualified	
  and	
  external	
  reviewers	
  ensuring	
  that	
  only	
  other	
  
experts	
  in	
  their	
  field	
  can	
  truly	
  judge	
  the	
  adequacy	
  of	
  advice,	
  thereby	
  insulating	
  
them	
  from	
  radical	
  external	
  criticism	
  of	
  their	
  results.32	
  	
  Knowledge	
  becomes	
  the	
  
domain	
  of	
  the	
  elite,	
  and	
  one	
  in	
  which	
  the	
  general	
  public	
  is	
  excluded.	
  	
  This	
  
presents	
  a	
  further	
  problem	
  for	
  democracy,	
  when	
  defined	
  as	
  ‘government	
  by	
  
discussion’,	
  because	
  the	
  discussion	
  itself	
  is	
  unintelligible	
  and	
  out	
  of	
  reach	
  for	
  the	
  
majority.33	
  
	
  
                    Here	
  we	
  can	
  find	
  Robert	
  Dahl’s	
  conception	
  of	
  the	
  democratic	
  ideal	
  useful	
  
in	
  better	
  understanding	
  the	
  significance	
  of	
  this	
  problem.	
  	
  Dahl	
  defines	
  the	
  ideal	
  
democracy	
  as	
  one	
  that	
  ensures	
  the	
  equal	
  empowerment	
  of	
  all,	
  meaning	
  that	
  even	
  
if	
  not	
  directly	
  participating	
  in	
  all	
  decisions,	
  no	
  citizen	
  should	
  be	
  specifically	
  
excluded	
  from	
  doing	
  so.	
  	
  As	
  the	
  above	
  discussion	
  indicates,	
  however,	
  modern	
  
democracies	
  are	
  far	
  removed	
  from	
  this	
  ideal,	
  as	
  the	
  elite	
  controls	
  access	
  to	
  forms	
  
of	
  knowledge	
  used	
  in	
  decision-­‐making.	
  	
  Recognising	
  this,	
  Dahl	
  suggests	
  a	
  
continuum	
  of	
  polyarchy34	
  based	
  on	
  levels	
  of	
  democratic	
  involvement	
  and	
  
popular	
  sovereignty.	
  	
  At	
  the	
  lower	
  end	
  of	
  this	
  continuum	
  are	
  those	
  countries	
  in	
  
which	
  the	
  minimum	
  of	
  free	
  and	
  fair	
  elections	
  is	
  achieved,	
  but	
  where	
  the	
  elite	
  
allows	
  for	
  little	
  public	
  involvement.	
  	
  At	
  the	
  upper	
  end	
  is	
  a	
  governance	
  structure	
  
within	
  which	
  each	
  citizen	
  is	
  equally	
  involved	
  in	
  the	
  defining	
  of	
  policy	
  agendas,	
  
and	
  where	
  policy	
  is	
  created	
  transparently,	
  originates	
  from	
  numerous	
  sources,	
  
and	
  public	
  deliberation	
  in	
  decision-­‐making	
  is	
  promoted.	
  	
  Standing	
  between	
  the	
  
lower	
  and	
  upper	
  levels	
  on	
  this	
  continuum	
  is	
  the	
  control	
  of	
  information	
  by	
  policy	
  
	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  
31	
  Quoted	
  in	
  ibid,	
  p.	
  166.	
  
32	
  Sassower,	
  Knowledge	
  without	
  Expertise,	
  pp.	
  64-­‐66.	
  
33	
  Stephen	
  P.	
  Turner,	
  Liberal	
  Democracy	
  3.0:	
  Civil	
  Society	
  in	
  an	
  Age	
  of	
  Experts,	
  

London,	
  SAGE	
  Publications,	
  2003,	
  pp.	
  5-­‐6.	
  
34	
  Meaning	
  a	
  governance	
  system	
  in	
  which	
  power	
  is	
  vested	
  in	
  many	
  actors.	
  




	
                                                                                                                                                                                                                                 7	
  
elites.35	
  	
  Thus	
  Dahl	
  would	
  argue	
  that	
  expertise,	
  as	
  an	
  elite	
  bastion	
  of	
  knowledge,	
  
lowers	
  the	
  level	
  of	
  democracy	
  in	
  those	
  countries	
  in	
  which	
  it	
  forms	
  the	
  basis	
  of	
  
decision-­‐making.	
  
	
  
The	
  Risk	
  Society	
  
	
  
                   At	
  the	
  same	
  time	
  as	
  expertise	
  has	
  come	
  to	
  undermine	
  the	
  legitimate	
  
functioning	
  of	
  democratic	
  governance,	
  a	
  crisis	
  in	
  confidence	
  has	
  beset	
  the	
  very	
  
authority	
  of	
  that	
  expertise.	
  	
  For	
  Ülrich	
  Beck,	
  the	
  sources	
  of	
  this	
  crisis	
  are	
  related	
  
to	
  what	
  he	
  terms	
  the	
  ‘risk	
  society’.	
  	
  Whereas	
  during	
  modernity,	
  the	
  belief	
  in	
  
progress,	
  truth,	
  and	
  the	
  purity	
  of	
  the	
  scientific	
  method	
  dominated,	
  our	
  ‘post-­‐
industrial’	
  society	
  is	
  beset	
  by	
  doubt	
  and	
  anxieties	
  related	
  to	
  environmental	
  
threats.	
  	
  As	
  a	
  result,	
  uncertainty	
  and	
  risk	
  have	
  become	
  central	
  to	
  politics,	
  not	
  
necessarily	
  due	
  to	
  the	
  discovery	
  of	
  new	
  threats	
  such	
  as	
  global	
  warming,	
  but	
  to	
  
the	
  recently	
  developed	
  understandings	
  of	
  the	
  inherent	
  limitations	
  of	
  science.	
  	
  
Once	
  thought	
  of	
  as	
  a	
  vehicle	
  through	
  which	
  domination	
  of	
  nature	
  could	
  be	
  
achieved,	
  we	
  now	
  distrust	
  science’s	
  ability	
  to	
  solve	
  the	
  problems	
  that	
  domination	
  
has	
  produced.36	
  	
  On	
  the	
  other	
  hand,	
  for	
  Beck,	
  ‘[t]he	
  exposure	
  of	
  scientific	
  
uncertainty	
  is	
  the	
  liberation	
  of	
  politics,	
  law	
  and	
  the	
  public	
  sphere	
  from	
  their	
  
patronization	
  by	
  technocracy’.37	
  	
  Yet	
  these	
  threats,	
  especially	
  global	
  warming,	
  
still	
  necessitate	
  by	
  their	
  very	
  nature	
  a	
  dependence	
  upon	
  expertise	
  at	
  the	
  very	
  
time	
  of	
  this	
  questioning.38	
  	
  For	
  expert	
  bodies,	
  such	
  as	
  the	
  International	
  Panel	
  on	
  
Climate	
  Change	
  (IPCC),	
  are	
  not	
  only	
  intimately	
  involved	
  in	
  the	
  construction	
  of	
  
public	
  perceptions	
  of	
  risk,	
  but	
  also	
  in	
  our	
  response	
  to	
  them,	
  given	
  that	
  the	
  
prevailing	
  approach	
  to	
  decision-­‐making	
  is	
  bound	
  up	
  in	
  modernity.39	
  	
  Indeed,	
  as	
  


	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  
35	
  W.	
  Lance	
  Bennett	
  and	
  Robert	
  M.	
  Entman	
  (eds.),	
  Mediated	
  Politics:	
  

Communication	
  in	
  the	
  Future	
  of	
  Democracy,	
  New	
  York,	
  Cambridge	
  University	
  
Press,	
  2001,	
  pp.	
  468-­‐469.	
  
36	
  Irwin,	
  Citizen	
  Science,	
  pp.	
  45-­‐46.	
  
37	
  Quoted	
  in	
  ibid,	
  p.	
  60.	
  
38	
  Ülrich	
  Beck,	
  Ecological	
  Politics	
  in	
  an	
  Age	
  of	
  Risk,	
  Cambridge,	
  Polity	
  Press,	
  1995,	
  

p.	
  161.	
  
39	
  Geert	
  Munnichs,	
  ‘Whom	
  to	
  Trust?:	
  	
  Public	
  Concerns,	
  Late	
  Modern	
  Risks,	
  and	
  

Expert	
  Trustworthiness,’	
  Journal	
  of	
  Agricultural	
  and	
  Environmental	
  Ethics,	
  Vol.	
  
17,	
  No.	
  2,	
  2004,	
  p.	
  114.	
  


	
                                                                                                                                                                                                                          8	
  
Beck	
  himself	
  points	
  out,	
  the	
  answer	
  of	
  industrial	
  society	
  to	
  the	
  challenge	
  of	
  risk	
  
is	
  to	
  intensify	
  technocratic	
  solutions.40	
  	
  	
  
	
  
                   Arguably	
  then,	
  what	
  is	
  required	
  is	
  the	
  democratization	
  of	
  expertise	
  itself.	
  	
  
Moves	
  towards	
  the	
  inclusion	
  of	
  lay	
  understandings	
  of	
  risk	
  issues,	
  with	
  a	
  view	
  to	
  
incorporating	
  them	
  within	
  decision-­‐making	
  processes,	
  have	
  in	
  fact	
  begun.41	
  	
  The	
  
House	
  of	
  Lords	
  in	
  Britain,	
  for	
  instance,	
  called	
  for	
  enhanced	
  public	
  involvement	
  in	
  
scientific	
  matters	
  in	
  2000,	
  and	
  the	
  European	
  Commission	
  committed	
  itself	
  in	
  
2001	
  to	
  ‘sustained	
  dialogue	
  between	
  experts,	
  public	
  and	
  policy	
  makers’.	
  	
  In	
  
Scandinavia,	
  moreover,	
  the	
  success	
  of	
  expert-­‐citizen	
  dialogue	
  models,	
  pioneered	
  
by	
  the	
  Danish	
  Board	
  of	
  Technology,	
  have	
  led	
  to	
  calls	
  for	
  their	
  adaptation	
  in	
  other	
  
Western	
  democracies.	
  	
  These	
  consensus	
  conferences	
  between	
  expert	
  and	
  lay	
  
panels	
  provide	
  a	
  platform	
  for	
  the	
  questioning	
  of	
  expert	
  pronouncements	
  on	
  both	
  
cognitive	
  and	
  normative	
  grounds.42	
  	
  Experts	
  are	
  thus	
  forced	
  to	
  justify	
  their	
  
assumptions	
  as	
  lay	
  audiences	
  search	
  for	
  value	
  judgements	
  and	
  the	
  infiltration	
  of	
  
special	
  interests	
  into	
  knowledge	
  generation.	
  	
  Such	
  conferences	
  are	
  particularly	
  
useful	
  in	
  the	
  context	
  of	
  uncertainty	
  and	
  controversy,	
  as	
  prior	
  contestation	
  
enhances	
  the	
  legitimacy	
  of	
  democratic	
  decisions.43	
  	
  These	
  initiatives	
  are	
  
therefore	
  gaining	
  credence	
  within	
  public	
  policy	
  discourse,	
  as	
  they	
  are	
  regarded	
  
as	
  a	
  means	
  of	
  addressing	
  ‘a	
  number	
  of	
  perceived	
  sources	
  of	
  potential	
  crisis	
  in	
  
contemporary	
  governance;	
  namely	
  deficits	
  of	
  knowledge,	
  trust,	
  and	
  legitimacy’.44	
  
                   	
  
                   	
  
                   	
  
                   	
  
                   	
  

	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  
40	
  Beck,	
  Ecological	
  Politics,	
  pp.	
  166-­‐167	
  
41	
  Tom	
  Horlick-­‐Jones	
  et	
  al.,	
  ‘Citizen	
  Engagement	
  Processes	
  as	
  Information	
  

Systems:	
  The	
  Role	
  of	
  Knowledge	
  and	
  the	
  Concept	
  of	
  Translation	
  Quality,	
  Public	
  
Understandings	
  of	
  Science,	
  Vol.	
  16,	
  2007,	
  p.	
  260.	
  
42	
  Anders	
  Blok,	
  ‘Experts	
  on	
  Public	
  Trial:	
  On	
  Democratizing	
  Expertise	
  Through	
  a	
  

Danish	
  Consensus	
  Conference’,	
  Public	
  Understandings	
  of	
  Science,	
  Vol.	
  16,	
  2007,	
  
pp.	
  163-­‐164.	
  
43	
  Ibid,	
  p.	
  176.	
  
44	
  Horlick-­‐Jones	
  et	
  al.,	
  ‘Citizen	
  Engagement’,	
  p.	
  259.	
  




	
                                                                                                                                                                                                                                 9	
  
Epistemic	
  Communities	
  and	
  Climate	
  Consensus	
  
	
  
                   Given	
  these	
  deficits	
  in	
  trust	
  and	
  legitimacy,	
  how	
  can	
  the	
  expert	
  consensus	
  
on	
  climate	
  change	
  and	
  its	
  authority	
  in	
  decision-­‐making,	
  be	
  explained?45	
  	
  Peter	
  
Haas	
  developed	
  the	
  notion	
  of	
  epistemic	
  communities	
  as	
  a	
  way	
  of	
  understanding	
  
how	
  such	
  bodies	
  gain	
  authority	
  through	
  consensus	
  building	
  surrounding	
  their	
  
specific	
  knowledge.	
  	
  Following	
  Adler,	
  such	
  communities	
  can	
  be	
  defined	
  as:	
  
	
  
                   a	
  network	
  of	
  individuals	
  or	
  groups	
  with	
  an	
  authoritative	
  claim	
  to	
  policy-­‐
                   relevant	
  knowledge	
  within	
  their	
  domain	
  of	
  expertise…They	
  adhere	
  to	
  the	
  
                   following:	
  	
  (1)	
  	
  shared	
  consummatory	
  values	
  	
  and	
  principled	
  beliefs;	
  (2)	
  
                   shared	
  causal	
  beliefs	
  or	
  professional	
  judgement;	
  (3)	
  common	
  notions	
  of	
  
                   validity	
  based	
  on	
  intersujective	
  internally	
  defined	
  criteria	
  for	
  validating	
  
                   knowledge;	
  and	
  (4)	
  a	
  common	
  policy	
  project.46	
  
	
  
Once	
  consensus	
  has	
  been	
  achieved,	
  and	
  epistemic	
  communities	
  formed	
  around	
  it,	
  
its	
  members	
  implant	
  themselves	
  within	
  state	
  and	
  international	
  bureaucracies	
  in	
  
order	
  to	
  affect	
  policy	
  decisions.	
  	
  They	
  are	
  thus	
  well	
  positioned	
  to	
  define	
  the	
  
content	
  of	
  policy	
  problems,	
  prescribe	
  solutions,	
  and	
  ultimately	
  assess	
  policy	
  
outcomes.47	
  	
  	
  
	
  
                   In	
  the	
  case	
  of	
  global	
  warming,	
  such	
  a	
  community	
  could	
  arguably	
  be	
  
located	
  within	
  the	
  body	
  of	
  the	
  IPCC.48	
  	
  Following	
  the	
  above	
  criteria,	
  the	
  IPCC,	
  


	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  
45	
  Those	
  subscribing	
  to	
  the	
  expert	
  consensus	
  believe	
  that	
  we	
  know	
  ‘beyond	
  

reasonable	
  doubt	
  that	
  the	
  world	
  is	
  warming	
  and	
  that	
  human	
  emissions	
  of	
  
greenhouse	
  gases	
  are	
  the	
  primary	
  cause’.	
  	
  Climate	
  Commission,	
  The	
  Critical	
  
Decade:	
  Climate	
  Science,	
  Risks	
  and	
  Responses,	
  Canberra,	
  Climate	
  Commission	
  
Secretariat,	
  2011,	
  p.	
  60,	
  retrieved	
  19	
  June	
  2011,	
  available	
  from	
  
<http://climatecommission.gov.au/topics/the-­‐critical-­‐decade/>.	
  
46	
  Quoted	
  in	
  Matthew	
  Paterson,	
  Global	
  Warming	
  and	
  Global	
  Politics,	
  New	
  York,	
  

Routledge,	
  1996,	
  p.	
  135.	
  
47	
  See	
  Peter	
  M.	
  Haas,	
  ‘Introduction:	
  Epistemic	
  Communities	
  and	
  International	
  

Policy	
  Coordination,’	
  International	
  Organization,	
  Vol.	
  46,	
  No.	
  1,	
  1992,	
  pp.	
  1-­‐35.	
  
48	
  Many	
  members	
  of	
  the	
  IPCC	
  have	
  been	
  involved	
  in	
  climate	
  research	
  since	
  the	
  

1970s,	
  and	
  involved	
  in	
  expert	
  bodies	
  such	
  as	
  the	
  World	
  Meteorological	
  
Organization	
  (WMO)	
  and	
  the	
  United	
  Nations	
  Environment	
  Programme	
  (UNEP),	
  


	
                                                                                                                                                                                                                          10	
  
through	
  its	
  four	
  year	
  reporting	
  structure,	
  periodically	
  publishes	
  shared	
  
principled	
  belief	
  statements,	
  despite	
  regular	
  admissions	
  of	
  uncertainty,49	
  along	
  
with	
  casual	
  judgements	
  related	
  to	
  the	
  role	
  of	
  carbon	
  dioxide	
  in	
  global	
  warming;50	
  
it	
  shares	
  agreed	
  mechanisms	
  for	
  testing	
  in	
  the	
  form	
  of	
  climate	
  modelling;51	
  and	
  it	
  
shares	
  a	
  common	
  policy	
  response	
  to	
  the	
  problem	
  –	
  the	
  drastic	
  reduction	
  of	
  
greenhouse	
  gas	
  emissions.52	
  	
  The	
  IPCC	
  and	
  its	
  predecessors,	
  moreover,	
  were	
  
vital	
  to	
  the	
  emergence	
  of	
  global	
  warming	
  as	
  an	
  area	
  of	
  significant	
  policy	
  concern,	
  
and	
  to	
  the	
  fostering	
  of	
  consensus	
  on	
  its	
  nature.53	
  
	
  
                                                      Yet	
  it	
  is	
  not	
  clear	
  that	
  epistemic	
  community	
  frameworks	
  are	
  sufficient	
  to	
  
deal	
  with	
  global	
  warming	
  for	
  two	
  reasons.	
  	
  Firstly,	
  the	
  level	
  of	
  consensus	
  on	
  the	
  
relationship	
  between	
  human	
  activity	
  and	
  warming	
  is	
  not	
  absolute,	
  with	
  multiple	
  
communities	
  claiming	
  true	
  knowledge.	
  	
  The	
  epistemic	
  community	
  approach,	
  
however,	
  takes	
  scientific	
  consensus	
  as	
  the	
  precursor	
  to	
  policy	
  influence,	
  when	
  it	
  
is	
  in	
  fact	
  far	
  more	
  complex	
  than	
  such	
  a	
  linear	
  relationship.54	
  	
  Consensus,	
  based	
  
here	
  upon	
  a	
  generally	
  agreed	
  set	
  of	
  possible	
  outcomes	
  rather	
  than	
  a	
  single	
  and	
  
exact	
  prediction,	
  is	
  reached	
  through	
  the	
  interplay	
  of	
  assertion	
  and	
  disagreement	
  
both	
  between	
  experts,	
  and	
  between	
  experts	
  and	
  policymakers.	
  	
