SlideShare ist ein Scribd-Unternehmen logo
1 von 9
Downloaden Sie, um offline zu lesen
Introduction

   Spinoza and the problem of expression


The reading of Spinoza that Gilles Deleuze presents in Expressionism in
Philosophy1 is both challenging and controversial: challenging from the point of
view of the complexity with which it engages the ideas of Spinoza; and
controversial from the point of view of the extent to which it serves to redeploy
Spinoza within the context of Deleuze’s own philosophical project. While closely
examining his reading of Spinoza, the present work focuses on the more
controversial issue of Deleuze’s Spinozism, or the way in which Deleuze redeploys
Spinoza, or the Spinozist concepts that he extracts from Spinoza’s philosophy, in
his project of constructing a philosophy of difference. Deleuze’s Spinozism is
examined in relation to both Expressionism in Philosophy and Difference and
Repetition,2 and to the seminars that Deleuze gave on Spinoza.3 What is proposed
therefore is a Deleuzian reading of Expressionism in Philosophy that positions
itself within the trajectory of the development of Deleuze’s philosophy.
    Deleuze’s reading of Spinoza is explicated within the context of contemporary
French Spinoza studies, particularly in relation to the work of Martial Gueroult and
Pierre Macherey. However, it is in relation to Hegel’s interpretation of Spinoza and
the position that Hegel assigns to Spinoza in both the dialectical progression of the
history of philosophy and the development of his dialectical logic that Deleuze
strategically redeploys Spinoza. The process of actualization determined by the
Hegelian dialectical logic in relation to the history of philosophy is determinately
linear and progressive, insofar as it is predominantly preoccupied with overcoming
moments of discontinuity, an example of which would be the system of the
philosophy of Spinoza, each of which is ‘at the centre of the necessity of an
evolutionary process’, which determines ‘the continuation of “history”’.4

   1
        Gilles Deleuze, Expressionism in Philosophy, Spinoza, trans. M. Joughin (New
York, 1992).
    2
        Gilles Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, trans. P. Patton (New York, 1994).
    3
        Gilles Deleuze’s seminars on Spinoza, entitled ‘sur Spinoza’, given between 1971
and 1987 at the Université Paris VIII Vincennes and Vincennes St-Denis, have been
published on the internet at URL <http://www.webdeleuze.com>.
    4
        Juliette Simont, Essai sur la quantité, la qualité, la relation chez Kant, Hegel,
Deleuze. Les ‘fleurs noires’ de la logique philosophique (Paris, 1997), p. 230. Simont also
writes that ‘the continuity of history is the form or the method of deciphering the actual
2                              The Logic of Expression
    In ‘Spinoza et la méthode de Gueroult’, when reviewing Gueroult’s two-
volume study of Spinoza,5 Deleuze details those elements of Gueroult’s method of
engagement with Spinoza that he considers to have had a profound effect both on
contemporary Spinoza studies, and also on the role of the history of philosophy in
the contemporary practice of philosophy in general. He argues that ‘Gueroult
renewed the history of philosophy by a structural–genetic method, which he had
elaborated well before structuralism imposed itself in other domains. Such a
structure is defined by an order of reasons, the reasons being differential and
generative elements of the corresponding system, veritable philosophemes which
only exist in their relations with each other’.6 ‘Gueroult’s admirable book’, he
continues, ‘has a double importance, both from the point of view of the general
method that it puts to work, and from the point of view of his Spinozism, which
does not represent one application of this method among others but rather
constitutes the most adequate, the most saturated, the most exhaustive term or
object concluding the series on Descartes, Malebranche and Leibniz. This book
founds the veritable scientific study of Spinozism’.7
    This characterization of the method of Gueroult actually outlines Deleuze’s
own philosophical project in Expressionism in Philosophy. It is there that Deleuze
undertakes the project of renewing the history of philosophy in relation to Spinoza.
The structural–genetic criteria that Deleuze deploys are determined according to a
logic of expression, which is elaborated in Difference and Repetition in relation to
the differential calculus as a logic of different/ciation. The ‘differential and
generative elements’ of this logic exist solely in the differential relations that they
have with each other. Expressionism in Philosophy is also doubly important, not
only insofar as it too advocates the ‘scientific study of Spinozism’, in particular
Spinoza’s relation to mathematics and the differential calculus of Leibniz, but also
insofar as it is the final text of a series of works on figures in the history of
philosophy: Hume, Nietzsche, Bergson,8 which constitutes Deleuze’s project of
renewing the history of philosophy by constructing an alternative lineage in the
history of philosophy. With this series of texts Deleuze proposes a new way of
reading the figures of the history of philosophy, ‘neither as the possessors of a truth
whose reactualization is being attempted, nor as the objects of an infinite
“deconstruction”, nor as the occupants of a privileged enclave accessible only to