  During	
  this	
  
process	
  the	
  content	
  of	
  consensus	
  can	
  be	
  altered	
  significantly	
  based	
  upon	
  value	
  
	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  
as	
  well	
  as	
  the	
  First	
  Climate	
  Change	
  Conference	
  and	
  the	
  International	
  Council	
  of	
  
Scientists.	
  	
  Paterson,	
  Global	
  Warming,	
  p.	
  140.	
  
49	
  In	
  the	
  IPCC’s	
  most	
  recent	
  assessment	
  report,	
  global	
  warming	
  was	
  described	
  as	
  

‘unequivocal’,	
  and	
  its	
  human	
  sources	
  as	
  ‘very	
  likely’,	
  despite	
  uncertainties	
  in	
  the	
  
accuracy	
  of	
  data	
  and	
  the	
  projections	
  based	
  upon	
  it.	
  	
  International	
  Panel	
  on	
  
Climate	
  Change,	
  IPCC	
  Fourth	
  Assessment	
  Report:	
  Climate	
  Change	
  2007:	
  Synthesis	
  
Report,	
  Cambridge,	
  Cambridge	
  University	
  Press,	
  2007,	
  p.	
  72,	
  retrieved	
  19	
  June	
  
2011,	
  available	
  from	
  <	
  http://www.ipcc.ch/publications_and_data/ar4/syr/en/	
  
contents.html>.	
  	
  It	
  is	
  important	
  to	
  recognize,	
  however,	
  that	
  the	
  uncertainty	
  
described,	
  and	
  indicated	
  by	
  the	
  phrase	
  ‘very	
  likely’,	
  refers	
  to	
  a	
  90	
  percent	
  
probability.	
  	
  Ibid,	
  p.	
  27.	
  
50	
  Ibid,	
  p.	
  72.	
  
51	
  See,	
  for	
  example,	
  ibid,	
  p.	
  51-­‐59.	
  
52	
  Ibid,	
  p.	
  60.	
  
53	
  Paterson,	
  Global	
  Warming,	
  pp.	
  140-­‐144.	
  	
  See	
  ibid,	
  pp.	
  144-­‐147,	
  for	
  the	
  

evolution	
  of	
  the	
  global	
  warming	
  agenda	
  from	
  the	
  1970s	
  to	
  the	
  mid-­‐1990s.	
  
54	
  Paul	
  N.	
  Edwards	
  and	
  Clark	
  A.	
  Miller,	
  ‘Introduction:	
  The	
  Globalization	
  of	
  

Climate	
  Science	
  and	
  Climate	
  Politics,’	
  in	
  Paul	
  N.	
  Edwards	
  and	
  Clark	
  A.	
  Miller	
  
(eds.),	
  Changing	
  the	
  Atmosphere:	
  Expert	
  Knowledge	
  and	
  Environmental	
  
Governance,	
  Cambridge,	
  MIT	
  Press,	
  2001,	
  p.	
  4.	
  


	
                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                             11	
  
judgements	
  by	
  actors	
  external	
  to	
  the	
  epistemic	
  community,	
  and	
  related	
  to	
  risk	
  
and	
  available	
  resources.55	
  	
  Secondly,	
  as	
  Karen	
  Liftin	
  has	
  argued,	
  the	
  approach	
  
tends	
  to	
  disregard	
  the	
  links	
  between	
  science	
  and	
  politics,	
  downplaying	
  ‘the	
  ways	
  
in	
  which	
  scientific	
  information	
  simply	
  rationalizes	
  or	
  reinforces	
  existing	
  political	
  
conflicts.56	
  	
  Indeed,	
  issues	
  such	
  as	
  global	
  warming	
  are	
  controversial	
  inasmuch	
  as	
  
they	
  involve	
  ‘ongoing	
  conflicts	
  over	
  basic	
  values	
  and	
  interest.’57	
  	
  Thus,	
  different	
  
actors,	
  each	
  seeking	
  particular	
  policy	
  goals,	
  have	
  manipulated	
  scientific	
  expertise	
  
with	
  their	
  own	
  values	
  and	
  interests	
  in	
  mind	
  through	
  the	
  primary	
  communication	
  
channel	
  for	
  the	
  lay	
  public	
  in	
  regards	
  to	
  global	
  warming	
  –	
  the	
  media.58	
  
	
  
                   In	
  the	
  case	
  of	
  global	
  warming	
  these	
  ongoing	
  political	
  conflicts	
  involve	
  
significant	
  implications	
  of	
  a	
  foundational	
  nature.	
  	
  On	
  the	
  one	
  hand,	
  the	
  possibility	
  
of	
  ecological	
  catastrophe	
  resulting	
  from	
  current	
  modes	
  of	
  human	
  activity	
  implies	
  
a	
  crisis	
  of	
  industrial	
  society	
  itself,	
  and	
  thus	
  demands	
  self-­‐reflection	
  on	
  its	
  very	
  
foundations.59	
  	
  Conflict	
  here	
  is	
  not	
  being	
  fought	
  over	
  the	
  spoils	
  of	
  profit	
  and	
  
prosperity,	
  but	
  the	
  allocation	
  of	
  negatives,	
  threats	
  and	
  possible	
  devastation.60	
  On	
  
the	
  other	
  hand,	
  the	
  global	
  warming	
  debate	
  has	
  become	
  a	
  space	
  for	
  the	
  possible	
  
reconfiguration	
  of	
  the	
  global	
  order,	
  with	
  institutions	
  created	
  on	
  a	
  worldwide	
  
scale	
  to	
  tackle	
  it	
  becoming	
  sites	
  of	
  contestation	
  over	
  norms	
  and	
  practice.61	
  	
  
Despite	
  the	
  importance	
  of	
  these	
  conflicts,	
  the	
  debate	
  is	
  framed	
  within	
  the	
  
Western	
  media	
  in	
  terms	
  of	
  science,	
  rather	
  than	
  as	
  an	
  investigation	
  into	
  the	
  social	
  
and	
  cultural	
  dimensions	
  of	
  the	
  risk	
  itself.62	
  
	
  
	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  
55	
  Paul	
  N.	
  Edwards	
  and	
  Stephen	
  H.	
  Schneider,	
  ‘Self-­‐Governance	
  and	
  Peer	
  Review	
  

in	
  Science-­‐for-­‐policy:	
  The	
  Case	
  of	
  the	
  IPCC	
  Second	
  Assessment	
  Report,’	
  in	
  Paul	
  N.	
  
Edwards	
  and	
  Clark	
  A.	
  Miller	
  (eds.),	
  Changing	
  the	
  Atmosphere:	
  Expert	
  Knowledge	
  
and	
  Environmental	
  Governance,	
  Cambridge,	
  MIT	
  Press,	
  2001,	
  pp.	
  244-­‐245	
  
56	
  Quoted	
  in	
  Paterson,	
  Global	
  Warming,	
  p.	
  150.	
  
57	
  Brown,	
  Science	
  in	
  Democracy,	
  pp.	
  2-­‐3.	
  
58	
  Alison	
  Anderson,	
  Media,	
  Culture	
  and	
  the	
  Environment,	
  London,	
  UCL	
  Press,	
  1997,	
  

pp.	
  107-­‐115.	
  
59	
  Ülrich	
  Beck	
  et	
  al.,	
  Reflexive	
  Modernization:	
  Politics,	
  Tradition	
  and	
  Aesthetics	
  in	
  

the	
  Modern	
  Social	
  Order,	
  Cambridge,	
  Polity	
  Press,	
  1994,	
  p.	
  8.	
  
60	
  Ülrich	
  Beck,	
  Ecological	
  Enlightenment:	
  Essays	
  on	
  the	
  Politics	
  of	
  the	
  Risk	
  Society,	
  

Atlantic	
  Highlands,	
  Humanities	
  Press,	
  1995,	
  p.	
  3.	
  
61	
  Edwards	
  and	
  Miller,	
  ‘Introduction’,	
  pp.	
  2-­‐4.	
  
62	
  Irwin,	
  Citizen	
  Science,	
  p.	
  37.	
  




	
                                                                                                                                                                                                                    12	
  
Indeed,	
  contestation	
  in	
  this	
  debate	
  has	
  generally	
  taken	
  place	
  on	
  the	
  
nature	
  of	
  the	
  consensus	
  itself.	
  	
  For	
  instance,	
  the	
  IPCC’s	
  Second	
  Assessment	
  
Report	
  of	
  1996,	
  in	
  its	
  eight	
  chapter,	
  concluded	
  that	
  ‘the	
  balance	
  of	
  evidence	
  
suggests	
  that	
  there	
  is	
  a	
  discernible	
  human	
  influence	
  on	
  global	
  climate’.	
  	
  
Immediately,	
  however,	
  these	
  claims	
  were	
  contested,	
  especially	
  on	
  the	
  basis	
  that	
  
human	
  activity	
  was	
  the	
  root	
  cause.	
  	
  Led	
  by	
  the	
  eminent	
  physicist	
  Frederick	
  Seitz,	
  
those	
  dissenting	
  claimed	
  that	
  the	
  peer	
  review	
  process	
  had	
  been	
  compromised	
  
for	
  political	
  reasons,	
  claims	
  that	
  ignited	
  a	
  debate	
  widely	
  reported	
  in	
  the	
  media.63	
  	
  
Unproven	
  claims	
  such	
  as	
  Seitz’s	
  gain	
  credence	
  in	
  the	
  public	
  sphere,	
  and	
  
undermine	
  trust	
  in	
  bodies	
  such	
  as	
  the	
  IPCC,	
  regardless	
  of	
  the	
  fact	
  that	
  IPCC	
  
publications	
  are	
  peer-­‐reviewed	
  by	
  hundreds	
  of	
  experts	
  prior	
  to	
  release,	
  a	
  
process	
  explained	
  by	
  the	
  overrepresentation	
  of	
  marginal	
  views	
  in	
  the	
  media,64	
  
and	
  by	
  the	
  nature	
  of	
  climate	
  science	
  itself.65	
  	
  Unfortunately,	
  due	
  to	
  their	
  technical	
  


	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  
63	
  Seitz’s	
  complaints	
  were	
  based	
  on	
  the	
  conclusions	
  contained	
  in	
  chapter	
  eight,	
  

which	
  he	
  claimed	
  had	
  been	
  altered	
  following	
  the	
  November	
  1995	
  plenary	
  
meeting	
  of	
  IPCC	
  Working	
  Group	
  I.	
  	
  At	
  this	
  meeting,	
  Seitz	
  claimed,	
  the	
  text	
  of	
  that	
  
chapter	
  had	
  been	
  agreed	
  too,	
  and	
  the	
  subsequent	
  deletion	
  of	
  passages	
  that	
  
indicated	
  uncertainty	
  amounted	
  to	
  the	
  corruption	
  of	
  peer	
  review	
  for	
  political	
  
ends.	
  	
  Not	
  surprisingly	
  the	
  IPCC	
  Secretariat,	
  who	
  pointed	
  to	
  peer	
  review	
  process	
  
undertaken	
  following	
  alterations	
  to	
  the	
  text,	
  dismissed	
  these	
  claims.	
  	
  Edwards	
  
and	
  Schneider,	
  ‘Self-­‐Governance	
  and	
  Peer	
  Review’,	
  p.	
  219.	
  
64	
  In	
  Australia,	
  for	
  example,	
  research	
  has	
  shown	
  that	
  the	
  media	
  is	
  the	
  main	
  

source	
  of	
  information	
  on	
  climate	
  change,	
  and	
  the	
  main	
  factor	
  shaping	
  people’s	
  
awareness	
  of	
  it,	
  especially	
  as	
  regards	
  uncertainty.	
  	
  Desley	
  L.	
  Speck,	
  ‘A	
  Hot	
  Topic?	
  
Climate	
  Change	
  Mitigation	
  Policies,	
  Politics,	
  and	
  the	
  Media	
  in	
  Australia,’	
  Human	
  
Ecology	
  Review,	
  Vol.	
  17,	
  No.	
  2,	
  2010,	
  p.	
  125.	
  	
  For	
  examples	
  of	
  the	
  publication	
  of	
  
marginal	
  views	
  in	
  the	
  media	
  in	
  Australia,	
  see	
  Jo	
  Chandler,	
  ‘When	
  Science	
  is	
  
Undone	
  by	
  Fiction’,	
  The	
  Age,	
  June	
  29	
  2011,	
  retrieved	
  29	
  June	
  2011,	
  available	
  
from	
  <http://www.theage.com.au/opinion/politics/when-­‐science-­‐is-­‐undone-­‐by-­‐
fiction-­‐20110628-­‐1gp26.html>;	
  and	
  John	
  Cook,	
  ‘Half	
  the	
  Truth	
  on	
  Emissions’,	
  
The	
  Age,	
  June	
  28	
  2011,	
  retrieved	
  29	
  June	
  2011,	
  available	
  from	
  
<http://www.theage.	
  com.au/opinion/society-­‐and-­‐culture/half-­‐the-­‐truth-­‐on-­‐
emissions-­‐20110627-­‐1gne1.html>.	
  
65	
  Climate	
  science	
  is	
  based	
  upon	
  modelling	
  using	
  ‘semi-­‐empirical	
  and	
  heuristic	
  

principles	
  derived	
  from	
  observation’.	
  	
  These	
  observations	
  suffer	
  from	
  problems	
  
of	
  scale	
  and	
  availability,	
  leading	
  to	
  inaccurate,	
  incomplete,	
  inconsistent	
  and	
  
temporally	
  brief	
  regional	
  data	
  sets,	
  which	
  are	
  then	
  globalized	
  through	
  
interpolating	
  and	
  correcting.	
  	
  Paul	
  N.	
  Edwards,	
  ‘Representing	
  the	
  Global	
  
Atmosphere:	
  Computer	
  Models,	
  Data,	
  and	
  Knowledge	
  about	
  Climate	
  Change’,	
  in	
  P.	
  
N.	
  Edwards	
  and	
  C.	
  A.	
  Miller	
  (eds.),	
  Changing	
  the	
  Atmosphere:	
  Expert	
  Knowledge	
  
and	
  Environmental	
  Governance,	
  Cambridge,	
  MIT	
  Press,	
  2001,	
  pp.	
  62-­‐63.	
  	
  For	
  a	
  


	
                                                                                                                                                                                                                    13	
  
nature,	
  the	
  facts	
  and	
  data	
  on	
  global	
  warming	
  do	
  not	
  speak	
  for	
  themselves,	
  and	
  
have	
  to	
  be	
  interpreted	
  and	
  acted	
  upon	
  based	
  on	
  expert	
  advice.66	
  	
  As	
  Professor	
  
Ross	
  Garnaut	
  has	
  claimed,	
  ‘the	
  outsider	
  to	
  climate	
  science	
  has	
  no	
  rational	
  choice	
  
but	
  to	
  accept	
  that,	
  on	
  a	
  balance	
  of	
  probabilities,	
  the	
  mainstream	
  science	
  is	
  right	
  
in	
  pointing	
  to	
  high	
  risks	
  from	
  unmitigated	
  climate	
  change’.67	
  	
  Regardless	
  of	
  this	
  
dependence,	
  sceptics	
  can	
  ‘cherry-­‐pick’	
  details	
  and	
  claim	
  them	
  as	
  contrary	
  to	
  the	
  
overall	
  consensus,	
  thereby	
  undermining	
  confidence.68	
  	
  
	
  
‘Climategate’	
  
	
  
                                                      The	
  effects	
  of	
  contestation	
  over	
  the	
  global	
  warming	
  ‘consensus’	
  are	
  best	
  
illustrated	
  by	
  the	
  so-­‐called	
  ‘climategate’	
  scandal.	
  	
  On	
  20	
  November	
  2009	
  hacked	
  
emails,	
  sent	
  over	
  a	
  15-­‐year	
  period,	
  and	
  originating	
  from	
  the	
  Climate	
  Research	
  
Unit	
  (CRU)69	
  of	
  the	
  University	
  of	
  East	
  Anglia,	
  were	
  released	
  publically	
  on	
  the	
  
website	
  realclimate.org.	
  	
  The	
  emails,	
  it	
  was	
  claimed,	
  showed	
  evidence	
  of	
  data	
  
suppression	
  and	
  manipulation,	
  as	
  well	
  as	
  intimidation	
  of	
  scientific	
  journal	
  
editors	
  in	
  order	
  to	
  prevent	
  the	
  publication	
  of	
  contrary	
  opinions,	
  all	
  as	
  part	
  of	
  an	
  
effort	
  to	
  manufacture	
  consensus	
  on	
  climate	
  change.70	
  	
  The	
  supposed	
  uncovering	
  
of	
  such	
  activity	
  amounted	
  to	
  what	
  one	
  climate	
  change	
  sceptic,	
  Christopher	
  
Brooks	
  of	
  The	
  Telegraph,	
  called	
  the	
  ‘worst	
  scientific	
  scandal	
  of	
  our	
  generation’.71	
  	
  

	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  
good	
  typology	
  of	
  climate	
  modeling	
  and	
  data	
  collection	
  see	
  ibid,	
  pp.	
  35-­‐49;	
  for	
  a	
  
detailed	
  overview	
  of	
  specific	
  modeling	
  methods	
  see	
  ibid,	
  pp.	
  55-­‐62.	
  
66	
  Ibid,	
  pp.	
  32-­‐33.	
  
67	
  Ross	
  Garnaut,	
  The	
  Garnaut	
  Climate	
  Change	
  Review:	
  Final	
  Report,	
  Port	
  

Melbourne,	
  Cambridge	
  University	
  Press,	
  2008,	
  p.	
  xcii.	
  
68	
  Irwin,	
  Citizen	
  Science,	
  pp.	
  67-­‐68.	
  	
  See	
  for	
  example,	
  Cook,	
  ‘Half	
  the	
  Truth	
  on	
  

Emissions’.	
  
69	
  The	
  CRU	
  is	
  one	
  of	
  the	
  most	
  influential	
  scientific	
  institutions	
  in	
  the	
  field	
  of	
  

climate	
  change,	
  heavily	
  involved	
  in	
  the	
  collection	
  of	
  datasets	
  and	
  climate	
  
modelling	
  used	
  in	
  the	
  IPCC’s	
  assessment	
  reports.	
  	
  Brigitte	
  Nerlich,	
  ‘"Climategate":	
  
Paradoxical	
  Metaphors	
  and	
  Political	
  Paralysis,’	
  Environmental	
  Values,	
  Vol.	
  19,	
  
2010,	
  pp.	
  421-­‐422.	
  
70	
  For	
  an	
  example	
  of	
  such	
  claims	
  see	
  George	
  H.	
  Avery,	
  ‘Scientific	
  Misconduct:	
  The	
  

Perversion	
  of	
  Scientific	
  Evidence	
  for	
  Public	
  Advocacy’,	
  World	
  Medical	
  &	
  Health	
  
Policy,	
  Vol.	
  2,	
  No.	
  4,	
  2010,	
  p.	
  20.	
  