connections of the historian’s reading, the individuation of the systems of which is the
material or the discontinuous content’ (p. 231). All citations quoted from French language
texts are my translations, unless otherwise indicated.
    5
         Martial Gueroult, Spinoza (t. I–II, Paris, 1968–74).
    6
         Deleuze, ‘Spinoza et la méthode générale de Gueroult’, Revue de Métaphysique et
de Morale, 74 (1969), p. 426.
    7
         Ibid., p. 437.
    8
         Deleuze later returns to this series with a text on Leibniz.
Spinoza and the problem of expression                           3
the erudite historian, but as interlocutors’ directly implicated in ‘the construction
and experimentation of new [modes] of thought’.9
    In ‘The encounter with Spinoza’, Macherey critiques Deleuze’s reading of
Spinoza by questioning whether it is ‘consistent with the original sense of the work
he purports to analyze, or does it rather misrepresent Spinoza’s philosophy’.10
Macherey maintains that Deleuze attempts to ‘introduce a new version of
Spinozism that [is] at variance, if not completely at odds, with the model of
demonstrative rationality explicitly adopted by Spinoza himself’.11 Macherey is one
of the most respected of contemporary Spinoza scholars in France, whose five-
volume study of the Ethics, entitled Introduction à l’Ethique de Spinoza,12
attempts, by extracting the persistent difficulties of Spinozism, to establish an
internal coherence to the system of the text. However, it is in relation to Hegel’s
interpretation of Spinoza that Macherey first distinguished himself as a Spinoza
scholar of repute. Chapter 1 examines his first major work on Spinoza, Hegel ou
Spinoza,13 which challenges the influence of Hegel’s reading of Spinoza by
stressing the degree to which Spinoza eludes the grasp of the Hegelian dialectical
progression of the history of philosophy. Macherey argues that Hegel provides a
defensive misreading of Spinoza, and that he had to ‘misread him’ in order to
maintain his teleological subjective idealism. The suggestion being that Spinoza’s
philosophy represents, not a moment that can be simply sublated and subsumed
within the dialectical progression of the history of philosophy, but rather an
alternative point of view for the development of a philosophy that overcomes
Hegelian idealism.
    Deleuze also considers Spinoza’s philosophy to resist the totalizing effects of
the dialectic. Indeed, Deleuze demonstrates, by means of Spinoza, that a more
complex philosophy antedates Hegel’s which cannot be supplanted by it. Spinoza
therefore becomes a significant figure in Deleuze’s project of tracing an alternative
lineage in the history of philosophy, which, by distancing itself from Hegelian
idealism, culminates in the construction of a philosophy of difference. Rather than
attempting to determine the elements of Deleuze already in Hegel,14 or the
adequacy of the Hegelian elements in Deleuze,15 or elaborating a Deleuzian



   9
        Manola Antonioli, Deleuze et l’histoire de la philosophie (Paris, 1999), p. 10.
   10
        Pierre Macherey, ‘The encounter with Spinoza’, trans. M. Joughin, in Paul Patton
(ed.), Deleuze, A Critical Reader (Oxford and Cambridge, 1996), p. 142.
    11
        Ibid., p. 141.
    12
        Pierre Macherey, Introduction à l’Ethique de Spinoza (t. I–V, Paris, 1994–98).
    13
        Pierre Macherey, Hegel ou Spinoza (Paris, 1979).
    14
        Pierre Verstraten recognizes in ‘the thought of Hegel … an unexpected premonition
of that of Deleuze’, see ‘La question du negative chez Deleuze’, Gilles Deleuze (Paris,
1998), p. 176.
    15
        Is Deleuze’s Hegel perhaps too Kojèvian? See Simont, p. 276.
4                               The Logic of Expression
Hegel or a Hegelian Deleuze,17 or, on the contrary, claiming that ‘no encounter is
      16

possible’,18 an alternative approach to the determination of the relation between
Deleuze and Hegel is to read their respective interpretations of Spinoza, and the
role that they each assign to Spinoza in the development of their respective
philosophical projects, together, alongside of each other, and also in direct relation
to each other. This strategy entails examining those points of convergence between
the elements of their respective interpretations of Spinoza, in order then to
determine what sets them radically apart. It is in the logic of the relations
established between the elements of their respective interpretations of Spinoza that
this radical difference is manifested, and it is by means of the determination of this
difference in logic between their respective interpretations of Spinoza that the
difference in the logic of their respective philosophical projects in general is
determined.
    Spinoza’s role in this strategy is demonstrated in chapter 2 by differentiating
Deleuze’s interpretation of the geometrical example of Spinoza’s Letter XII (on the
problem of the infinite) from that which Hegel presents in the Science of Logic.19
Both Hegel and Deleuze each position the geometrical example at different stages
in the early development of the differential calculus. By demonstrating the relation
between ‘the differential point of view of the infinitesimal calculus’ and the
differential calculus of contemporary mathematics, it is argued in chapter 3 that
Deleuze effectively bypasses the methods of the differential calculus which Hegel
uses to support the development of the dialectical logic. By exploiting the
implications of the differential point of view of the infinitesimal calculus in his
interpretation of the physics of bodies in the second part of the Ethics, Deleuze is
able to read the system of the Ethics as a whole as determined according to the
logic of different/ciation. The explication of this reading strategy is what
constitutes the Deleuzian reading of Expressionism in Philosophy that is
undertaken in the present work. This strategy of reading the Ethics as determined
according to a logic of different/ciation marks not only the originality of Deleuze’s
interpretation of Spinoza, but also one of the points where Deleuze can be
considered to depart from the Cartesian and Hegelian Spinoza familiar to scholars


     16
        Juliette Simont actually argues that Deleuze’s Hegel is perhaps too ‘Hegelian’, ‘a
terribly Hegelian Hegel’, and proposes instead another Hegel, ‘the other Hegel’, who ‘is
perhaps too Deleuzian, or is only possible when read across Deleuze’ (Ibid., p. 297).
     17
        Catherine Malabou, in ‘Who’s afraid of Hegelian Wolves?’ (Patton, Deleuze, A
Critical Reader), argues that ‘doing justice to Deleuze’s finely wrought thinking concerning
affirmation implies, in my opinion, affirming Hegel’s role in it’ (p. 136).
     18
        Manola Antonioli, in Deleuze et l’histoire de la philosophie, argues that ‘with Hegel
… no encounter is possible: the recourse to the negative and to contradiction is
irreconcilable with the affirmative presuppositions of the Deleuzian philosophy, there is
nothing “to put together” between Deleuze and Hegel’ (p. 80).
     19
        G.W.F. Hegel, Hegel’s Science of Logic, trans. A.V. Miller (London, 1969), p. 251.
Spinoza and the problem of expression                             5
working in the field of Spinoza studies by tracing an alternative lineage in the
history of philosophy between Spinoza’s ontology and the mathematics of Leibniz.


One of the recurring critiques of Deleuze’s reading of Spinoza in Expressionism in
Philosophy is that the Deleuzian concepts inspired by Spinozist ideas are nowhere
to be found in the text of the Ethics. Macherey conducts his critique of
Expressionism in Philosophy in ‘The encounter with Spinoza’ by disputing such
Deleuzian concepts, in particular the concept of ‘joyful passive affections’, which
is addressed in chapter 7, and the concept of ‘expression’, which is addressed in
chapter 10. In quality and quantity in the philosophy of Spinoza, Charles Ramond
disputes Deleuze’s use of the concept of ‘intensive quantity’ in Expressionism in
Philosophy. He argues that ‘we can … only be surprised to see Deleuze make the
notion of “intensive quantity” the foundation of his interpretation of Spinoza’s
theory of the essence of singular things, as if Spinoza had effectively supported
such a position’. In relation to the concept of ‘intensity’ and to that of ‘intensive
parts’ Ramond argues that: ‘According to Deleuze, Spinoza locates, by using the
notion of “intensity”, “a long Scholastic tradition”, of which only “Scotism”,
without more precision, is evoked’; and that ‘When Deleuze … declares that, in
Spinoza, “modal essences are … intensive parts”, he utters an assertion strictly
incomprehensible within the framework of Spinozism’.20 However, these
Deleuzian concepts are, more often than not, considered and criticized for
themselves, independently of the context which supports their exposition because
of its extremely technical character. It is by means of these concepts in
Expressionism in Philosophy that Deleuze shifts the reading of the philosophy of
Spinoza onto an entirely different terrain. Rather than reading the philosophy of
Spinoza either solely in relation to Descartes, or simply as one stage in the
dialectical progression of the history of philosophy, Deleuze reads the philosophy
of Spinoza insofar as it contributes to the construction of an alternative lineage in
the history of philosophy, which features the work of Duns Scotus, in particular the
concept of formal distinction, the concept of the univocity of being and the concept
of individuality. Deleuze does not read Spinoza as a Scotist, but rather, by reading
Scotus alongside of Spinoza, he examines Spinoza’s reformulation of these Scotist
concepts in order to develop those aspects of Spinoza’s philosophy that are
specifically Anticartesian. The mechanism by means of which Deleuze does this is
elaborated in chapter 4. This Anticartesian reading of Spinoza provides the
framework for the development of a reading of Spinoza that challenges the
Hegelian concept of the dialectical progression of the history of philosophy. The
Deleuzian domain of engagement with Spinoza is determined therefore by
deterritorializing a fairly traditional reading of Spinoza from a particularly