71	
  Christopher	
  Booker,	
  ‘Climate	
  Change:	
  This	
  is	
  the	
  Worst	
  Scientific	
  Scandal	
  of	
  

our	
  Generation’,	
  The	
  Telegraph,	
  28	
  November	
  2009,	
  retrieved	
  19	
  June	
  2011	
  
available	
  from	
  <http://www.telegraph.co.uk/comment/columnists/	
  


	
                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                             14	
  
Conservative	
  bloggers,	
  moreover,	
  framed	
  the	
  ‘scandal’	
  as	
  evidence	
  of	
  a	
  climate	
  
change	
  ‘scam’,	
  and	
  the	
  scientific	
  advice	
  behind	
  the	
  consensus	
  as	
  untrustworthy.72	
  	
  	
  
	
  
                                                      Three	
  independent	
  panels	
  would	
  later	
  conclude	
  that	
  there	
  was	
  in	
  fact	
  no	
  
evidence	
  of	
  misconduct	
  on	
  the	
  part	
  of	
  the	
  scientists.	
  	
  Yet	
  media	
  publicity	
  
surrounding	
  the	
  issue	
  ensured	
  the	
  damage	
  had	
  been	
  done.73	
  	
  Analysis	
  of	
  the	
  
emails	
  themselves	
  was	
  never	
  more	
  than	
  perfunctory,	
  allowing	
  the	
  ‘cherry-­‐
picking’	
  of	
  seemingly	
  incriminating	
  details	
  to	
  supress	
  the	
  full	
  story.	
  	
  By	
  the	
  time	
  
of	
  the	
  release	
  of	
  the	
  panels’	
  findings,	
  the	
  reputations	
  of	
  the	
  experts	
  involved	
  had	
  
already	
  been	
  tarnished	
  and	
  have	
  since	
  struggled	
  to	
  recover.74	
  	
  Brigitte	
  Nerlich,	
  
who	
  has	
  studied	
  the	
  reaction	
  to	
  the	
  release	
  of	
  the	
  emails	
  found	
  that	
  even	
  its	
  
framing	
  as	
  ‘climategate’,	
  with	
  negative	
  connotations	
  of	
  the	
  Watergate	
  scandal	
  
and	
  political	
  cover	
  up,	
  resonated	
  ‘with	
  popular	
  imagination	
  and	
  cultural	
  
knowledge’.	
  	
  This	
  process	
  opened	
  ‘up	
  a	
  whole	
  narrative	
  space	
  or	
  frame’	
  which	
  
allowed	
  ‘people	
  to	
  easily	
  structure	
  their	
  arguments	
  about	
  a	
  controversial	
  
topic’.75	
  	
  Indeed,	
  regardless	
  of	
  the	
  veracity	
  of	
  the	
  claims,	
  the	
  scandal	
  certainly	
  
served	
  to	
  undermine	
  the	
  public’s	
  trust	
  in	
  climate	
  science.	
  	
  For	
  example,	
  in	
  the	
  
aftermath	
  of	
  the	
  release	
  of	
  the	
  emails,	
  and	
  the	
  failure	
  of	
  the	
  Copenhagen	
  
negotiations	
  on	
  global	
  responses	
  to	
  climate	
  change,	
  a	
  British	
  study	
  revealed	
  that	
  
‘the	
  proportion	
  of	
  adults	
  who	
  believe	
  climate	
  change	
  is	
  “definitely”	
  a	
  reality	
  
dropped	
  by	
  30%	
  over	
  the	
  last	
  year,	
  from	
  44%	
  to	
  31%.’76	
  	
  The	
  public	
  outrage	
  that	
  
	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  
christopherbooker/6679082/Climate-­‐change-­‐this-­‐is-­‐the-­‐worst-­‐scientific-­‐
scandal-­‐of-­‐our-­‐generation.html>.	
  
72	
  Brigitte	
  Nerlich,	
  ‘"Climategate”’,	
  pp.	
  421-­‐422.	
  
73	
  Richard	
  Fielding,	
  ‘The	
  Perversion	
  of	
  Scientific	
  Evidence	
  for	
  Policy	
  Advocacy:	
  A	
  

Perspective	
  on	
  Avery	
  2010’,	
  World	
  Medical	
  &	
  Health	
  Policy,	
  Vol.	
  3,	
  No.	
  1,	
  2011,	
  p.	
  
2.	
  	
  For	
  an	
  example	
  of	
  one	
  of	
  the	
  panels	
  findings	
  see	
  	
  
74	
  Fred	
  Pearce,	
  ‘How	
  the	
  “Climategate”	
  Scandal	
  is	
  Bogus	
  and	
  Based	
  on	
  Climate	
  

Sceptics’	
  Lies’,	
  The	
  Guardian,	
  2	
  February	
  2010,	
  p.	
  7,	
  retrieved	
  19	
  June	
  2011,	
  
available	
  from	
  <http://www.guardian.co.uk/environment/2010/feb/01/	
  
climate-­‐emails-­‐sceptics>.	
  	
  As	
  it	
  cannot	
  be	
  undertaken	
  here,	
  for	
  an	
  in	
  depth	
  
analysis	
  of	
  the	
  content	
  of	
  the	
  emails,	
  and	
  the	
  phrases	
  that	
  led	
  people	
  to	
  believe	
  
that	
  a	
  ‘scam’	
  had	
  been	
  uncovered,	
  see	
  Celia	
  Deane-­‐Drummond,	
  ‘A	
  Case	
  for	
  
Collective	
  Conscience:	
  Climate	
  Gate,	
  COP-­‐15	
  and	
  Climate	
  Justice’,	
  Studies	
  in	
  
Christian	
  Ethics,	
  Vol.	
  24,	
  No.	
  1,	
  2011,	
  p.	
  8-­‐10.	
  
75	
  Nerlich,	
  ‘”Climategate”’,	
  p.	
  423.	
  
76	
  Juliette	
  Jowit,	
  ‘Sharp	
  Decline	
  in	
  the	
  Public’s	
  Belief	
  in	
  Climate	
  Threat,	
  British	
  

Poll	
  Reveals’,	
  The	
  Guardian,	
  24	
  February	
  2010,	
  p.	
  9,	
  retrieved	
  19	
  June	
  2011,	
  


	
                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                             15	
  
followed,	
  however	
  misplaced,	
  weakened	
  pressure	
  for	
  political	
  action	
  on	
  a	
  global	
  
scale,	
  a	
  fact	
  highlighted	
  by	
  the	
  failure	
  of	
  Copenhagen,	
  and	
  fed	
  into	
  debates	
  over	
  
the	
  legitimacy	
  of	
  scientific	
  expertise	
  in	
  democracies.77	
  	
  	
  
	
  
                                                      Yet	
  ‘Climategate’	
  did	
  bring	
  about	
  several	
  important	
  changes	
  in	
  the	
  
conduct	
  of	
  climate	
  expertise.	
  	
  Many	
  bodies	
  involved	
  in	
  data	
  collection	
  moved	
  
towards	
  the	
  opening	
  up	
  of	
  datasets	
  to	
  public	
  scrutiny.	
  	
  It	
  also	
  forced	
  experts	
  to	
  
acknowledge	
  that	
  climate	
  change	
  policy	
  is	
  not	
  created	
  in	
  a	
  linear	
  relationship	
  
between	
  science	
  and	
  decision-­‐making,	
  but	
  rather	
  includes	
  a	
  complex	
  set	
  of	
  value	
  
and	
  interest	
  inputs	
  which	
  must	
  be	
  negotiated.78	
  	
  Nonetheless,	
  critics	
  continue	
  to	
  
claim	
  that	
  the	
  dependence	
  on	
  funding	
  streams,	
  linked	
  to	
  the	
  political	
  existence	
  of	
  
the	
  threat,	
  creates	
  inherent	
  incentives	
  for	
  research	
  outcomes	
  to	
  support	
  the	
  
significance	
  of	
  the	
  threat	
  of	
  global	
  warming.79	
  	
  It	
  is	
  argued	
  that	
  the	
  consensus	
  is	
  
garnered	
  through	
  the	
  framing	
  of	
  realities	
  consistent	
  with	
  the	
  scientists’	
  ethics	
  in	
  
order	
  to	
  convince	
  the	
  public	
  of	
  their	
  preferred	
  policy	
  actions.	
  	
  Expertise	
  here	
  
moves	
  from	
  mere	
  observation	
  to	
  outright	
  advocacy.80	
  	
  	
  
	
  
                                                      The	
  case	
  of	
  ‘Climategate’	
  highlights	
  that	
  the	
  global	
  warming	
  ‘consensus’	
  is	
  
in	
  fact	
  contested	
  in	
  nature.	
  	
  This	
  contestation	
  plays	
  upon	
  the	
  uncertain	
  nature	
  of	
  
knowledge	
  on	
  this	
  issue	
  in	
  particular,	
  and	
  in	
  scientific	
  expertise	
  more	
  generally.	
  	
  
As	
  expert	
  authority	
  is	
  based	
  on	
  epistemological	
  certainty,	
  gathered	
  through	
  
neutral	
  observation,	
  it	
  is	
  necessarily	
  diminished	
  as	
  a	
  result.81	
  	
  The	
  established	
  
position	
  of	
  the	
  IPCC	
  as	
  an	
  authority	
  on	
  climate	
  science	
  suffers	
  also	
  as	
  it	
  finds	
  
itself	
  immersed	
  in	
  the	
  crisis	
  of	
  trust	
  and	
  expert	
  legitimacy	
  in	
  the	
  public	
  eye.	
  	
  As	
  
Garnaut	
  has	
  pointed	
  out,	
  it	
  is	
  ‘public	
  attitudes	
  in	
  Australia	
  and	
  in	
  other	
  countries	
  
	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  
available	
  from	
  <http://www.guardian.co.uk/environment/2010/feb/23/british-­‐
public-­‐belief-­‐climate-­‐poll>.	
  
77	
  Deane-­‐Drummond,	
  Studies	
  in	
  Christian	
  Ethics,	
  pp.	
  8-­‐9.	
  
78	
  Mark	
  Hulme,	
  ‘The	
  Year	
  Climate	
  Science	
  was	
  Redefined’,	
  The	
  Guardian,	
  16	
  

November	
  2010,	
  retrieved	
  19	
  June	
  2011,	
  available	
  <http://www.guardian.co.uk/	
  
environment/2010/nov/15/year-­‐climate-­‐science-­‐was-­‐redefined?INTCMP=	
  
SRCH>.	
  
79	
  Avery,	
  ‘Scientific	
  Misconduct’,	
  p.	
  26.	
  
80	
  Ibid,	
  pp.	
  19-­‐20.	
  
81	
  Indeed,	
  Karl	
  Popper	
  convincingly	
  argued	
  the	
  view	
  that	
  without	
  certainty	
  

expertise	
  holds	
  no	
  authority.	
  	
  See	
  Sassower,	
  Knowledge	
  without	
  Expertise,	
  pp.	
  67.	
  


	
                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                             16	
  
[that]	
  create	
  the	
  possibility	
  of	
  major	
  reform…despite	
  the	
  inherent	
  difficulty	
  of	
  
the	
  policy	
  problem’.82	
  
	
  
	
  
Contestation	
  and	
  Democracy	
  
	
  
                     In	
  order	
  both	
  to	
  democratize	
  expertise,	
  and	
  to	
  rescue	
  its	
  authority	
  in	
  
decision-­‐making,	
  real	
  contestation	
  over	
  expert	
  advice	
  needs	
  to	
  take	
  place.	
  	
  It	
  
must	
  be	
  recognised	
  that	
  expert	
  knowledge	
  is	
  often	
  incomplete	
  or	
  uncertain,	
  
especially	
  in	
  cases	
  such	
  as	
  global	
  warming,	
  whose	
  indeterminate	
  nature	
  ensures	
  
that	
  no	
  single	
  and	
  unambiguous	
  answer	
  can	
  be	
  found.	
  	
  This	
  fact	
  allows	
  interest	
  
groups	
  to	
  exploit	
  lay	
  understandings	
  of	
  issues	
  through	
  the	
  use	
  of	
  counter-­‐
expertise,	
  rather	
  than	
  the	
  proper	
  evaluation	
  of	
  the	
  case	
  at	
  hand.83	
  	
  Science	
  alone	
  
cannot	
  provide	
  these	
  judgements,	
  as	
  its	
  normative	
  dimensions	
  relating	
  to	
  
distribution	
  and	
  justice	
  is	
  a	
  concern	
  for	
  the	
  public	
  at	
  large,	
  and	
  necessitates	
  lay	
  
involvement.84	
  	
  	
  
	
  
                     Yet	
  it	
  is	
  debatable	
  whether	
  scientists	
  can	
  or	
  even	
  should	
  remove	
  
themselves	
  from	
  normative	
  questions.	
  	
  Arguments	
  for	
  them	
  to	
  do	
  so	
  are	
  rooted	
  
in	
  the	
  belief	
  of	
  science	
  as	
  objective	
  representation,	
  a	
  hangover	
  from	
  modernity.	
  	
  
In	
  fact,	
  normative	
  statements	
  are	
  bound	
  up	
  in	
  expert	
  statements	
  and	
  advice,	
  and	
  
hence	
  the	
  interpretation	
  of	
  results,	
  by	
  the	
  very	
  process	
  of	
  research	
  selection	
  and	
  
design.85	
  	
  What	
  is	
  required	
  then	
  is	
  contestation,	
  in	
  an	
  open	
  and	
  transparent	
  
manner,	
  alongside	
  democratic	
  participation	
  by	
  lay	
  publics	
  so	
  that	
  trust	
  may	
  be	
  
engendered.86	
  	
  For	
  different	
  types	
  of	
  information,	
  lay	
  and	
  expert,	
  social	
  and	
  
scientific,	
  serve	
  to	
  co-­‐construct	
  our	
  understanding	
  of	
  issues	
  such	
  as	
  global	
  
warming.87	
  	
  Each	
  must	
  be	
  examined	
  so	
  that	
  legitimacy	
  may	
  be	
  lent	
  to	
  the	
  
decision-­‐making	
  process.	
  

	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  
82	
  Garnaut,	
  ‘The	
  Garnaut	
  Climate	
  Change	
  Review’,	
  p.	
  xix.	
  
83	
  Brown,	
  Science	
  in	
  Democracy,	
  pp.	
  11-­‐12.	
  
84	
  Turner,	
  Liberal	
  Democracy	
  3.0,	
  p.	
  4.	
  
85	
  Munnichs,	
  ‘Whom	
  to	
  Trust?’,	
  pp.	
  118-­‐119.	
  
86	
  Ibid,	
  pp.	
  121-­‐124.	
  
87	
  Jacquelin	
  Burgess	
  et	
  al.,	
  ‘Global	
  Warming	
  in	
  the	
  Public	
  Sphere’,	
  p.	
  2767.	
  




	
                                                                                                                                                                                                                                 17	
  
 
                   Contestation	
  here	
  is	
  not	
  taken	
  to	
  mean	
  the	
  overrepresentation	
  of	
  
countervailing	
  opinions	
  in	
  the	
  news	
  media.	
  	
  Superficial	
  questioning	
  of	
  this	
  kind	
  
does	
  not	
  result	
  in	
  a	
  more	
  informed	
  and	
  critically	
  aware	
  polity,	
  nor	
  does	
  it	
  add	
  to	
  
the	
  content	
  of	
  expertise.	
  	
  This	
  is	
  especially	
  the	
  case	
  when	
  governments	
  and	
  
interest	
  groups	
  use	
  expertise	
  in	
  ways	
  that	
  serve	
  to	
  constrain	
  debate	
  on	
  the	
  
strengths	
  and	
  weaknesses	
  of	
  scientific	
  knowledge.88	
  	
  Nevertheless,	
  lay	
  
participation,	
  though	
  seen	
  by	
  many	
  to	
  allow	
  irrational	
  responses	
  to	
  risk	
  issues,	
  
can	
  lead	
  to	
  the	
  inclusion	
  of	
  wider	
  perspectives	
  perhaps	
  not	
  considered	
  by	
  
technical	
  experts.89	
  	
  Indeed,	
  scientific	
  knowledge,	
  while	
  valuable,	
  is	
  incomplete	
  
especially	
  as	
  regards	
  issues	
  with	
  significant	
  normative	
  implications.	
  	
  It	
  can	
  help	
  
explain	
  if	
  and	
  why	
  a	
  relationship	
  exists,	
  but	
  is	
  not	
  in	
  a	
  position	
  to	
  answer	
  what	
  
‘ought’	
  to	
  be	
  done	
  about	
  it	
  in	
  the	
  moral	
  and	
  ethical	
  sense,	
  which	
  is	
  the	
  domain	
  of	
  
democratic	
  decision-­‐making.90	
  	
  As	
  important	
  is	
  the	
  legitimacy	
  contestation	
  and	
  
public	
  participation	
  lend	
  to	
  expert	
  advice	
  in	
  those	
  processes,	
  through	
  the	
  
democratization	
  of	
  expertise	
  itself.	
  	
  Public	
  participation,	
  which	
  is	
  not	
  aided	
  by	
  
the	
  current	
  form	
  of	
  contestation	
  on	
  this	
  issue,	
  must	
  be	
  encouraged	
  if	
  democracy	
  
and	
  expertise	
  are	
  to	
  be	
  amendable.	
  
	
  
Conclusions	
  
	
  
                   Science	
  and	
  its	
  institutions	
  are	
  in	
  a	
  sense	
  the	
  antithesis	
  of	
  democratic	
  
systems	
  –	
  they	
  are	
  a	
  professionalized	
  elite	
  of	
  expertise,	
  closed	
  to	
  the	
  majority.91	
  	
  
Yet	
  expertise	
  in	
  democracies	
  only	
  encounters	
  problems	
  in	
  certain	
  situations.	
  	
  
Conflict	
  arises	
  in	
  cases	
  where	
  its	
  audience	
  is	
  public,	
  while	
  its	
  funding	
  private,	
  or	
  
when	
  those	
  in	
  public	
  administration	
  accept	
  their	
  knowledge	
  as	
  authoritative.	
  	
  
Hence,	
  the	
  political	
  issue	
  for	
  democracies	
  is	
  not	
  the	
  existence	
  of	
  expertise,	
  but	
  



	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  
88	
  Myanna	
  Lahsen,	
  ‘Technocracy,	
  Democracy,	
  and	
  U.S.	
  Climate	
  Politics:	
  The	
  Need	
  

for	
  Demarcations,’	
  Science,	
  Technology,	
  &	
  Human	
  Values,	
  Vol.	
  30,	
  No.	
  1,	
  2005,	
  pp.	
  
138-­‐139.	
  
89	
  Horlick-­‐Jones	
  et	
  al.,	
  ‘Citizen	
  Engagement’,	
  p.	
  260.	
  
90	
  Avery,	
  ‘Scientific	
  Misconduct’,	
  p.	
  19.	
  
91	
  Salomon,	
  ‘Science,	
  Technology	
  and	
  Democracy’,	
  p.	
  33.	
  




	
                                                                                                                                                                                                                        18	
  
the	
  discretionary	
  use	
  of	
  it	
  in	
  the	
  public	
  sphere.92	
  	
  When	
  opened	
  up	
  to	
  public	
  
scrutiny	
  of	
  its	
  use	
  the	
  conflict	
  between	
  expertise	
  and	
  democracy	
  is	
  less	
  
pronounced.	
  	
  Indeed,	
  the	
  spirit	
  of	
  free	
  inquiry	
  upon	
  which	
  modern	
  science	
  is	
  
based	
  is	
  itself	
  a	
  foundational	
  democratic	
  principal.	
  