   20
        Charles Ramond, qualité et quantité dans la philosophie de Spinoza (Paris, 1995), p.
201.
6                              The Logic of Expression
Cartesian and Hegelian point of view, to that of a more Scotist and even Leibnizian
point of view, thereby determining an alternative lineage in the history of
philosophy.
    Deleuze considers Spinoza’s Ethics to have given expression to the concept of
individuality, whose themes can be found scattered among several other authors of
the seventeenth century: for Deleuze’s purposes most notably in the work of Duns
Scotus. In relation to the concept of individuality, the Hegelian categories of
quantity, quality and relation, which articulate differences in the distances or
dimensions of things (quantity), in their nature (quality), and in their order
(relation), are considered by Deleuze to be antedated by the three different
dimensions of the individual as presented by Spinoza, namely relation, power
(quantity), and mode (quality). The individual is characterized as relation insofar as
there is a composition of individuals in relation to one another, or amongst
themselves. In chapter 2 it is argued that the infinitesimal calculus puts into play a
certain type of relation for Deleuze – the differential relation – which is
characteristic of the compositional relations between individuals. The
characterization of the individual as power (potentia) indicates the individual’s
capacity to compose new relations with other individuals. The concept of potentia,
which is translated by the concept of power as force or capacity, is different to that
of potestas, which is translated by power in the juridico–political sense of the
term,21 insofar as it expresses that which an individual body can do, and which is
verified by joy. Composition therefore refers not only to the characteristic relations
between individuals, but also to the capacity or potential to create these kinds of
relations, the mechanism of which is determined as operating according to the logic
of different/ciation, and is elaborated in chapter 3. The third dimension of the
individual is characterized as mode, which Deleuze considers to be expressive of
the Scotist concept of an ‘intrinsic mode’. Deleuze’s characterization of the
‘intrinsic mode’ of an individual as the ‘intensive part’, or singular modal essence,
of an individual, or of its corresponding finite existing mode, is elaborated in
chapter 4. The mechanism by means of which intensive parts are distinguished not
only from one another, but also from the extensive parts corresponding to them, is
determined as operating according to the logic of different/ciation. The question of
how the intensive parts of different individuals are differentiated from one another
as more or less powerful is then investigated in chapter 5. Chapter 6 raises the
question of whether the power, or capacity, of an individual, which Deleuze
characterizes as its power to act, should be understood to be fixed or variable, and