	
  
                   In	
  the	
  case	
  of	
  the	
  global	
  warming	
  debate,	
  two	
  effects	
  of	
  the	
  closed	
  nature	
  
of	
  expertise	
  are	
  evident.	
  	
  Firstly,	
  sceptics	
  find	
  debate	
  over	
  method	
  and	
  
uncertainty	
  convenient	
  to	
  their	
  cause,	
  despite	
  their	
  marginal	
  nature.	
  	
  Secondly,	
  
the	
  media,	
  having	
  shifted	
  pseudo-­‐contestation	
  to	
  the	
  public	
  sphere,	
  helps	
  them	
  
in	
  their	
  cause.93	
  	
  As	
  a	
  consequence,	
  there	
  have	
  been	
  policy	
  failures	
  ranging	
  from	
  
the	
  global,	
  such	
  as	
  the	
  Copenhagen	
  negotiations,	
  to	
  the	
  local,	
  such	
  as	
  the	
  
Emissions	
  Trading	
  Scheme	
  (ETS)	
  in	
  Australia.94	
  	
  The	
  reality	
  is	
  that	
  in	
  the	
  face	
  of	
  
environmental	
  risks	
  such	
  as	
  global	
  warming,	
  we	
  are	
  dependent	
  upon	
  technical	
  
expertise.	
  	
  It	
  cannot	
  then	
  be	
  simply	
  eradicated	
  from	
  democracy.	
  	
  In	
  order	
  to	
  
democratize	
  expertise	
  and	
  conduct	
  real	
  evaluations	
  of	
  it,	
  contestation	
  in	
  
decision-­‐making,	
  based	
  upon	
  lay	
  participation	
  and	
  inquiry,	
  needs	
  to	
  be	
  instituted	
  
within	
  democratic	
  forms	
  of	
  governance.	
  
                   	
  
	
  
	
                                                                            	
  




	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  	
  
92	
  Stephen	
  P.	
  Turner,	
  ‘What	
  is	
  the	
  Problem	
  with	
  Experts?,’	
  Social	
  Studies	
  of	
  

Science,	
  Vol.	
  31,	
  No.	
  1,	
  2001,	
  pp.	
  140-­‐141.	
  
93	
  Burgess	
  et	
  al.,	
  ‘Global	
  Warming	
  in	
  the	
  Public	
  Sphere’,	
  p.	
  2751.	
  
94	
  Climate	
  change	
  policy	
  in	
  Australia	
  would	
  be	
  significantly	
  affected	
  particularly	
  

following	
  the	
  failure	
  of	
  the	
  Copenhagen	
  negotiations.	
  	
  After	
  two	
  defeats	
  in	
  the	
  
Australian	
  Senate	
  for	
  the	
  ETS	
  the	
  government	
  of	
  the	
  Australian	
  Labour	
  Party	
  
announced	
  that	
  it	
  would	
  not	
  seen	
  an	
  economy-­‐wide	
  market-­‐based	
  mitigation	
  
program	
  until	
  after	
  2013.	
  	
  Garnaut,	
  What	
  if	
  Mainstream	
  Science	
  if	
  Right?,	
  p.	
  7.	
  


	
                                                                                                                                                                                                                         19	
  
Bibliography	
  
	
  
Primary	
  Sources	
  
	
  
Climate	
  Commission,	
  The	
  Critical	
  Decade:	
  Climate	
  Science,	
  Risks	
  and	
  Responses,	
  
        Canberra,	
  Climate	
  Commission	
  Secretariat,	
  2011,	
  retrieved	
  19	
  June	
  2011,	
  
        available	
  from	
  <http://climatecommission.gov.au/topics/the-­‐critical-­‐
        decade/>.	
  
	
  
International	
  Panel	
  on	
  Climate	
  Change,	
  IPCC	
  Fourth	
  Assessment	
  Report:	
  Climate	
  
        Change	
  2007:	
  Synthesis	
  Report,	
  Cambridge,	
  Cambridge	
  University	
  Press,	
  
        2007,	
  retrieved	
  19	
  June	
  2011,	
  available	
  from	
  <http://www.ipcc.ch	
  
        /publications_	
  and_data/ar4/syr/en/	
  contents.html>.	
  
	
  
Newspaper	
  Articles	
  
	
  
Booker,	
  C.,	
  ‘Climate	
  Change:	
  This	
  is	
  the	
  Worst	
  Scientific	
  Scandal	
  of	
  our	
  
        Generation’,	
  The	
  Telegraph,	
  28	
  November	
  2009,	
  retrieved	
  19	
  June	
  2011	
  
        available	
  from	
  <http://www.telegraph.co.uk/comment/columnists/	
  
        christopherbooker	
  /6679082/Climate-­‐change-­‐this-­‐is-­‐the-­‐worst-­‐scientific-­‐
        scandal-­‐of-­‐our-­‐generation.html>.	
  
	
  
Chandler,	
  J.,	
  ‘When	
  Science	
  is	
  Undone	
  by	
  Fiction’,	
  The	
  Age,	
  June	
  29	
  2011,	
  
        retrieved	
  29	
  June	
  2011,	
  available	
  from	
  <http://www.theage.com.au/	
  
        opinion/politics/when-­‐science-­‐is-­‐undone-­‐by-­‐fiction-­‐20110628-­‐
        1gp26.html>.	
  
	
  
Cook,	
  J.,	
  ‘Half	
  the	
  Truth	
  on	
  Emissions’,	
  The	
  Age,	
  June	
  28	
  2011,	
  retrieved	
  29	
  June	
  
        2011,	
  available	
  from	
  <http://www.theage.com.au/opinion/society-­‐and-­‐
        culture/half-­‐the-­‐truth-­‐on-­‐emissions-­‐20110627-­‐1gne1.html>.	
  
	
  
Hulme,	
  M.,	
  ‘The	
  Year	
  Climate	
  Science	
  was	
  Redefined’,	
  The	
  Guardian,	
  16	
  
        November	
  2010,	
  retrieved	
  19	
  June	
  2011,	
  available	
  


	
                                                                                                                           20	
  
<http://www.guardian.co.uk/	
  environment/2010/nov/15/year-­‐climate-­‐
        science-­‐was-­‐redefined?INTCMP=SRCH>.	
  
	
  
Hulme,	
  M.,	
  ‘The	
  Year	
  Climate	
  Science	
  was	
  Redefined’,	
  The	
  Guardian,	
  16	
  
        November	
  2010,	
  retrieved	
  19	
  June	
  2011,	
  available	
  
        <http://www.guardian.co.uk/environment/2010/nov/15/year-­‐climate-­‐
        science-­‐was-­‐redefined?INTCMP=SRCH>.	
  
	
  
Pearce,	
  F.,	
  ‘How	
  the	
  “Climategate”	
  Scandal	
  is	
  Bogus	
  and	
  Based	
  on	
  Climate	
  
        Sceptics’	
  Lies’,	
  The	
  Guardian,	
  2	
  February	
  2010,	
  p.	
  7,	
  retrieved	
  19	
  June	
  2011,	
  
        available	
  from	
  <http://www.guardian.co.uk/environment/2010/feb/01/	
  
        climate-­‐emails-­‐sceptics>.	
  	
  	
  
	
  
Secondary	
  Sources	
  
	
  
Anderson,	
  A.	
  Media,	
  Culture	
  and	
  the	
  Environment,	
  London,	
  UCL	
  Press,	
  1997.	
  
	
  
Avery,	
  G.	
  H.,	
  ‘Scientific	
  Misconduct:	
  The	
  Perversion	
  of	
  Scientific	
  Evidence	
  for	
  
        Public	
  Advocacy’,	
  World	
  Medical	
  &	
  Health	
  Policy,	
  Vol.	
  2,	
  No.	
  4,	
  pp.	
  17-­‐31.	
  
	
  
Beck,	
  Ü.,	
  Risk	
  Society:	
  Towards	
  a	
  New	
  Modernity,	
  London,	
  SAGE	
  Publications,	
  
        1992.	
  
	
  
Beck,	
  Ü.,	
  Ecological	
  Enlightenment:	
  Essays	
  on	
  the	
  Politics	
  of	
  the	
  Risk	
  Society,	
  
        Atlantic	
  Highlands,	
  Humanities	
  Press,	
  1995.	
  
	
  
Beck,	
  Ü.,	
  Ecological	
  Politics	
  in	
  an	
  Age	
  of	
  Risk,	
  Cambridge,	
  Polity	
  Press,	
  1995.	
  
	
  
Beck,	
  Ü.	
  et	
  al.,	
  Reflexive	
  Modernization:	
  Politics,	
  Tradition	
  and	
  Aesthetics	
  in	
  the	
  
        Modern	
  Social	
  Order,	
  Cambridge,	
  Polity	
  Press,	
  1994.	
  
	
  
Bennett,	
  W.	
  L.	
  and	
  Entman,	
  R.	
  M.	
  (eds.),	
  Mediated	
  Politics:	
  Communication	
  in	
  the	
  
        Future	
  of	
  Democracy,	
  New	
  York,	
  Cambridge	
  University	
  Press,	
  2001.	
  


	
                                                                                                                             21	
  
 
Blok,	
  A.,	
  ‘Experts	
  on	
  Public	
  Trial:	
  On	
  Democratizing	
  Expertise	
  Through	
  a	
  Danish	
  
        Consensus	
  Conference’,	
  Public	
  Understandings	
  of	
  Science,	
  Vol.	
  16,	
  2007,	
  pp.	
  
        163-­‐182.	
  
	
  
Boehmer-­‐Christiansen,	
  S.	
  A.,	
  ‘Britain	
  and	
  the	
  International	
  Panel	
  on	
  Climate	
  
        Change:	
  The	
  Impacts	
  of	
  Scientific	
  Advice	
  on	
  Global	
  Warming	
  Part	
  1:	
  
        Integrated	
  Policy	
  Analysis	
  and	
  the	
  Global	
  Dimension’,	
  Environmental	
  
        Politics,	
  Vol.	
  4,	
  No.	
  1,	
  1995,	
  pp.	
  1-­‐18.	
  
	
  
Brown,	
  M.	
  B.,	
  Science	
  in	
  Democracy:	
  Expertise,	
  Institutions,	
  and	
  Representation,	
  
        London,	
  MIT	
  Press,	
  2009.	
  
	
  
Burgess,	
  J.	
  et	
  al.,	
  ‘Global	
  Warming	
  in	
  the	
  Public	
  Sphere,’	
  Philosophical	
  
        Transactions:	
  Mathematical,	
  Physical	
  and	
  Engineering	
  Sciences,	
  Vol.	
  365,	
  No.	
  
        1860,	
  2007,	
  pp.	
  2741-­‐2776.	
  
	
  
Cerutti,	
  F.,	
  Global	
  Challenges	
  for	
  Leviathan:	
  A	
  Political	
  Philosophy	
  of	
  Nuclear	
  
        Weapons	
  and	
  Global	
  Warming,	
  Lanham,	
  Lexington	
  Books,	
  2007.	
  
	
  
Cozzens,	
  S.	
  E.	
  and	
  Woodhouse,	
  E.	
  J.,	
  ‘Science,	
  Government,	
  and	
  the	
  Politics	
  of	
  
        Knowledge,’	
  in	
  S.	
  Jasanoff	
  et	
  al.	
  (eds.),	
  Handbook	
  of	
  Science	
  and	
  Technology	
  
        Studies,	
  Thousand	
  Oaks,	
  SAGE	
  Publications,	
  1995,	
  pp.	
  533-­‐553.	
  
	
  
Deane-­‐Drummond,	
  C.,	
  ‘A	
  Case	
  for	
  Collective	
  Conscience:	
  Climate	
  Gate,	
  COP-­‐15	
  
        and	
  Climate	
  Justice’,	
  Studies	
  in	
  Christian	
  Ethics,	
  Vol.	
  24,	
  No.	
  1,	
  2011,	
  pp.	
  5-­‐22.	
  
	
  
Drori,	
  G.	
  S.	
  et	
  al.,	
  Science	
  in	
  the	
  Modern	
  World	
  Polity:	
  Institutionalization	
  and	
  
        Globalization,	
  Stanford,	
  Stanford	
  University	
  Press,	
  2003.	
  
	
  
Golding,	
  D.	
  et	
  al.,	
  ‘Risk,	
  Trust	
  and	
  Democratic	
  Theory’,	
  in	
  G.	
  Cvetkovich	
  and	
  R.	
  E.	
  
        Löfstedt	
  (eds.),	
  Social	
  Trust	
  and	
  the	
  Management	
  of	
  Risk,	
  London,	
  Earthscan,	
  
        1999,	
  pp.	
  22-­‐41.	
  


	
                                                                                                                               22	
  
 
Edwards,	
  P.	
  N.,	
  ‘Representing	
  the	
  Global	
  Atmosphere:	
  Computer	
  Models,	
  Data,	
  
        and	
  Knowledge	
  about	
  Climate	
  Change’,	
  in	
  P.	
  N.	
  Edwards	
  and	
  C.	
  A.	
  Miller	
  
        (eds.),	
  Changing	
  the	
  Atmosphere:	
  Expert	
  Knowledge	
  and	
  Environmental	
  
        Governance,	
  Cambridge,	
  MIT	
  Press,	
  2001,	
  pp.	
  31-­‐66.	
  
	
  
Edwards,	
  P.	
  N.	
  and	
  Miller,	
  C.	
  A.,	
  ‘Introduction:	
  The	
  Globalization	
  of	
  Climate	
  
        Science	
  and	
  Climate	
  Politics,’	
  in	
  P.	
  N.	
  Edwards	
  and	
  C.	
  A.	
  Miller	
  (eds.),	
  
        Changing	
  the	
  Atmosphere:	
  Expert	
  Knowledge	
  and	
  Environmental	
  Governance,	
  
        Cambridge,	
  MIT	
  Press,	
  2001,	
  pp.	
  1-­‐31.	
  
	
  
Edwards	
  P.	
  N.	
  and	
  Schneider,	
  S.	
  H.	
  ‘Self-­‐Governance	
  and	
  Peer	
  Review	
  in	
  Science-­‐
        for-­‐policy:	
  The	
  Case	
  of	
  the	
  IPCC	
  Second	
  Assessment	
  Report,’	
  in	
  P.	
  N.	
  
        Edwards	
  and	
  C.	
  A.	
  Miller	
  (eds.),	
  Changing	
  the	
  Atmosphere:	
  Expert	
  
        Knowledge	
  and	
  Environmental	
  Governance,	
  Cambridge,	
  MIT	
  Press,	
  2001,	
  pp.	
  
        219-­‐246.	
  
	
  
Evans	
  R.	
  and	
  Plows,	
  A.,	
  ‘Listening	
  without	
  Prejudice?:	
  Re-­‐discovering	
  the	
  Value	
  of	
  
        the	
  Disinterested	
  Citizen,’	
  Social	
  Studies	
  of	
  Science,	
  Vol.	
  37,	
  No.	
  6,	
  2007,	
  pp.	
  
        827-­‐853.	
  
	
  
Evetts,	
  J.	
  et	
  al.,	
  ‘Professionalization,	
  Scientific	
  Expertise,	
  and	
  Elitism:	
  A	
  
        Sociological	
  Perspective,’	
  in	
  N.	
  Charness	
  et	
  al.	
  (eds.),	
  The	
  Cambridge	
  
        Handbook	
  of	
  Expertise	
  and	
  Expert	
  Performance,	
  Cambridge,	
  Cambridge	
  
        University	
  Press,	
  2006,	
  pp.	
  105-­‐123.	
  
	
  
Ferris,	
  T.,	
  The	
  Science	
  of	
  Liberty:	
  Democracy,	
  Reason,	
  and	
  the	
  Laws	
  of	
  Nature,	
  New	
  
        York,	
  Harper,	
  2010.	
  
	
  
Fielding,	
  R.,	
  ‘The	
  Perversion	
  of	
  Scientific	
  Evidence	
  for	
  Policy	
  Advocacy:	
  A	
  
        Perspective	
  on	
  Avery	
  2010’,	
  World	
  Medical	
  &	
  Health	
  Policy,	
  Vol.	
  3,	
  No.	
  1,	
  
        2011,	
  pp.	
  1-­‐4.	
  
	
  


	
                                                                                                                           23	
  
Democracy and Expertise: Lessons from the Debate over Global Warming
Democracy and Expertise: Lessons from the Debate over Global Warming
Democracy and Expertise: Lessons from the Debate over Global Warming
Democracy and Expertise: Lessons from the Debate over Global Warming

Weitere ähnliche Inhalte

Was ist angesagt?

Consequences of democratic citizens' policy agenda 2
Consequences of democratic citizens' policy agenda 2Consequences of democratic citizens' policy agenda 2
Consequences of democratic citizens' policy agenda 2jordanlachance
 
Political Science 2 – Comparative Politics - Power Point #1
Political Science 2 – Comparative Politics - Power Point #1Political Science 2 – Comparative Politics - Power Point #1
Political Science 2 – Comparative Politics - Power Point #1John Paul Tabakian
 
AP_Thesis_Using_Indirect_Policy_Feedback_12_26_2012
AP_Thesis_Using_Indirect_Policy_Feedback_12_26_2012AP_Thesis_Using_Indirect_Policy_Feedback_12_26_2012
AP_Thesis_Using_Indirect_Policy_Feedback_12_26_2012Arnab Pal
 
PLCY 340 - UNC-CH 2000 election paper
PLCY 340 - UNC-CH 2000 election paperPLCY 340 - UNC-CH 2000 election paper
PLCY 340 - UNC-CH 2000 election paperZeeshan Haque
 
Understanding the Tipping Point of Urban Conflict: Public Lecture
Understanding the Tipping Point of Urban Conflict: Public Lecture Understanding the Tipping Point of Urban Conflict: Public Lecture
Understanding the Tipping Point of Urban Conflict: Public Lecture Global Development Institute
 
Institutionalizing delay climatic change. Lecturas recomendadas Ferran Puig V.
Institutionalizing delay climatic change. Lecturas recomendadas Ferran Puig V. Institutionalizing delay climatic change. Lecturas recomendadas Ferran Puig V.
Institutionalizing delay climatic change. Lecturas recomendadas Ferran Puig V. Ecologistas en Accion
 
Politics, poverty and violent conflicts exploring their
Politics, poverty and violent conflicts exploring theirPolitics, poverty and violent conflicts exploring their
Politics, poverty and violent conflicts exploring theirAlexander Decker
 
Ben Duke - Keele University - European Journal of Interdisciplinary Studies
Ben Duke - Keele University - European Journal of Interdisciplinary StudiesBen Duke - Keele University - European Journal of Interdisciplinary Studies
Ben Duke - Keele University - European Journal of Interdisciplinary StudiesBen Duke
 
Complexity and parsons change
Complexity and parsons changeComplexity and parsons change
Complexity and parsons changeSara Harfoush
 
How Neighborhoods affect Choice and Well-being
How Neighborhoods affect Choice and Well-beingHow Neighborhoods affect Choice and Well-being
How Neighborhoods affect Choice and Well-beingMalte Nyfos Mathiasen
 
The Correlates of Torture
The Correlates of TortureThe Correlates of Torture
The Correlates of TortureKeven Munoz
 
Theories of bureaucratic politics ppt
Theories of bureaucratic politics pptTheories of bureaucratic politics ppt
Theories of bureaucratic politics pptM Edward
 
Revised second presentation grds hari 2014 1
Revised  second  presentation grds hari 2014 1Revised  second  presentation grds hari 2014 1
Revised second presentation grds hari 2014 1Global R & D Services
 

Was ist angesagt? (17)

Consequences of democratic citizens' policy agenda 2
Consequences of democratic citizens' policy agenda 2Consequences of democratic citizens' policy agenda 2
Consequences of democratic citizens' policy agenda 2
 
Political Science 2 – Comparative Politics - Power Point #1
Political Science 2 – Comparative Politics - Power Point #1Political Science 2 – Comparative Politics - Power Point #1
Political Science 2 – Comparative Politics - Power Point #1
 
AP_Thesis_Using_Indirect_Policy_Feedback_12_26_2012
AP_Thesis_Using_Indirect_Policy_Feedback_12_26_2012AP_Thesis_Using_Indirect_Policy_Feedback_12_26_2012
AP_Thesis_Using_Indirect_Policy_Feedback_12_26_2012
 
PLCY 340 - UNC-CH 2000 election paper
PLCY 340 - UNC-CH 2000 election paperPLCY 340 - UNC-CH 2000 election paper
PLCY 340 - UNC-CH 2000 election paper
 
Understanding the Tipping Point of Urban Conflict: Public Lecture
Understanding the Tipping Point of Urban Conflict: Public Lecture Understanding the Tipping Point of Urban Conflict: Public Lecture
Understanding the Tipping Point of Urban Conflict: Public Lecture
 
Institutionalizing delay climatic change. Lecturas recomendadas Ferran Puig V.
Institutionalizing delay climatic change. Lecturas recomendadas Ferran Puig V. Institutionalizing delay climatic change. Lecturas recomendadas Ferran Puig V.
Institutionalizing delay climatic change. Lecturas recomendadas Ferran Puig V.
 
Politics, poverty and violent conflicts exploring their
Politics, poverty and violent conflicts exploring theirPolitics, poverty and violent conflicts exploring their
Politics, poverty and violent conflicts exploring their
 
564 3799-2-pb
564 3799-2-pb564 3799-2-pb
564 3799-2-pb
 
Ben Duke - Keele University - European Journal of Interdisciplinary Studies
Ben Duke - Keele University - European Journal of Interdisciplinary StudiesBen Duke - Keele University - European Journal of Interdisciplinary Studies
Ben Duke - Keele University - European Journal of Interdisciplinary Studies
 
Complexity and parsons change
Complexity and parsons changeComplexity and parsons change
Complexity and parsons change
 
Violent Crime in America
Violent Crime in AmericaViolent Crime in America
Violent Crime in America
 
How Neighborhoods affect Choice and Well-being
How Neighborhoods affect Choice and Well-beingHow Neighborhoods affect Choice and Well-being
How Neighborhoods affect Choice and Well-being
 
The Correlates of Torture
The Correlates of TortureThe Correlates of Torture
The Correlates of Torture
 
Theories of bureaucratic politics ppt
Theories of bureaucratic politics pptTheories of bureaucratic politics ppt
Theories of bureaucratic politics ppt
 
GOVT ESSAY
GOVT ESSAYGOVT ESSAY
GOVT ESSAY
 
05 06+ch+1+jowhell(1)
05 06+ch+1+jowhell(1)05 06+ch+1+jowhell(1)
05 06+ch+1+jowhell(1)
 
Revised second presentation grds hari 2014 1
Revised  second  presentation grds hari 2014 1Revised  second  presentation grds hari 2014 1
Revised second presentation grds hari 2014 1
 

Andere mochten auch

Nanostructured materials controlling biological processes
Nanostructured materials controlling biological processesNanostructured materials controlling biological processes
Nanostructured materials controlling biological processesDiego Herrera
 
How Apple Sidesteps Billions in Taxes
How Apple Sidesteps Billions in TaxesHow Apple Sidesteps Billions in Taxes
How Apple Sidesteps Billions in TaxesLuis Taveras EMBA, MS
 
Si new role for universities
Si new role for universitiesSi new role for universities
Si new role for universitiesFredrik Björk
 
Sales & PLC of Gleevec
Sales & PLC of GleevecSales & PLC of Gleevec
Sales & PLC of GleevecAkshay Saxena
 
Smart parking 2020 vision
Smart parking 2020 vision Smart parking 2020 vision
Smart parking 2020 vision vishal waghmare
 
Publication - RSM India Budget 2016 Key Aspects
Publication   - RSM India Budget 2016 Key AspectsPublication   - RSM India Budget 2016 Key Aspects
Publication - RSM India Budget 2016 Key AspectsRSM India
 
IFRS in India - RSM India publication (pre 2010)
IFRS in India - RSM India publication (pre 2010)IFRS in India - RSM India publication (pre 2010)
IFRS in India - RSM India publication (pre 2010)RSM India
 
Building a new feature with microservice while moving away from monolithic ap...
Building a new feature with microservice while moving away from monolithic ap...Building a new feature with microservice while moving away from monolithic ap...
Building a new feature with microservice while moving away from monolithic ap...Adrien Vaschalde
 

Andere mochten auch (14)

Nanostructured materials controlling biological processes
Nanostructured materials controlling biological processesNanostructured materials controlling biological processes
Nanostructured materials controlling biological processes
 
High School Graduation Rates
High School Graduation Rates High School Graduation Rates
High School Graduation Rates
 
How Apple Sidesteps Billions in Taxes
How Apple Sidesteps Billions in TaxesHow Apple Sidesteps Billions in Taxes
How Apple Sidesteps Billions in Taxes
 
Si new role for universities
Si new role for universitiesSi new role for universities
Si new role for universities
 
Lucy
LucyLucy
Lucy
 
Trabajemos juntos cas
Trabajemos juntos casTrabajemos juntos cas
Trabajemos juntos cas
 
东淫同学
东淫同学东淫同学
东淫同学
 
Sales & PLC of Gleevec
Sales & PLC of GleevecSales & PLC of Gleevec
Sales & PLC of Gleevec
 
chien tranh tien te
chien tranh tien techien tranh tien te
chien tranh tien te
 
Smart parking 2020 vision
Smart parking 2020 vision Smart parking 2020 vision
Smart parking 2020 vision
 
Publication - RSM India Budget 2016 Key Aspects
Publication   - RSM India Budget 2016 Key AspectsPublication   - RSM India Budget 2016 Key Aspects
Publication - RSM India Budget 2016 Key Aspects
 
IFRS in India - RSM India publication (pre 2010)
IFRS in India - RSM India publication (pre 2010)IFRS in India - RSM India publication (pre 2010)
IFRS in India - RSM India publication (pre 2010)
 
Building a new feature with microservice while moving away from monolithic ap...
Building a new feature with microservice while moving away from monolithic ap...Building a new feature with microservice while moving away from monolithic ap...
Building a new feature with microservice while moving away from monolithic ap...
 
EcoHouse
EcoHouseEcoHouse
EcoHouse
 

Ähnlich wie Democracy and Expertise: Lessons from the Debate over Global Warming

Debate on Peace and Political Conflicts, in the era of Globalization and Digi...
Debate on Peace and Political Conflicts, in the era of Globalization and Digi...Debate on Peace and Political Conflicts, in the era of Globalization and Digi...
Debate on Peace and Political Conflicts, in the era of Globalization and Digi...AJHSSR Journal
 
Debate on Political Leadership,in the era of Digital Capitalism
Debate on Political Leadership,in the era of Digital CapitalismDebate on Political Leadership,in the era of Digital Capitalism
Debate on Political Leadership,in the era of Digital CapitalismAJHSSR Journal
 
Leveraging science diplomacy for public good in africa
Leveraging science diplomacy for public good in  africaLeveraging science diplomacy for public good in  africa
Leveraging science diplomacy for public good in africaAbdeslam Badre, PhD
 
Top of FormPresentation Research in the Social SciencesSoc.docx
Top of FormPresentation Research in the Social SciencesSoc.docxTop of FormPresentation Research in the Social SciencesSoc.docx
Top of FormPresentation Research in the Social SciencesSoc.docxedwardmarivel
 
Lectures: Scientists & Advocacy / Models of Science Communication
Lectures: Scientists & Advocacy / Models of Science CommunicationLectures: Scientists & Advocacy / Models of Science Communication
Lectures: Scientists & Advocacy / Models of Science CommunicationMatthew Nisbet
 
Week 2 | PUAD 6289 Research Design
Week 2 | PUAD 6289 Research DesignWeek 2 | PUAD 6289 Research Design
Week 2 | PUAD 6289 Research DesignDavid Carter
 
Responsible innovation and the role of scientific advice in democracy
Responsible innovation and the role of scientific advice in democracyResponsible innovation and the role of scientific advice in democracy
Responsible innovation and the role of scientific advice in democracyFondazione Giannino Bassetti
 
Essay On Land Pollution
Essay On Land PollutionEssay On Land Pollution
Essay On Land PollutionErika Burgos
 
Cultural Contradictions of Scanning in an Evidence-based Policy Environment
Cultural Contradictions of Scanning in an Evidence-based Policy EnvironmentCultural Contradictions of Scanning in an Evidence-based Policy Environment
Cultural Contradictions of Scanning in an Evidence-based Policy EnvironmentWendy Schultz
 
RationalChoicePaper.pdf
RationalChoicePaper.pdfRationalChoicePaper.pdf
RationalChoicePaper.pdfMarieMarie94
 
Public Understanding of Science - Lecture 2 #SciCommLSU
Public Understanding of Science - Lecture 2 #SciCommLSUPublic Understanding of Science - Lecture 2 #SciCommLSU
Public Understanding of Science - Lecture 2 #SciCommLSUPaige Jarreau
 
Day1 Civic Science Lab: Experts in the Policymaking Process & Models of Scien...
Day1 Civic Science Lab: Experts in the Policymaking Process & Models of Scien...Day1 Civic Science Lab: Experts in the Policymaking Process & Models of Scien...
Day1 Civic Science Lab: Experts in the Policymaking Process & Models of Scien...Matthew Nisbet
 
Is Global Warming Man Made Essay.pdf
Is Global Warming Man Made Essay.pdfIs Global Warming Man Made Essay.pdf
Is Global Warming Man Made Essay.pdfJanet Katarezzy
 

Ähnlich wie Democracy and Expertise: Lessons from the Debate over Global Warming (20)

Debate on Peace and Political Conflicts, in the era of Globalization and Digi...
Debate on Peace and Political Conflicts, in the era of Globalization and Digi...Debate on Peace and Political Conflicts, in the era of Globalization and Digi...
Debate on Peace and Political Conflicts, in the era of Globalization and Digi...
 
Debate on Political Leadership,in the era of Digital Capitalism
Debate on Political Leadership,in the era of Digital CapitalismDebate on Political Leadership,in the era of Digital Capitalism
Debate on Political Leadership,in the era of Digital Capitalism
 
Leveraging science diplomacy for public good in africa
Leveraging science diplomacy for public good in  africaLeveraging science diplomacy for public good in  africa
Leveraging science diplomacy for public good in africa
 
Communicating Science to Policymakers
Communicating Science to PolicymakersCommunicating Science to Policymakers
Communicating Science to Policymakers
 
Top of FormPresentation Research in the Social SciencesSoc.docx
Top of FormPresentation Research in the Social SciencesSoc.docxTop of FormPresentation Research in the Social SciencesSoc.docx
Top of FormPresentation Research in the Social SciencesSoc.docx
 
Lectures: Scientists & Advocacy / Models of Science Communication
Lectures: Scientists & Advocacy / Models of Science CommunicationLectures: Scientists & Advocacy / Models of Science Communication
Lectures: Scientists & Advocacy / Models of Science Communication
 
Week 2 | PUAD 6289 Research Design
Week 2 | PUAD 6289 Research DesignWeek 2 | PUAD 6289 Research Design
Week 2 | PUAD 6289 Research Design
 
Responsible innovation and the role of scientific advice in democracy
Responsible innovation and the role of scientific advice in democracyResponsible innovation and the role of scientific advice in democracy
Responsible innovation and the role of scientific advice in democracy
 
Nisbet aaas sept2016
Nisbet aaas sept2016Nisbet aaas sept2016
Nisbet aaas sept2016
 
Essay On Land Pollution
Essay On Land PollutionEssay On Land Pollution
Essay On Land Pollution
 
Delvalle_3300_L8-RP
Delvalle_3300_L8-RPDelvalle_3300_L8-RP
Delvalle_3300_L8-RP
 
Cultural Contradictions of Scanning in an Evidence-based Policy Environment
Cultural Contradictions of Scanning in an Evidence-based Policy EnvironmentCultural Contradictions of Scanning in an Evidence-based Policy Environment
Cultural Contradictions of Scanning in an Evidence-based Policy Environment
 
RationalChoicePaper.pdf
RationalChoicePaper.pdfRationalChoicePaper.pdf
RationalChoicePaper.pdf
 
MP0605 (R)
MP0605 (R)MP0605 (R)
MP0605 (R)
 
David Victor on Climate Change Denialism
David Victor on Climate Change DenialismDavid Victor on Climate Change Denialism
David Victor on Climate Change Denialism
 
WP19_WEB.PDF
WP19_WEB.PDFWP19_WEB.PDF
WP19_WEB.PDF
 
Poster
PosterPoster
Poster
 
Public Understanding of Science - Lecture 2 #SciCommLSU
Public Understanding of Science - Lecture 2 #SciCommLSUPublic Understanding of Science - Lecture 2 #SciCommLSU
Public Understanding of Science - Lecture 2 #SciCommLSU
 
Day1 Civic Science Lab: Experts in the Policymaking Process & Models of Scien...
Day1 Civic Science Lab: Experts in the Policymaking Process & Models of Scien...Day1 Civic Science Lab: Experts in the Policymaking Process & Models of Scien...
Day1 Civic Science Lab: Experts in the Policymaking Process & Models of Scien...
 
Is Global Warming Man Made Essay.pdf
Is Global Warming Man Made Essay.pdfIs Global Warming Man Made Essay.pdf
Is Global Warming Man Made Essay.pdf
 