    21
        Eugene Holland notes that Martial Gueroult, in his two-volume study of Spinoza, is
one of the first to demonstrate the importance of the distinction between potentia and
potestas in Spinoza (Holland, ‘Spinoza and Marx’, Cultural Logic, 2.1 (Fall, 1998), §29).
For a thorough examination of the social and political implications of this distinction in
relation to Spinoza see Antonio Negri, The Savage Anomaly: the power of Spinoza’s
metaphysics and politics, trans. M. Hardt (Minneapolis, 1991).
Spinoza and the problem of expression                           7
how such a power to act is implicated in the transformations of the characteristic
relations determinative of an individual. Deleuze’s disputed distinction of passions
into joyful passive affections and sad passive affections is elaborated in chapter 7,
as is the manner by means of which joyful passive affections are pivotal in
determining the transition from inadequate ideas of the imagination to adequate
ideas of reason. Chapter 8 investigates in detail the mechanism by means of which
joyful passive affections are implicated in the dynamic changes or transformations
of the characteristic relations determinative of an individual by mapping the
mathematical concept of accumulation onto the ontological concept of the
accumulation of joyful passive affections, such that there are ‘correspondences
without resemblance’ that ‘are of a structural–genetic nature’22 between them, that
is, insofar as both are determined as operating according to the logic of
different/ciation.
    The distinction between the duration of an individual, or of its finite modal
existence, and its eternity is investigated in chapter 9, where the thesis that
occupies the fifth part of the Ethics which deals with the relation between death and
the eternity of the soul according to the third kind of knowledge, and which is often
mistaken for a discussion advocating the immortality of the soul, is developed. That
which concerns the concept of eternity in the Ethics has interested scholars and
commentators since the earliest interpretations of Spinoza, which were used either
to reinforce piety by espousing one’s opposition to Spinoza’s atheism, or, on the
contrary, and more rarely, to justify one’s pantheism by defending Spinozism.23
These studies often took the form of demonstrating that the thesis on eternity in
part five was incoherent with that of the preceding parts of the Ethics, notably with
the principle of parallelism. This aspect of the Ethics is still widely disputed among
scholars working in the field of Spinoza studies. My contention is that Deleuze’s
argument from powers, which is explicated in chapter 9 according to the logic of
different/ciation, demonstrates an alternative approach that allows a better
comprehension of the coherence between the different parts of the Ethics. The logic
of different/ciation is therefore determinative not only of the mechanism by means
of which joyful passive affections operate in Deleuze’s reading of the Ethics, but it
is also the logic that is determinative of Deleuze’s reading of the system of the
Ethics as a whole.


The project of the present work is to develop an understanding of Deleuze’s
Spinoza by providing a Deleuzian reading of Expressionism in Philosophy, which
involves not only determining the mechanism of operation of the logic of

   22
       Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, p. 184.
   23
       For an account of the multiple conflicting readings of Spinoza’s early interpreters
see Frederick C. Beiser, The fate of reason: German philosophy from Kant to Fichte
(Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1987).
8                              The Logic of Expression
different/ciation in Expressionism in Philosophy, but also involves positioning
Deleuze’s Spinoza, and the logic with which it is explicated, within the context of
the development of Deleuze’s wider philosophical project. Such a Deleuzian
reading of Expressionism in Philosophy is therefore important for the
determination of the way in which Spinoza becomes for Deleuze a significant
figure in his project of tracing an alternative lineage in the history of philosophy,
and serves well to situate Expressionism in Philosophy within the context of
Deleuze’s project of constructing a philosophy of difference. The context of this
dual Deleuzian project is explicated in chapter 10 in relation to Deleuze’s other
major text from the same period, Difference and Repetition.
    It is in Difference and Repetition, in relation to the Scotist concept of the
univocity of being, that Deleuze specifically positions Spinoza as a significant
figure in the project of tracing an alternative lineage in the history of philosophy.
He argues that there are ‘three principal moments in the history of the
philosophical elaboration of the univocity of being’,24 which he locates
respectively in the work of Scotus, Spinoza and Nietzsche. My argument in chapter
10 is that this alternative lineage in the history of philosophy only makes sense in
relation to the demands of a concept of temporality that is determined according to
the logic of different/ciation.
    In What is Philosophy?, Deleuze claims that ‘philosophy is the discipline that
involves creating concepts’.25 The manner by means of which concepts are created
is determined by the encounters between the concepts belonging to philosophies of
the past which generate the problems of which the new concepts are the solution.
The concepts of philosophies of the past, to which Deleuze refers, are determined
in relation to the history of philosophy and include, for example, the Scotist
concept of univocity, the Spinozist concept of Substance as immanent cause, and
the Nietzschean concept of the eternal return. It is by means of the encounters
between these concepts (of the past) that, on the one hand, new concepts are
created, and that, on the other hand, the problem, onto which each of these
concepts (of the past) is grafted, is generated. The determination of these concepts
(of the past) and of the manner by means of which the encounters between them
create new concepts and generate problems is explicated in chapter 10 according to
the logic of different/ciation.
    The concept of expression and the concept of intensity are two other concepts
whose explication is pivotal in determining the manner by means of which Deleuze
reads the Ethics in Expressionism in Philosophy. What is expression? And what is
the relation between Spinoza’s Ethics and the concept of expression explicated by
Deleuze in Expressionism in Philosophy? These questions are addressed in chapter
10 where I contend that it is in relation to the concept of expression that the logic