Democracy and Expertise: Lessons from the Debate over Global Warming

  • 1. Democracy  and  Expertise:  Lessons  from  the  Debate  over   Global  Warming     Whereas  the  role  of  the  technical  expert  in  democratic  decision-­‐making   was  formerly  seen  to  be  the  provision  of  disinterested  advice  for  use  in  policy   formulation,  their  capacity  in  this  regard  is  increasingly  under  question.    Many   argue  that  expertise  is  in  fact  vulnerable  to  politicization  for  self-­‐serving  ends,   due  in  part  to  the  unachievable  nature  of  objectivity,  and  hence  not  as  infallible   as  was  once  thought.    Science  is  now  often  viewed  as  ‘politics  by  other  means’.1     As  a  result  technical  knowledge  is  increasingly  being  contested  in  the  public   sphere,  by  expert  and  lay  groups  alike.2    This  paper  will  address  the  extent  to   which  this  contestation  either  enhances  or  hinders  democratic  governance.     In  order  to  address  this  issue  I  will  be  investigating  the  debate   surrounding  anthropogenic  climate  change.    Despite  the  apparent  consensus  on   its  existence  and  human  causes,  this  issue,  and  the  adequacy  of  scientific   expertise  surrounding  it,  has  been  hotly  contested  in  recent  years.3    I  will  seek  to   analyse  the  nature  of  this  contestation,  its  implications  for  the  formulation  of   climate  change  policy,  and  for  the  conflict  between  expertise  and  democracy.     From  this  discussion,  I  will  suggest  ways  in  which  this  conflict  can  be  nullified.     Initially  though,  I  shall  begin  with  an  investigation  of  expertise  and  its  place  in   democracy.     Expertise  and  Democracy     The  use  of  scientific  expertise  in  democratic  decision-­‐making  has,   throughout  the  modern  period,  been  governed  by  the  ideal  of  neutrality.    Under   this  traditional  (Western)  model,  scientific  experts  are  presumed  detached  from                                                                                                                   1  Bruno  Latour,  quoted  in  Mark  B.  Brown,  Science  in  Democracy:  Expertise,   Institutions,  and  Representation,  London,  MIT  Press,  2009,  p.  185.   2  Ibid,  pp.  2-­‐3.   3  Jacquelin  Burgess,  et  al.,  ‘Global  Warming  in  the  Public  Sphere,’  Philosophical   Transactions:  Mathematical,  Physical  and  Engineering  Sciences,  Vol.  365,  No.  1860,   2007,  2751.     1  
  • 2. the  political,  social  and  cultural  processes  underlying  the  societies  which  they   inhabit  such  that  they  may  provide  objective  and  value  neutral  advice  to  political   representatives.    Consequently,  while  part  of  the  political  process,  experts  and   expert  advice  are  deemed  apolitical.4    The  authority  of  their  advice,  and  hence   their  legitimacy  within  the  democratic  system,  is  premised  on  the  supposed   attainability  of  scientific  certainty  through  the  use  of  the  scientific  method.5    This   image  of  the  expert  as  the  disinterested  and  authoritative  arbiter  has,  however,   been  challenged  since  the  mid  twentieth-­‐century  by  the  growing  awareness  of   limits  to  expert  knowledge,  and  the  perception  that  bias  and  special  interests  are   influencing  the  conduct  of  scientific  knowledge  generation.6    The  very  public   nature  of  contestation  and  controversy  in  scientific  discourse,  such  as  that   witnessed  during  the  global  warming  debate  is,  at  least  in  part,  responsible  for   this  reformulation.    For  rather  than  expertise  ‘speaking  truth  to  power’,  scientific   experts  are  often  viewed  as  an  interest  group  like  any  other.7     It  is  indeed  the  case  that  research,  from  which  expert  knowledge  and   advice  is  generated,  is  to  a  large  degree  directed  by  government  and  commercial   funding.    Often  dependent  upon  external  sources  for  funding  streams,  expert   bodies  are  rarely  in  total  control  of  their  research  programs.8    For  example,  the   use  by  Western  governments  of  mechanisms  such  as  tax  credits  and  favourable                                                                                                                   4  Brown,  Science  in  Democracy,  pp.  9-­‐10.   5  I  take  ‘scientific  method’  to  indicate  inquiry  based  upon  the  gathering  of   empirical  data  and  testing  of  hypotheses,  both  through  the  use  of  reason  and   instrumental  rationality.    Raphael  Sassower,  Knowledge  without  Expertise:  On  the   Status  of  Scientists,  Albany,  State  University  of  New  York  Press,  1993,  p.  69.   6  Brian  Martin  and  Eveleen  Richards,  ‘Scientific  Knowledge,  Controversy,  and   Public  Decision  Making,’  in  Sheila  Jasanoff  et  al.  (eds.),  Handbook  of  Science  and   Technology  Studies,  Thousand  Oaks,  SAGE  Publications,  1995,  pp.  506-­‐507.   7  Clark  A.  Miller,  ‘Challenges  in  the  Application  of  Science  to  Global  Affairs:   Contingency,  Trust,  and  Moral  Order,’  in  Paul  N.  Edwards  and  Clark  A.  Miller   (eds.),  Changing  the  Atmosphere:  Expert  Knowledge  and  Environmental   Governance,  Cambridge,  MIT  Press,  2001,  p.  278.    For  an  example  of  this  line  of   argument  see  S.  A.  Boehmer-­‐Christiansen,  ‘Britain  and  the  International  Panel  on   Climate  Change:  The  Impacts  of  Scientific  Advice  on  Global  Warming  Part  1:   Integrated  Policy  Analysis  and  the  Global  Dimension’,  Environmental  Politics,  Vol.   4,  No.  1,  1995,  pp.  15-­‐16.   8  Roy  Macleod,  ‘Science  and  Democracy:  Historical  Reflections  on  Present   Discontents,’  Minerva,  Vol.  35,  1997,  p.  374.     2  
  • 3. patent  policies,  coupled  with  commercial  sector  funding  of  industrial  labs,  has   helped  guide  scientific  research  towards  profit-­‐orientated  applications.9    Experts,   moreover,  are  now  often  in  the  employ  of  governments,  advocacy  groups,  NGOs,   and  commercial  entities,  which  seek  to  use  the  authority  of  expertise  to  garner   support  for  their  particular  policy  goals.10    Such  activity  undermines  the  ‘truth  to   power’  model,  and  its  assumption  of  a  linear  relationship  between  neutral   scientific  knowledge  and  its  subsequent  use  in  policy  formulation,  by  appearing   to  align  expertise  with  particular  interest  groups.11         This  realisation  of  the  political  usage  of  scientific  expertise  has  been   accompanied  by  an  appreciation  of  the  political  nature  of  scientific  knowledge   itself.    Instead  of  such  knowledge  being  seen  as  an  objective  representation  of   nature,  or  verifiable  truth,  it  is  now  widely  understood  to  involve  the  negotiated   outcome  of  interactions  between  experts  and  the  outside  world.12    These   interactions  are  necessarily  affected  by  social,  cultural,  and  political  concerns,   which  in  turn  influence  the  content  of  those  engagements.13    Manifested  in  the   laying  down  of  assumptions,  and  the  interpretation  of  uncertainties,  these   interactions  can  result  in  very  different  representations  of  nature,  in  what  is   ultimately  a  human  and  constrained  exercise.14    Nonetheless,  the  authority   granted  to  scientific  expertise  in  contemporary  democratic  decision-­‐making   continues  to  be  grounded  in  ideals  of  ethical  and  value  neutrality.15    Scientists   are  thus  expected  to  be  infallible,  removed  from  the  sphere  of  moral  or  political                                                                                                                   9  Brown,  Science  in  Democracy,  pp.  10-­‐11.   10  Alan  Irwin,  Citizen  Science:  A  Study  of  People,  Expertise,  and  Sustainable   Development,  London,  Routledge,  1995,  p.  9.   11  Esther  Turnhout,  ‘Heads  in  the  Clouds:  Knowledge  Democracy  as  a  Utopian   Dream,’  in  Roeland  J.  in  ‘t  Veld  (ed.)  Knowledge  Democracy:  Consequences  for   Science,  Politics,  and  Media,  Heidelberg,  Springer,  2010,  pp.  25-­‐26.   12  Susan  E.  Cozzens  and  Edward  J.  Woodhouse,  ‘Science,  Government,  and  the   Politics  of  Knowledge,’  in  Sheila  Jasanoff  et  al.  (eds.),  Handbook  of  Science  and   Technology  Studies,  Thousand  Oaks,  SAGE  Publications,  1995,  pp.  533-­‐534.   13  This  process  is  similar  in  operation  to  democratic  representation,  which  rather   than  being  a  mirror  for  the  pre-­‐existing  reality  of  popular  will,  is  a  negotiated   outcome  conducted  by  correspondence.    Brown,  Science  in  Democracy,  p.  5-­‐8.   14  Irwin,  Citizen  Science,  p.  49.  Brown  5-­‐7   15  Frank  Fischer,  Technocracy  and  the  Politics  of  Expertise,  Newbury  Park,  SAGE   Publications,  1990,  p.  146.     3  
  • 4. judgement.16    This  is  even  the  case  when  the  area  under  investigation  is  one  of   vital  human  interest,  as  it  is  with  the  threat  of  global  warming.    Unwilling  to   ‘confront  the  politics  of  knowledge’,  the  ideal  of  value  neutral  scientific  expertise   stubbornly  persists  in  Western  democracies.17     This  is  perhaps  not  surprising,  given  that  the  ideal  itself  is  deeply   grounded  in  the  modernist  project.    From  the  sixteenth  to  the  nineteenth   centuries,  our  social  and  political  processes  were  moulded  by  the   institutionalization  of  what  Max  Weber  identified  as  the  application  of  reason   and  instrumental  rationality  to  everyday  society  by  way  of  the  scientific  method.     The  very  functioning  of  democratic  forms  of  governance  was  justified  upon  the   use  of  this  ‘higher’  form  of  knowledge.18    Yet  as  science  shifted  out  of  the  private   sphere  and  into  the  public  and  institutional  during  the  nineteenth-­‐century,  the   professionalization  and  standardization  of  scientific  practice  led  to  a  necessary   restriction  of  access  to  knowledge  generation.    The  ‘scientist’  progressively   moved  away  from  the  Enlightenment  ideal  of  the  ‘cultivated  scholar’,  and   towards  the  emerging  specialized  expert.19    With  forms  of  knowing  grounded  in   scientific  method  already  privileged  over  all  other  forms,  this  process  created  an   implicit  elitism  within  supposedly  democratic  systems.20    As  access  to  expertise   receded  further  with  the  emergence  of  formalized  communication  systems  and   the  use  of  esoteric  language,  claims  to  objectivity  and  neutrality  allowed  experts   a  certain  level  of  cultural  and  social  authority.21    This  process  above  all  ran                                                                                                                   16  Jean-­‐Jacques  Salomon,  ‘Science,  Technology  and  Democracy,’  Minerva,  Vol.  38,   2000,  p.  37.   17  Robert  Proctor,  Value-­‐free  Science?:  Purity  and  Power  in  Modern  Knowledge,   Cambridge,  Harvard  University  Press,  1991,  p.  267.   18  Fischer,  Technocracy  and  the  Politics  of  Expertise,  pp.  61-­‐63.   19  Proctor,  Value-­‐free  Science?,  p.  264.   20  Indeed,  the  outward  commitment  to  universal  education  did  little  to  the   growth  of  elitism,  as  increased  specialization  dimmed  the  utopian  dream  of  a   fully  informed  polity.    Macleod,  ‘Science  and  Democracy’,  pp.  372-­‐374.       21  Of  course,  boundaries  of  this  kind  are  constructed  partly  to  secure  scientific   knowledge  against  degradation  by  inferior  forms,  but  also  to  secure  authority  in   the  wider  social  realm,  legitimating  claims  to  it  within  the  system.    Julia  Evetts,   ‘Professionalization,  Scientific  Expertise,  and  Elitism:  A  Sociological  Perspective,’   in  Neil  Charness  et  al.  (eds.),  The  Cambridge  Handbook  of  Expertise  and  Expert   Performance,  Cambridge,  Cambridge  University  Press,  2006,  p.  115.     4  
  • 5. counter  to  the  democratic  ideals  of  inclusion  and  equal  rights,  narrowing  the   scope  for  public  participation,  and  undermining  the  democratic  governance   scientific  knowledge  was  presumed  to  maintain.     Despite  this  apparent  conflict  between  scientific  expertise  and  democracy,   the  former’s  institutionalization  within  decision-­‐making  grew  exponentially   during  the  twentieth-­‐century.    Partly  this  can  be  seen  as  a  reaction  to  the   ostensible  success  of  applied  science  during  the  destruction  of  World  War  I  and   II,  which  seemed  to  show  that  democracy  without  science  is  both  ‘inefficient  and   vulnerable’  in  the  face  of  encroachment  by  aggressive  authoritarianism.22    Of  no   less  importance,  however,  was  the  desire  to  usurp  the  influence  of  patronage   politics;  through  the  use  of  disinterested  policies  based  upon  scientific  method   and  rationality  such  political  expediency  would  be  undermined.    The  emergence   of  ‘think  tanks’  and  their  ever-­‐increasing  influence  within  policy  formulation  is   indicative  of  this  trend  towards  the  ‘scientization’  of  politics.23       Nico  Stehr  argues  that  the  growth  of  expert  influence  in  political  systems,   and  the  ‘scientization’  of  politics,  can  be  seen  as  part  of  the  emergence  of  the   ‘knowledge  society’.    Manifested  in  the  penetration  of  scientific  and  technical   understanding  into  the  core  of  the  economy,  social  action,  and  politics  itself,  this   ‘post-­‐industrial  society’  ascribes  value  and  power  to  the  guardianship  of   knowledge.24    As  a  result  of  this  shift  from  material  to  information  value,  the  old   interest-­‐based  politics  is  replaced  by  governance  systems  directed  towards  the                                                                                                                   22  Macleod,  ‘Science  and  Democracy’,  pp.  375-­‐377.   23  Arguably  though,  policy  choice  is  no  clearer  than  before,  largely  due  to  the   plethora  of  (often  contradictory)  studies  advocating  every  position  on  every   conceivable  issue,  all  backed  by  scientific  expertise.    Andrew  M.  Rich,  Think   Tanks,  Public  Policy,  and  the  Politics  of  Expertise,  Cambridge,  Cambridge   University  Press,  2004,  pp.  2-­‐4.    The  public,  moreover,  has  rightly  come  to  view   think  tanks  as  bastions  of  ideology  rather  than  disinterested  fact,  a  belief  that   seriously  undermines  trust  in  their  ‘expert’  advice  amongst  lay  audiences.    Ibid,   pp.  25-­‐6.   24  Nico  Stehr,  Knowledge  Societies,  London,  SAGE  Publications,  1994,  pp.  1-­‐15.     This  is  not  to  say,  however,  that  experts  can  be  thought  of  as  a  social  class,  being   merely  members  of  loose  associations.    Indeed,  while  they  have  power  in  the   elite  institutions  that  generate  knowledge,  they  have  only  influence  outside  of   them.    Ibid,  pp.  167-­‐168.     5  
  • 6. identification  of  social  policy  ‘problems’,  with  feasibility  studies  and  apolitical   decision-­‐making  determining  the  scope  of  policy  choice.    Little  room  is  left  for   public  opinion  and  citizen  participation,  both  of  which  are  viewed  as  inferior,   even  irrational,  forms  of  policy  input.25       There  has  certainly  been  an  identifiable  shift  towards  ‘scientific’  decision-­‐ making  in  Western  democracies  over  the  course  of  the  last  century.    Responding   to  concerns  that  policymaking  is  being  negatively  affected  by  the  vagaries  of  an   irrational  political  process,  political  and  administrative  leaders  have   progressively  institutionalized  technocracies  in  supposedly  democratic   countries.26      Following  Frank  Fisher,  this  system  of  governance  can  be  defined   as  one  in  which  ‘technically  trained  experts  rule  by  virtue  of  their  specialized   knowledge  and  position  in  dominant  political  and  economic  institutions’.27    As   Jürgen  Habermas  has  argued  elsewhere,  this  reduction  of  political  power  into   rational  administration  can  occur  only  at  the  expense  of  democracy  itself.28    For   not  only  are  the  public  excluded  from  decision-­‐making,  but  the  traditional  role  of   their  political  representatives  in  democratic  systems  is  given  over  to   ‘administratively  based  cadres  of  policy  experts’,  who  determine  the  direction  of   economic  and  social  policy.29       At  the  same  time  we  have  become  reliant  on  scientific  expertise.    For   despite  growing  evidence  of  lay  disenchantment  with  the  functioning  of   expertise  in  democratic  governance,  society  must  still  defer  to  expert  authority   on  issues  ranging  from  the  mundane  to  the  infinitely  complex.30    As  Dietrich   Rueschemeyer  argues  in  relation  to  experts:                                                                                                                     25  Fischer,  Technocracy  and  the  Politics  of  Expertise,  pp.  15-­‐16.   26  Ibid,  p.  21.   27  Ibid,  p.  17.   28  Jürgen  Habermas,  Toward  a  Rational  Society:  Student  Protest,  Science,  and   Politics,  London,  Heinemann  Educational,  1971,  p.  68.   29  Fischer,  Technocracy  and  the  Politics  of  Expertise,  pp.  18-­‐19.   30  Stehr,  Knowledge  Societies,  pp.  163-­‐165.     6  
  • 7. [T]hey  define  the  situation  for  the  untutored,  they  suggest  priorities,  they   shape  people’s  outlook  on  their  life  and  world,  and  they  establish   standards  of  judgement  in  the  different  areas  of  expertise.31     Simply  put,  experts  are  those  adjudged  the  most  competent  in  answering   questions  related  to  their  specific  area  of  expertise.    Non-­‐experts,  or  the  lay   public,  are  at  best  unqualified  and  external  reviewers  ensuring  that  only  other   experts  in  their  field  can  truly  judge  the  adequacy  of  advice,  thereby  insulating   them  from  radical  external  criticism  of  their  results.32    Knowledge  becomes  the   domain  of  the  elite,  and  one  in  which  the  general  public  is  excluded.    This   presents  a  further  problem  for  democracy,  when  defined  as  ‘government  by   discussion’,  because  the  discussion  itself  is  unintelligible  and  out  of  reach  for  the   majority.33     Here  we  can  find  Robert  Dahl’s  conception  of  the  democratic  ideal  useful   in  better  understanding  the  significance  of  this  problem.    Dahl  defines  the  ideal   democracy  as  one  that  ensures  the  equal  empowerment  of  all,  meaning  that  even   if  not  directly  participating  in  all  decisions,  no  citizen  should  be  specifically   excluded  from  doing  so.    As  the  above  discussion  indicates,  however,  modern   democracies  are  far  removed  from  this  ideal,  as  the  elite  controls  access  to  forms   of  knowledge  used  in  decision-­‐making.    Recognising  this,  Dahl  suggests  a   continuum  of  polyarchy34  based  on  levels  of  democratic  involvement  and   popular  sovereignty.    At  the  lower  end  of  this  continuum  are  those  countries  in   which  the  minimum  of  free  and  fair  elections  is  achieved,  but  where  the  elite   allows  for  little  public  involvement.    At  the  upper  end  is  a  governance  structure   within  which  each  citizen  is  equally  involved  in  the  defining  of  policy  agendas,   and  where  policy  is  created  transparently,  originates  from  numerous  sources,   and  public  deliberation  in  decision-­‐making  is  promoted.    Standing  between  the   lower  and  upper  levels  on  this  continuum  is  the  control  of  information  by  policy                                                                                                                   31  Quoted  in  ibid,  p.  166.   32  Sassower,  Knowledge  without  Expertise,  pp.  64-­‐66.   33  Stephen  P.  Turner,  Liberal  Democracy  3.0:  Civil  Society  in  an  Age  of  Experts,   London,  SAGE  Publications,  2003,  pp.  5-­‐6.   34  Meaning  a  governance  system  in  which  power  is  vested  in  many  actors.     7  