    24
       Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, p. 39.
    25
       Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, What is Philosophy?, trans. H. Tomlinson and G.
Burchell (New York, 1994), p. 5.
Spinoza and the problem of expression                          9
of different/ciation is explicated in the text of Expressionism in Philosophy as a
logic of expression. It is according to the logic of expression that the Spinozist
concept of Substance as immanent cause and the Nietzschean concept of the
eternal return are problematized in relation to one another in Difference and
Repetition, thereby creating the Deleuzian concept of intensity. It is by means of
the development of the problematic relation between the Deleuzian concept of
intensity, which is determined according to the logic of expression, and the concept
of intensity determined rather by the Hegelian dialectical logic, that the logic of
expression is determined as an alternative to the Hegelian dialectical logic. Insofar
as the logic of expression is determined as the logic according to which the
philosophy of difference is constructed, it functions not only as an alternative to
the Hegelian dialectical logic, but it is also determined as the logic according to
which the philosophy of difference functions as an alternative to the dialectical
philosophy determined by the Hegelian dialectical logic. Deleuze’s reading of
Spinoza in Expressionism in Philosophy therefore redeploys Spinoza in relation to
an alternative lineage in the history of philosophy in order to mobilize his
philosophy of difference as an alternative to the dialectical philosophy determined
by the Hegelian dialectical logic.
    While acknowledging some of the problematical elements of Deleuze’s
challenging interpretation of Spinoza, the central focus of the work remains an
examination of the manner by means of which Spinoza is mobilized by Deleuze in
his project of constructing a philosophy of difference. The reading of Deleuze’s
philosophy that is presented in the present work is therefore resolutely partial.
Neither the implications of Deleuze’s Spinozism for understanding his other works,
nor the extent to which these are influenced by his Spinozism is treated in any great
detail. Indeed when certain of these texts are nevertheless referred to, it is solely in
order to better determine the schema of problematization associated with the
development of the logic of expression in Expressionism in Philosophy, or serves
merely to suggest the implications of such a development for Deleuze’s subsequent
works. As for the latter, rather than suggesting in detail the full range of potential
implications, that which is suggested is solely the manner by means of which these
implications are determined, that is, that they too are determinable according to the
logic of expression. For example, the present work concludes by suggesting the
implications of the logic of expression for determining an understanding of the
relation between, what Deleuze and Guattari refer to in What is Philosophy? as, a
philosophy’s plane of immanence, and the concepts created by this philosophy that
are distributed over this plane.

Weitere ähnliche Inhalte

Andere mochten auch (10)

Systems se
Systems seSystems se
Systems se
 
流行趨勢報告2012春夏
流行趨勢報告2012春夏流行趨勢報告2012春夏
流行趨勢報告2012春夏
 
20sites303
20sites30320sites303
20sites303
 
Especial novarejo
Especial novarejoEspecial novarejo
Especial novarejo
 
生活型態趨勢分析 2012
生活型態趨勢分析 2012生活型態趨勢分析 2012
生活型態趨勢分析 2012
 
Fashion Trend 2012 Spring Summer 流行趨勢報告2012春夏
Fashion Trend 2012 Spring Summer 流行趨勢報告2012春夏Fashion Trend 2012 Spring Summer 流行趨勢報告2012春夏
Fashion Trend 2012 Spring Summer 流行趨勢報告2012春夏
 
22946884 a-coarse-taxonomy-of-artificial-immune-systems
22946884 a-coarse-taxonomy-of-artificial-immune-systems22946884 a-coarse-taxonomy-of-artificial-immune-systems
22946884 a-coarse-taxonomy-of-artificial-immune-systems
 
Tnhp daniel garber
Tnhp daniel garberTnhp daniel garber
Tnhp daniel garber
 
Assistivetech
AssistivetechAssistivetech
Assistivetech
 
Sankyo music box
Sankyo music boxSankyo music box
Sankyo music box
 

Ähnlich wie Logic of expression_intro

SEP-FEP-abstract-booklet-2012
SEP-FEP-abstract-booklet-2012SEP-FEP-abstract-booklet-2012
SEP-FEP-abstract-booklet-2012
Ellie Harper
 