  • 8. elites.35    Thus  Dahl  would  argue  that  expertise,  as  an  elite  bastion  of  knowledge,   lowers  the  level  of  democracy  in  those  countries  in  which  it  forms  the  basis  of   decision-­‐making.     The  Risk  Society     At  the  same  time  as  expertise  has  come  to  undermine  the  legitimate   functioning  of  democratic  governance,  a  crisis  in  confidence  has  beset  the  very   authority  of  that  expertise.    For  Ülrich  Beck,  the  sources  of  this  crisis  are  related   to  what  he  terms  the  ‘risk  society’.    Whereas  during  modernity,  the  belief  in   progress,  truth,  and  the  purity  of  the  scientific  method  dominated,  our  ‘post-­‐ industrial’  society  is  beset  by  doubt  and  anxieties  related  to  environmental   threats.    As  a  result,  uncertainty  and  risk  have  become  central  to  politics,  not   necessarily  due  to  the  discovery  of  new  threats  such  as  global  warming,  but  to   the  recently  developed  understandings  of  the  inherent  limitations  of  science.     Once  thought  of  as  a  vehicle  through  which  domination  of  nature  could  be   achieved,  we  now  distrust  science’s  ability  to  solve  the  problems  that  domination   has  produced.36    On  the  other  hand,  for  Beck,  ‘[t]he  exposure  of  scientific   uncertainty  is  the  liberation  of  politics,  law  and  the  public  sphere  from  their   patronization  by  technocracy’.37    Yet  these  threats,  especially  global  warming,   still  necessitate  by  their  very  nature  a  dependence  upon  expertise  at  the  very   time  of  this  questioning.38    For  expert  bodies,  such  as  the  International  Panel  on   Climate  Change  (IPCC),  are  not  only  intimately  involved  in  the  construction  of   public  perceptions  of  risk,  but  also  in  our  response  to  them,  given  that  the   prevailing  approach  to  decision-­‐making  is  bound  up  in  modernity.39    Indeed,  as                                                                                                                   35  W.  Lance  Bennett  and  Robert  M.  Entman  (eds.),  Mediated  Politics:   Communication  in  the  Future  of  Democracy,  New  York,  Cambridge  University   Press,  2001,  pp.  468-­‐469.   36  Irwin,  Citizen  Science,  pp.  45-­‐46.   37  Quoted  in  ibid,  p.  60.   38  Ülrich  Beck,  Ecological  Politics  in  an  Age  of  Risk,  Cambridge,  Polity  Press,  1995,   p.  161.   39  Geert  Munnichs,  ‘Whom  to  Trust?:    Public  Concerns,  Late  Modern  Risks,  and   Expert  Trustworthiness,’  Journal  of  Agricultural  and  Environmental  Ethics,  Vol.   17,  No.  2,  2004,  p.  114.     8  
  • 9. Beck  himself  points  out,  the  answer  of  industrial  society  to  the  challenge  of  risk   is  to  intensify  technocratic  solutions.40         Arguably  then,  what  is  required  is  the  democratization  of  expertise  itself.     Moves  towards  the  inclusion  of  lay  understandings  of  risk  issues,  with  a  view  to   incorporating  them  within  decision-­‐making  processes,  have  in  fact  begun.41    The   House  of  Lords  in  Britain,  for  instance,  called  for  enhanced  public  involvement  in   scientific  matters  in  2000,  and  the  European  Commission  committed  itself  in   2001  to  ‘sustained  dialogue  between  experts,  public  and  policy  makers’.    In   Scandinavia,  moreover,  the  success  of  expert-­‐citizen  dialogue  models,  pioneered   by  the  Danish  Board  of  Technology,  have  led  to  calls  for  their  adaptation  in  other   Western  democracies.    These  consensus  conferences  between  expert  and  lay   panels  provide  a  platform  for  the  questioning  of  expert  pronouncements  on  both   cognitive  and  normative  grounds.42    Experts  are  thus  forced  to  justify  their   assumptions  as  lay  audiences  search  for  value  judgements  and  the  infiltration  of   special  interests  into  knowledge  generation.    Such  conferences  are  particularly   useful  in  the  context  of  uncertainty  and  controversy,  as  prior  contestation   enhances  the  legitimacy  of  democratic  decisions.43    These  initiatives  are   therefore  gaining  credence  within  public  policy  discourse,  as  they  are  regarded   as  a  means  of  addressing  ‘a  number  of  perceived  sources  of  potential  crisis  in   contemporary  governance;  namely  deficits  of  knowledge,  trust,  and  legitimacy’.44                                                                                                                             40  Beck,  Ecological  Politics,  pp.  166-­‐167   41  Tom  Horlick-­‐Jones  et  al.,  ‘Citizen  Engagement  Processes  as  Information   Systems:  The  Role  of  Knowledge  and  the  Concept  of  Translation  Quality,  Public   Understandings  of  Science,  Vol.  16,  2007,  p.  260.   42  Anders  Blok,  ‘Experts  on  Public  Trial:  On  Democratizing  Expertise  Through  a   Danish  Consensus  Conference’,  Public  Understandings  of  Science,  Vol.  16,  2007,   pp.  163-­‐164.   43  Ibid,  p.  176.   44  Horlick-­‐Jones  et  al.,  ‘Citizen  Engagement’,  p.  259.     9  
  • 10. Epistemic  Communities  and  Climate  Consensus     Given  these  deficits  in  trust  and  legitimacy,  how  can  the  expert  consensus   on  climate  change  and  its  authority  in  decision-­‐making,  be  explained?45    Peter   Haas  developed  the  notion  of  epistemic  communities  as  a  way  of  understanding   how  such  bodies  gain  authority  through  consensus  building  surrounding  their   specific  knowledge.    Following  Adler,  such  communities  can  be  defined  as:     a  network  of  individuals  or  groups  with  an  authoritative  claim  to  policy-­‐ relevant  knowledge  within  their  domain  of  expertise…They  adhere  to  the   following:    (1)    shared  consummatory  values    and  principled  beliefs;  (2)   shared  causal  beliefs  or  professional  judgement;  (3)  common  notions  of   validity  based  on  intersujective  internally  defined  criteria  for  validating   knowledge;  and  (4)  a  common  policy  project.46     Once  consensus  has  been  achieved,  and  epistemic  communities  formed  around  it,   its  members  implant  themselves  within  state  and  international  bureaucracies  in   order  to  affect  policy  decisions.    They  are  thus  well  positioned  to  define  the   content  of  policy  problems,  prescribe  solutions,  and  ultimately  assess  policy   outcomes.47         In  the  case  of  global  warming,  such  a  community  could  arguably  be   located  within  the  body  of  the  IPCC.48    Following  the  above  criteria,  the  IPCC,                                                                                                                   45  Those  subscribing  to  the  expert  consensus  believe  that  we  know  ‘beyond   reasonable  doubt  that  the  world  is  warming  and  that  human  emissions  of   greenhouse  gases  are  the  primary  cause’.    Climate  Commission,  The  Critical   Decade:  Climate  Science,  Risks  and  Responses,  Canberra,  Climate  Commission   Secretariat,  2011,  p.  60,  retrieved  19  June  2011,  available  from   <http://climatecommission.gov.au/topics/the-­‐critical-­‐decade/>.   46  Quoted  in  Matthew  Paterson,  Global  Warming  and  Global  Politics,  New  York,   Routledge,  1996,  p.  135.   47  See  Peter  M.  Haas,  ‘Introduction:  Epistemic  Communities  and  International   Policy  Coordination,’  International  Organization,  Vol.  46,  No.  1,  1992,  pp.  1-­‐35.   48  Many  members  of  the  IPCC  have  been  involved  in  climate  research  since  the   1970s,  and  involved  in  expert  bodies  such  as  the  World  Meteorological   Organization  (WMO)  and  the  United  Nations  Environment  Programme  (UNEP),     10  
  • 11. through  its  four  year  reporting  structure,  periodically  publishes  shared   principled  belief  statements,  despite  regular  admissions  of  uncertainty,49  along   with  casual  judgements  related  to  the  role  of  carbon  dioxide  in  global  warming;50   it  shares  agreed  mechanisms  for  testing  in  the  form  of  climate  modelling;51  and  it   shares  a  common  policy  response  to  the  problem  –  the  drastic  reduction  of   greenhouse  gas  emissions.52    The  IPCC  and  its  predecessors,  moreover,  were   vital  to  the  emergence  of  global  warming  as  an  area  of  significant  policy  concern,   and  to  the  fostering  of  consensus  on  its  nature.53     Yet  it  is  not  clear  that  epistemic  community  frameworks  are  sufficient  to   deal  with  global  warming  for  two  reasons.    Firstly,  the  level  of  consensus  on  the   relationship  between  human  activity  and  warming  is  not  absolute,  with  multiple   communities  claiming  true  knowledge.    The  epistemic  community  approach,   however,  takes  scientific  consensus  as  the  precursor  to  policy  influence,  when  it   is  in  fact  far  more  complex  than  such  a  linear  relationship.54    Consensus,  based   here  upon  a  generally  agreed  set  of  possible  outcomes  rather  than  a  single  and   exact  prediction,  is  reached  through  the  interplay  of  assertion  and  disagreement   both  between  experts,  and  between  experts  and  policymakers.    During  this   process  the  content  of  consensus  can  be  altered  significantly  based  upon  value                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                               as  well  as  the  First  Climate  Change  Conference  and  the  International  Council  of   Scientists.    Paterson,  Global  Warming,  p.  140.   49  In  the  IPCC’s  most  recent  assessment  report,  global  warming  was  described  as   ‘unequivocal’,  and  its  human  sources  as  ‘very  likely’,  despite  uncertainties  in  the   accuracy  of  data  and  the  projections  based  upon  it.    International  Panel  on   Climate  Change,  IPCC  Fourth  Assessment  Report:  Climate  Change  2007:  Synthesis   Report,  Cambridge,  Cambridge  University  Press,  2007,  p.  72,  retrieved  19  June   2011,  available  from  <  http://www.ipcc.ch/publications_and_data/ar4/syr/en/   contents.html>.    It  is  important  to  recognize,  however,  that  the  uncertainty   described,  and  indicated  by  the  phrase  ‘very  likely’,  refers  to  a  90  percent   probability.    Ibid,  p.  27.   50  Ibid,  p.  72.   51  See,  for  example,  ibid,  p.  51-­‐59.   52  Ibid,  p.  60.   53  Paterson,  Global  Warming,  pp.  140-­‐144.    See  ibid,  pp.  144-­‐147,  for  the   evolution  of  the  global  warming  agenda  from  the  1970s  to  the  mid-­‐1990s.   54  Paul  N.  Edwards  and  Clark  A.  Miller,  ‘Introduction:  The  Globalization  of   Climate  Science  and  Climate  Politics,’  in  Paul  N.  Edwards  and  Clark  A.  Miller   (eds.),  Changing  the  Atmosphere:  Expert  Knowledge  and  Environmental   Governance,  Cambridge,  MIT  Press,  2001,  p.  4.     11  
  • 12. judgements  by  actors  external  to  the  epistemic  community,  and  related  to  risk   and  available  resources.55    Secondly,  as  Karen  Liftin  has  argued,  the  approach   tends  to  disregard  the  links  between  science  and  politics,  downplaying  ‘the  ways   in  which  scientific  information  simply  rationalizes  or  reinforces  existing  political   conflicts.56    Indeed,  issues  such  as  global  warming  are  controversial  inasmuch  as   they  involve  ‘ongoing  conflicts  over  basic  values  and  interest.’57    Thus,  different   actors,  each  seeking  particular  policy  goals,  have  manipulated  scientific  expertise   with  their  own  values  and  interests  in  mind  through  the  primary  communication   channel  for  the  lay  public  in  regards  to  global  warming  –  the  media.58     In  the  case  of  global  warming  these  ongoing  political  conflicts  involve   significant  implications  of  a  foundational  nature.    On  the  one  hand,  the  possibility   of  ecological  catastrophe  resulting  from  current  modes  of  human  activity  implies   a  crisis  of  industrial  society  itself,  and  thus  demands  self-­‐reflection  on  its  very   foundations.59    Conflict  here  is  not  being  fought  over  the  spoils  of  profit  and   prosperity,  but  the  allocation  of  negatives,  threats  and  possible  devastation.60  On   the  other  hand,  the  global  warming  debate  has  become  a  space  for  the  possible   reconfiguration  of  the  global  order,  with  institutions  created  on  a  worldwide   scale  to  tackle  it  becoming  sites  of  contestation  over  norms  and  practice.61     Despite  the  importance  of  these  conflicts,  the  debate  is  framed  within  the   Western  media  in  terms  of  science,  rather  than  as  an  investigation  into  the  social   and  cultural  dimensions  of  the  risk  itself.62                                                                                                                     55  Paul  N.  Edwards  and  Stephen  H.  Schneider,  ‘Self-­‐Governance  and  Peer  Review   in  Science-­‐for-­‐policy:  The  Case  of  the  IPCC  Second  Assessment  Report,’  in  Paul  N.   Edwards  and  Clark  A.  Miller  (eds.),  Changing  the  Atmosphere:  Expert  Knowledge   and  Environmental  Governance,  Cambridge,  MIT  Press,  2001,  pp.  244-­‐245   56  Quoted  in  Paterson,  Global  Warming,  p.  150.   57  Brown,  Science  in  Democracy,  pp.  2-­‐3.   58  Alison  Anderson,  Media,  Culture  and  the  Environment,  London,  UCL  Press,  1997,   pp.  107-­‐115.   59  Ülrich  Beck  et  al.,  Reflexive  Modernization:  Politics,  Tradition  and  Aesthetics  in   the  Modern  Social  Order,  Cambridge,  Polity  Press,  1994,  p.  8.   60  Ülrich  Beck,  Ecological  Enlightenment:  Essays  on  the  Politics  of  the  Risk  Society,   Atlantic  Highlands,  Humanities  Press,  1995,  p.  3.   61  Edwards  and  Miller,  ‘Introduction’,  pp.  2-­‐4.   62  Irwin,  Citizen  Science,  p.  37.     12  
  • 13. Indeed,  contestation  in  this  debate  has  generally  taken  place  on  the   nature  of  the  consensus  itself.    For  instance,  the  IPCC’s  Second  Assessment   Report  of  1996,  in  its  eight  chapter,  concluded  that  ‘the  balance  of  evidence   suggests  that  there  is  a  discernible  human  influence  on  global  climate’.     Immediately,  however,  these  claims  were  contested,  especially  on  the  basis  that   human  activity  was  the  root  cause.    Led  by  the  eminent  physicist  Frederick  Seitz,   those  dissenting  claimed  that  the  peer  review  process  had  been  compromised   for  political  reasons,  claims  that  ignited  a  debate  widely  reported  in  the  media.63     Unproven  claims  such  as  Seitz’s  gain  credence  in  the  public  sphere,  and   undermine  trust  in  bodies  such  as  the  IPCC,  regardless  of  the  fact  that  IPCC   publications  are  peer-­‐reviewed  by  hundreds  of  experts  prior  to  release,  a   process  explained  by  the  overrepresentation  of  marginal  views  in  the  media,64   and  by  the  nature  of  climate  science  itself.65    Unfortunately,  due  to  their  technical                                                                                                                   63  Seitz’s  complaints  were  based  on  the  conclusions  contained  in  chapter  eight,   which  he  claimed  had  been  altered  following  the  November  1995  plenary   meeting  of  IPCC  Working  Group  I.    At  this  meeting,  Seitz  claimed,  the  text  of  that   chapter  had  been  agreed  too,  and  the  subsequent  deletion  of  passages  that   indicated  uncertainty  amounted  to  the  corruption  of  peer  review  for  political   ends.    Not  surprisingly  the  IPCC  Secretariat,  who  pointed  to  peer  review  process   undertaken  following  alterations  to  the  text,  dismissed  these  claims.    Edwards   and  Schneider,  ‘Self-­‐Governance  and  Peer  Review’,  p.  219.   64  In  Australia,  for  example,  research  has  shown  that  the  media  is  the  main   source  of  information  on  climate  change,  and  the  main  factor  shaping  people’s   awareness  of  it,  especially  as  regards  uncertainty.    Desley  L.  Speck,  ‘A  Hot  Topic?   Climate  Change  Mitigation  Policies,  Politics,  and  the  Media  in  Australia,’  Human   Ecology  Review,  Vol.  17,  No.  2,  2010,  p.  125.    For  examples  of  the  publication  of   marginal  views  in  the  media  in  Australia,  see  Jo  Chandler,  ‘When  Science  is   Undone  by  Fiction’,  The  Age,  June  29  2011,  retrieved  29  June  2011,  available   from  <http://www.theage.com.au/opinion/politics/when-­‐science-­‐is-­‐undone-­‐by-­‐ fiction-­‐20110628-­‐1gp26.html>;  and  John  Cook,  ‘Half  the  Truth  on  Emissions’,   The  Age,  June  28  2011,  retrieved  29  June  2011,  available  from   <http://www.theage.  com.au/opinion/society-­‐and-­‐culture/half-­‐the-­‐truth-­‐on-­‐ emissions-­‐20110627-­‐1gne1.html>.   65  Climate  science  is  based  upon  modelling  using  ‘semi-­‐empirical  and  heuristic   principles  derived  from  observation’.    These  observations  suffer  from  problems   of  scale  and  availability,  leading  to  inaccurate,  incomplete,  inconsistent  and   temporally  brief  regional  data  sets,  which  are  then  globalized  through   interpolating  and  correcting.    Paul  N.  Edwards,  ‘Representing  the  Global   Atmosphere:  Computer  Models,  Data,  and  Knowledge  about  Climate  Change’,  in  P.   N.  Edwards  and  C.  A.  Miller  (eds.),  Changing  the  Atmosphere:  Expert  Knowledge   and  Environmental  Governance,  Cambridge,  MIT  Press,  2001,  pp.  62-­‐63.    For  a     13  
  • 14. nature,  the  facts  and  data  on  global  warming  do  not  speak  for  themselves,  and   have  to  be  interpreted  and  acted  upon  based  on  expert  advice.66    As  Professor   Ross  Garnaut  has  claimed,  ‘the  outsider  to  climate  science  has  no  rational  choice   but  to  accept  that,  on  a  balance  of  probabilities,  the  mainstream  science  is  right   in  pointing  to  high  risks  from  unmitigated  climate  change’.67    Regardless  of  this   dependence,  sceptics  can  ‘cherry-­‐pick’  details  and  claim  them  as  contrary  to  the   overall  consensus,  thereby  undermining  confidence.68       ‘Climategate’     The  effects  of  contestation  over  the  global  warming  ‘consensus’  are  best   illustrated  by  the  so-­‐called  ‘climategate’  scandal.    On  20  November  2009  hacked   emails,  sent  over  a  15-­‐year  period,  and  originating  from  the  Climate  Research   Unit  (CRU)69  of  the  University  of  East  Anglia,  were  released  publically  on  the   website  realclimate.org.    The  emails,  it  was  claimed,  showed  evidence  of  data   suppression  and  manipulation,  as  well  as  intimidation  of  scientific  journal   editors  in  order  to  prevent  the  publication  of  contrary  opinions,  all  as  part  of  an   effort  to  manufacture  consensus  on  climate  change.70    The  supposed  uncovering   of  such  activity  amounted  to  what  one  climate  change  sceptic,  Christopher   Brooks  of  The  Telegraph,  called  the  ‘worst  scientific  scandal  of  our  generation’.71                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                 good  typology  of  climate  modeling  and  data  collection  see  ibid,  pp.  35-­‐49;  for  a   detailed  overview  of  specific  modeling  methods  see  ibid,  pp.  55-­‐62.   66  Ibid,  pp.  32-­‐33.   67  Ross  Garnaut,  The  Garnaut  Climate  Change  Review:  Final  Report,  Port   Melbourne,  Cambridge  University  Press,  2008,  p.  xcii.   68  Irwin,  Citizen  Science,  pp.  67-­‐68.    See  for  example,  Cook,  ‘Half  the  Truth  on   Emissions’.   69  The  CRU  is  one  of  the  most  influential  scientific  institutions  in  the  field  of   climate  change,  heavily  involved  in  the  collection  of  datasets  and  climate   modelling  used  in  the  IPCC’s  assessment  reports.    Brigitte  Nerlich,  ‘"Climategate":   Paradoxical  Metaphors  and  Political  Paralysis,’  Environmental  Values,  Vol.  19,   2010,  pp.  421-­‐422.   70  For  an  example  of  such  claims  see  George  H.  Avery,  ‘Scientific  Misconduct:  The   Perversion  of  Scientific  Evidence  for  Public  Advocacy’,  World  Medical  &  Health   Policy,  Vol.  2,  No.  4,  2010,  p.  20.   71  Christopher  Booker,  ‘Climate  Change:  This  is  the  Worst  Scientific  Scandal  of   our  Generation’,  The  Telegraph,  28  November  2009,  retrieved  19  June  2011   available  from  <http://www.telegraph.co.uk/comment/columnists/     14  
  • 15. Conservative  bloggers,  moreover,  framed  the  ‘scandal’  as  evidence  of  a  climate   change  ‘scam’,  and  the  scientific  advice  behind  the  consensus  as  untrustworthy.72         Three  independent  panels  would  later  conclude  that  there  was  in  fact  no   evidence  of  misconduct  on  the  part  of  the  scientists.    Yet  media  publicity   surrounding  the  issue  ensured  the  damage  had  been  done.73    Analysis  of  the   emails  themselves  was  never  more  than  perfunctory,  allowing  the  ‘cherry-­‐ picking’  of  seemingly  incriminating  details  to  supress  the  full  story.    By  the  time   of  the  release  of  the  panels’  findings,  the  reputations  of  the  experts  involved  had   already  been  tarnished  and  have  since  struggled  to  recover.74    Brigitte  Nerlich,   who  has  studied  the  reaction  to  the  release  of  the  emails  found  that  even  its   framing  as  ‘climategate’,  with  negative  connotations  of  the  Watergate  scandal   and  political  cover  up,  resonated  ‘with  popular  imagination  and  cultural   knowledge’.    This  process  opened  ‘up  a  whole  narrative  space  or  frame’  which   allowed  ‘people  to  easily  structure  their  arguments  about  a  controversial   topic’.75    Indeed,  regardless  of  the  veracity  of  the  claims,  the  scandal  certainly   served  to  undermine  the  public’s  trust  in  climate  science.    For  example,  in  the   aftermath  of  the  release  of  the  emails,  and  the  failure  of  the  Copenhagen   negotiations  on  global  responses  to  climate  change,  a  British  study  revealed  that   ‘the  proportion  of  adults  who  believe  climate  change  is  “definitely”  a  reality   dropped  by  30%  over  the  last  year,  from  44%  to  31%.’76    The  public  outrage  that                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                               christopherbooker/6679082/Climate-­‐change-­‐this-­‐is-­‐the-­‐worst-­‐scientific-­‐ scandal-­‐of-­‐our-­‐generation.html>.   72  Brigitte  Nerlich,  ‘"Climategate”’,  pp.  421-­‐422.   73  Richard  Fielding,  ‘The  Perversion  of  Scientific  Evidence  for  Policy  Advocacy:  A   Perspective  on  Avery  2010’,  World  Medical  &  Health  Policy,  Vol.  3,  No.  1,  2011,  p.   2.    For  an  example  of  one  of  the  panels  findings  see     74  Fred  Pearce,  ‘How  the  “Climategate”  Scandal  is  Bogus  and  Based  on  Climate   Sceptics’  Lies’,  The  Guardian,  2  February  2010,  p.  7,  retrieved  19  June  2011,   available  from  <http://www.guardian.co.uk/environment/2010/feb/01/   climate-­‐emails-­‐sceptics>.    As  it  cannot  be  undertaken  here,  for  an  in  depth   analysis  of  the  content  of  the  emails,  and  the  phrases  that  led  people  to  believe   that  a  ‘scam’  had  been  uncovered,  see  Celia  Deane-­‐Drummond,  ‘A  Case  for   Collective  Conscience:  Climate  Gate,  COP-­‐15  and  Climate  Justice’,  Studies  in   Christian  Ethics,  Vol.  24,  No.  1,  2011,  p.  8-­‐10.   75  Nerlich,  ‘”Climategate”’,  p.  423.   76  Juliette  Jowit,  ‘Sharp  Decline  in  the  Public’s  Belief  in  Climate  Threat,  British   Poll  Reveals’,  The  Guardian,  24  February  2010,  p.  9,  retrieved  19  June  2011,     15  
  • 16. followed,  however  misplaced,  weakened  pressure  for  political  action  on  a  global   scale,  a  fact  highlighted  by  the  failure  of  Copenhagen,  and  fed  into  debates  over   the  legitimacy  of  scientific  expertise  in  democracies.77         Yet  ‘Climategate’  did  bring  about  several  important  changes  in  the   conduct  of  climate  expertise.    Many  bodies  involved  in  data  collection  moved   towards  the  opening  up  of  datasets  to  public  scrutiny.    It  also  forced  experts  to   acknowledge  that  climate  change  policy  is  not  created  in  a  linear  relationship   between  science  and  decision-­‐making,  but  rather  includes  a  complex  set  of  value   and  interest  inputs  which  must  be  negotiated.78    Nonetheless,  critics  continue  to   claim  that  the  dependence  on  funding  streams,  linked  to  the  political  existence  of   the  threat,  creates  inherent  incentives  for  research  outcomes  to  support  the   significance  of  the  threat  of  global  warming.79    It  is  argued  that  the  consensus  is   garnered  through  the  framing  of  realities  consistent  with  the  scientists’  ethics  in   order  to  convince  the  public  of  their  preferred  policy  actions.    Expertise  here   moves  from  mere  observation  to  outright  advocacy.80         The  case  of  ‘Climategate’  highlights  that  the  global  warming  ‘consensus’  is   in  fact  contested  in  nature.    This  contestation  plays  upon  the  uncertain  nature  of   knowledge  on  this  issue  in  particular,  and  in  scientific  expertise  more  generally.     As  expert  authority  is  based  on  epistemological  certainty,  gathered  through   neutral  observation,  it  is  necessarily  diminished  as  a  result.81    The  established   position  of  the  IPCC  as  an  authority  on  climate  science  suffers  also  as  it  finds   itself  immersed  in  the  crisis  of  trust  and  expert  legitimacy  in  the  public  eye.    As   Garnaut  has  pointed  out,  it  is  ‘public  attitudes  in  Australia  and  in  other  countries                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                               available  from  <http://www.guardian.co.uk/environment/2010/feb/23/british-­‐ public-­‐belief-­‐climate-­‐poll>.   77  Deane-­‐Drummond,  Studies  in  Christian  Ethics,  pp.  8-­‐9.   78  Mark  Hulme,  ‘The  Year  Climate  Science  was  Redefined’,  The  Guardian,  16   November  2010,  retrieved  19  June  2011,  available  <http://www.guardian.co.uk/   environment/2010/nov/15/year-­‐climate-­‐science-­‐was-­‐redefined?INTCMP=   SRCH>.   79  Avery,  ‘Scientific  Misconduct’,  p.  26.   80  Ibid,  pp.  19-­‐20.   81  Indeed,  Karl  Popper  convincingly  argued  the  view  that  without  certainty   expertise  holds  no  authority.    See  Sassower,  Knowledge  without  Expertise,  pp.  67.     16  
  • 17. [that]  create  the  possibility  of  major  reform…despite  the  inherent  difficulty  of   the  policy  problem’.82       Contestation  and  Democracy     In  order  both  to  democratize  expertise,  and  to  rescue  its  authority  in   decision-­‐making,  real  contestation  over  expert  advice  needs  to  take  place.    It   must  be  recognised  that  expert  knowledge  is  often  incomplete  or  uncertain,   especially  in  cases  such  as  global  warming,  whose  indeterminate  nature  ensures   that  no  single  and  unambiguous  answer  can  be  found.    This  fact  allows  interest   groups  to  exploit  lay  understandings  of  issues  through  the  use  of  counter-­‐ expertise,  rather  than  the  proper  evaluation  of  the  case  at  hand.83    Science  alone   cannot  provide  these  judgements,  as  its  normative  dimensions  relating  to   distribution  and  justice  is  a  concern  for  the  public  at  large,  and  necessitates  lay   involvement.84         Yet  it  is  debatable  whether  scientists  can  or  even  should  remove   themselves  from  normative  questions.    Arguments  for  them  to  do  so  are  rooted   in  the  belief  of  science  as  objective  representation,  a  hangover  from  modernity.     In  fact,  normative  statements  are  bound  up  in  expert  statements  and  advice,  and   hence  the  interpretation  of  results,  by  the  very  process  of  research  selection  and   design.85    What  is  required  then  is  contestation,  in  an  open  and  transparent   manner,  alongside  democratic  participation  by  lay  publics  so  that  trust  may  be   engendered.86    For  different  types  of  information,  lay  and  expert,  social  and   scientific,  serve  to  co-­‐construct  our  understanding  of  issues  such  as  global   warming.87    Each  must  be  examined  so  that  legitimacy  may  be  lent  to  the   decision-­‐making  process.                                                                                                                   82  Garnaut,  ‘The  Garnaut  Climate  Change  Review’,  p.  xix.   83  Brown,  Science  in  Democracy,  pp.  11-­‐12.   84  Turner,  Liberal  Democracy  3.0,  p.  4.   85  Munnichs,  ‘Whom  to  Trust?’,  pp.  118-­‐119.   86  Ibid,  pp.  121-­‐124.   87  Jacquelin  Burgess  et  al.,  ‘Global  Warming  in  the  Public  Sphere’,  p.  2767.     17  
  • 18.   Contestation  here  is  not  taken  to  mean  the  overrepresentation  of   countervailing  opinions  in  the  news  media.    Superficial  questioning  of  this  kind   does  not  result  in  a  more  informed  and  critically  aware  polity,  nor  does  it  add  to   the  content  of  expertise.    This  is  especially  the  case  when  governments  and   interest  groups  use  expertise  in  ways  that  serve  to  constrain  debate  on  the   strengths  and  weaknesses  of  scientific  knowledge.88    Nevertheless,  lay   participation,  though  seen  by  many  to  allow  irrational  responses  to  risk  issues,   can  lead  to  the  inclusion  of  wider  perspectives  perhaps  not  considered  by   technical  experts.89    Indeed,  scientific  knowledge,  while  valuable,  is  incomplete   especially  as  regards  issues  with  significant  normative  implications.    It  can  help   explain  if  and  why  a  relationship  exists,  but  is  not  in  a  position  to  answer  what   ‘ought’  to  be  done  about  it  in  the  moral  and  ethical  sense,  which  is  the  domain  of   democratic  decision-­‐making.90    As  important  is  the  legitimacy  contestation  and   public  participation  lend  to  expert  advice  in  those  processes,  through  the   democratization  of  expertise  itself.    Public  participation,  which  is  not  aided  by   the  current  form  of  contestation  on  this  issue,  must  be  encouraged  if  democracy   and  expertise  are  to  be  amendable.     Conclusions     Science  and  its  institutions  are  in  a  sense  the  antithesis  of  democratic   systems  –  they  are  a  professionalized  elite  of  expertise,  closed  to  the  majority.91     Yet  expertise  in  democracies  only  encounters  problems  in  certain  situations.     Conflict  arises  in  cases  where  its  audience  is  public,  while  its  funding  private,  or   when  those  in  public  administration  accept  their  knowledge  as  authoritative.     Hence,  the  political  issue  for  democracies  is  not  the  existence  of  expertise,  but                                                                                                                   88  Myanna  Lahsen,  ‘Technocracy,  Democracy,  and  U.S.  Climate  Politics:  The  Need   for  Demarcations,’  Science,  Technology,  &  Human  Values,  Vol.  30,  No.  1,  2005,  pp.   138-­‐139.   89  Horlick-­‐Jones  et  al.,  ‘Citizen  Engagement’,  p.  260.   90  Avery,  ‘Scientific  Misconduct’,  p.  19.   91  Salomon,  ‘Science,  Technology  and  Democracy’,  p.  33.     18  
  • 19. the  discretionary  use  of  it  in  the  public  sphere.92    When  opened  up  to  public   scrutiny  of  its  use  the  conflict  between  expertise  and  democracy  is  less   pronounced.    Indeed,  the  spirit  of  free  inquiry  upon  which  modern  science  is   based  is  itself  a  foundational  democratic  principal.     In  the  case  of  the  global  warming  debate,  two  effects  of  the  closed  nature   of  expertise  are  evident.    Firstly,  sceptics  find  debate  over  method  and   uncertainty  convenient  to  their  cause,  despite  their  marginal  nature.    Secondly,   the  media,  having  shifted  pseudo-­‐contestation  to  the  public  sphere,  helps  them   in  their  cause.93    As  a  consequence,  there  have  been  policy  failures  ranging  from   the  global,  such  as  the  Copenhagen  negotiations,  to  the  local,  such  as  the   Emissions  Trading  Scheme  (ETS)  in  Australia.94    The  reality  is  that  in  the  face  of   environmental  risks  such  as  global  warming,  we  are  dependent  upon  technical   expertise.    It  cannot  then  be  simply  eradicated  from  democracy.    In  order  to   democratize  expertise  and  conduct  real  evaluations  of  it,  contestation  in   decision-­‐making,  based  upon  lay  participation  and  inquiry,  needs  to  be  instituted   within  democratic  forms  of  governance.                                                                                                                           92  Stephen  P.  Turner,  ‘What  is  the  Problem  with  Experts?,’  Social  Studies  of   Science,  Vol.  31,  No.  1,  2001,  pp.  140-­‐141.   93  Burgess  et  al.,  ‘Global  Warming  in  the  Public  Sphere’,  p.  2751.   94  Climate  change  policy  in  Australia  would  be  significantly  affected  particularly   following  the  failure  of  the  Copenhagen  negotiations.    After  two  defeats  in  the   Australian  Senate  for  the  ETS  the  government  of  the  Australian  Labour  Party   announced  that  it  would  not  seen  an  economy-­‐wide  market-­‐based  mitigation   program  until  after  2013.    Garnaut,  What  if  Mainstream  Science  if  Right?,  p.  7.     19  
  • 20. Bibliography     Primary  Sources     Climate  Commission,  The  Critical  Decade:  Climate  Science,  Risks  and  Responses,   Canberra,  Climate  Commission  Secretariat,  2011,  retrieved  19  June  2011,   available  from  <http://climatecommission.gov.au/topics/the-­‐critical-­‐ decade/>.     International  Panel  on  Climate  Change,  IPCC  Fourth  Assessment  Report:  Climate   Change  2007:  Synthesis  Report,  Cambridge,  Cambridge  University  Press,   2007,  retrieved  19  June  2011,  available  from  <http://www.ipcc.ch   /publications_  and_data/ar4/syr/en/  contents.html>.     Newspaper  Articles     Booker,  C.,  ‘Climate  Change:  This  is  the  Worst  Scientific  Scandal  of  our   Generation’,  The  Telegraph,  28  November  2009,  retrieved  19  June  2011   available  from  <http://www.telegraph.co.uk/comment/columnists/   christopherbooker  /6679082/Climate-­‐change-­‐this-­‐is-­‐the-­‐worst-­‐scientific-­‐ scandal-­‐of-­‐our-­‐generation.html>.     Chandler,  J.,  ‘When  Science  is  Undone  by  Fiction’,  The  Age,  June  29  2011,   retrieved  29  June  2011,  available  from  <http://www.theage.com.au/   opinion/politics/when-­‐science-­‐is-­‐undone-­‐by-­‐fiction-­‐20110628-­‐ 1gp26.html>.     Cook,  J.,  ‘Half  the  Truth  on  Emissions’,  The  Age,  June  28  2011,  retrieved  29  June   2011,  available  from  <http://www.theage.com.au/opinion/society-­‐and-­‐ culture/half-­‐the-­‐truth-­‐on-­‐emissions-­‐20110627-­‐1gne1.html>.     Hulme,  M.,  ‘The  Year  Climate  Science  was  Redefined’,  The  Guardian,  16   November  2010,  retrieved  19  June  2011,  available     20  
  • 21. <http://www.guardian.co.uk/  environment/2010/nov/15/year-­‐climate-­‐ science-­‐was-­‐redefined?INTCMP=SRCH>.     Hulme,  M.,  ‘The  Year  Climate  Science  was  Redefined’,  The  Guardian,  16   November  2010,  retrieved  19  June  2011,  available   <http://www.guardian.co.uk/environment/2010/nov/15/year-­‐climate-­‐ science-­‐was-­‐redefined?INTCMP=SRCH>.     Pearce,  F.,  ‘How  the  “Climategate”  Scandal  is  Bogus  and  Based  on  Climate   Sceptics’  Lies’,  The  Guardian,  2  February  2010,  p.  7,  retrieved  19  June  2011,   available  from  <http://www.guardian.co.uk/environment/2010/feb/01/   climate-­‐emails-­‐sceptics>.         Secondary  Sources     Anderson,  A.  Media,  Culture  and  the  Environment,  London,  UCL  Press,  1997.     Avery,  G.  H.,  ‘Scientific  Misconduct:  The  Perversion  of  Scientific  Evidence  for   Public  Advocacy’,  World  Medical  &  Health  Policy,  Vol.  2,  No.  4,  pp.  17-­‐31.     Beck,  Ü.,  Risk  Society:  Towards  a  New  Modernity,  London,  SAGE  Publications,   1992.     Beck,  Ü.,  Ecological  Enlightenment:  Essays  on  the  Politics  of  the  Risk  Society,   Atlantic  Highlands,  Humanities  Press,  1995.     Beck,  Ü.,  Ecological  Politics  in  an  Age  of  Risk,  Cambridge,  Polity  Press,  1995.     Beck,  Ü.  et  al.,  Reflexive  Modernization:  Politics,  Tradition  and  Aesthetics  in  the   Modern  Social  Order,  Cambridge,  Polity  Press,  1994.     Bennett,  W.  L.  and  Entman,  R.  M.  (eds.),  Mediated  Politics:  Communication  in  the   Future  of  Democracy,  New  York,  Cambridge  University  Press,  2001.     21  
  • 22.   Blok,  A.,  ‘Experts  on  Public  Trial:  On  Democratizing  Expertise  Through  a  Danish   Consensus  Conference’,  Public  Understandings  of  Science,  Vol.  16,  2007,  pp.   163-­‐182.     Boehmer-­‐Christiansen,  S.  A.,  ‘Britain  and  the  International  Panel  on  Climate   Change:  The  Impacts  of  Scientific  Advice  on  Global  Warming  Part  1:   Integrated  Policy  Analysis  and  the  Global  Dimension’,  Environmental   Politics,  Vol.  4,  No.  1,  1995,  pp.  1-­‐18.     Brown,  M.  B.,  Science  in  Democracy:  Expertise,  Institutions,  and  Representation,   London,  MIT  Press,  2009.     Burgess,  J.  et  al.,  ‘Global  Warming  in  the  Public  Sphere,’  Philosophical   Transactions:  Mathematical,  Physical  and  Engineering  Sciences,  Vol.  365,  No.   1860,  2007,  pp.  2741-­‐2776.     Cerutti,  F.,  Global  Challenges  for  Leviathan:  A  Political  Philosophy  of  Nuclear   Weapons  and  Global  Warming,  Lanham,  Lexington  Books,  2007.     Cozzens,  S.  E.  and  Woodhouse,  E.  J.,  ‘Science,  Government,  and  the  Politics  of   Knowledge,’  in  S.  Jasanoff  et  al.  (eds.),  Handbook  of  Science  and  Technology   Studies,  Thousand  Oaks,  SAGE  Publications,  1995,  pp.  533-­‐553.     Deane-­‐Drummond,  C.,  ‘A  Case  for  Collective  Conscience:  Climate  Gate,  COP-­‐15   and  Climate  Justice’,  Studies  in  Christian  Ethics,  Vol.  24,  No.  1,  2011,  pp.  5-­‐22.     Drori,  G.  S.  et  al.,  Science  in  the  Modern  World  Polity:  Institutionalization  and   Globalization,  Stanford,  Stanford  University  Press,  2003.     Golding,  D.  et  al.,  ‘Risk,  Trust  and  Democratic  Theory’,  in  G.  Cvetkovich  and  R.  E.   Löfstedt  (eds.),  Social  Trust  and  the  Management  of  Risk,  London,  Earthscan,   1999,  pp.  22-­‐41.     22  
  • 23.   Edwards,  P.  N.,  ‘Representing  the  Global  Atmosphere:  Computer  Models,  Data,   and  Knowledge  about  Climate  Change’,  in  P.  N.  Edwards  and  C.  A.  Miller   (eds.),  Changing  the  Atmosphere:  Expert  Knowledge  and  Environmental   Governance,  Cambridge,  MIT  Press,  2001,  pp.  31-­‐66.     Edwards,  P.  N.  and  Miller,  C.  A.,  ‘Introduction:  The  Globalization  of  Climate   Science  and  Climate  Politics,’  in  P.  N.  Edwards  and  C.  A.  Miller  (eds.),   Changing  the  Atmosphere:  Expert  Knowledge  and  Environmental  Governance,   Cambridge,  MIT  Press,  2001,  pp.  1-­‐31.     Edwards  P.  N.  and  Schneider,  S.  H.  ‘Self-­‐Governance  and  Peer  Review  in  Science-­‐ for-­‐policy:  The  Case  of  the  IPCC  Second  Assessment  Report,’  in  P.  N.   Edwards  and  C.  A.  Miller  (eds.),  Changing  the  Atmosphere:  Expert   Knowledge  and  Environmental  Governance,  Cambridge,  MIT  Press,  2001,  pp.   219-­‐246.     Evans  R.  and  Plows,  A.,  ‘Listening  without  Prejudice?:  Re-­‐discovering  the  Value  of   the  Disinterested  Citizen,’  Social  Studies  of  Science,  Vol.  37,  No.  6,  2007,  pp.   827-­‐853.     Evetts,  J.  et  al.,  ‘Professionalization,  Scientific  Expertise,  and  Elitism:  A   Sociological  Perspective,’  in  N.  Charness  et  al.  (eds.),  The  Cambridge   Handbook  of  Expertise  and  Expert  Performance,  Cambridge,  Cambridge   University  Press,  2006,  pp.  105-­‐123.     Ferris,  T.,  The  Science  of  Liberty:  Democracy,  Reason,  and  the  Laws  of  Nature,  New   York,  Harper,  2010.     Fielding,  R.,  ‘The  Perversion  of  Scientific  Evidence  for  Policy  Advocacy:  A   Perspective  on  Avery  2010’,  World  Medical  &  Health  Policy,  Vol.  3,  No.  1,   2011,  pp.  1-­‐4.       23