Hegeland Spinoza
Hegeland SpinozaHegeland Spinoza
Hegeland Spinoza
David Proud
 
สัปดาห์ที่ 16 phenomenology
สัปดาห์ที่ 16 phenomenologyสัปดาห์ที่ 16 phenomenology
สัปดาห์ที่ 16 phenomenology
Sani Satjachaliao
 
Hegel and Spinoza
Hegel and SpinozaHegel and Spinoza
Hegel and Spinoza
David Proud
 
Ncercc Socialpedagogybook Chap11
Ncercc Socialpedagogybook Chap11Ncercc Socialpedagogybook Chap11
Ncercc Socialpedagogybook Chap11
gaz12000
 
Hypatia, Inc. Simone de Beauvoirs Phenomenology of Sexu.docx
Hypatia, Inc. Simone de Beauvoirs Phenomenology of Sexu.docxHypatia, Inc. Simone de Beauvoirs Phenomenology of Sexu.docx
Hypatia, Inc. Simone de Beauvoirs Phenomenology of Sexu.docx
adampcarr67227
 
Lecture 1. philosophy_in_general
Lecture 1. philosophy_in_generalLecture 1. philosophy_in_general
Lecture 1. philosophy_in_general
sekapeka
 
Sophia speaks presentation
Sophia speaks presentationSophia speaks presentation
Sophia speaks presentation
B_Alderman
 

Ähnlich wie Logic of expression_intro (20)

SEP-FEP-abstract-booklet-2012
SEP-FEP-abstract-booklet-2012SEP-FEP-abstract-booklet-2012
SEP-FEP-abstract-booklet-2012
 
Hegeland Spinoza
Hegeland SpinozaHegeland Spinoza
Hegeland Spinoza
 
สัปดาห์ที่ 16 phenomenology
สัปดาห์ที่ 16 phenomenologyสัปดาห์ที่ 16 phenomenology
สัปดาห์ที่ 16 phenomenology
 
Hegel and Spinoza
Hegel and SpinozaHegel and Spinoza
Hegel and Spinoza
 
On the Relation Between Philosophy and Science
On the Relation Between Philosophy and ScienceOn the Relation Between Philosophy and Science
On the Relation Between Philosophy and Science
 
Ncercc Socialpedagogybook Chap11
Ncercc Socialpedagogybook Chap11Ncercc Socialpedagogybook Chap11
Ncercc Socialpedagogybook Chap11
 
Ontologia velez dpto_2015
Ontologia velez dpto_2015Ontologia velez dpto_2015
Ontologia velez dpto_2015
 
2011 - The Language Of Research Argument Metaphors In English And Lithuanian...
2011 - The Language Of Research  Argument Metaphors In English And Lithuanian...2011 - The Language Of Research  Argument Metaphors In English And Lithuanian...
2011 - The Language Of Research Argument Metaphors In English And Lithuanian...
 
Unit 1
Unit 1Unit 1
Unit 1
 
Hypatia, Inc. Simone de Beauvoirs Phenomenology of Sexu.docx
Hypatia, Inc. Simone de Beauvoirs Phenomenology of Sexu.docxHypatia, Inc. Simone de Beauvoirs Phenomenology of Sexu.docx
Hypatia, Inc. Simone de Beauvoirs Phenomenology of Sexu.docx
 
Franz Martin Wimmer - Polylog between conflicting values
Franz Martin Wimmer - Polylog between conflicting valuesFranz Martin Wimmer - Polylog between conflicting values
Franz Martin Wimmer - Polylog between conflicting values
 
What is philosophy1
What is philosophy1What is philosophy1
What is philosophy1
 
Lecture 1. philosophy_in_general
Lecture 1. philosophy_in_generalLecture 1. philosophy_in_general
Lecture 1. philosophy_in_general
 
Phenomenology: What is it and where does it fit? - Dave Aldridge
Phenomenology: What is it and where does it fit? - Dave AldridgePhenomenology: What is it and where does it fit? - Dave Aldridge
Phenomenology: What is it and where does it fit? - Dave Aldridge
 
The self-criticism of science
The self-criticism of scienceThe self-criticism of science
The self-criticism of science
 
Philosophy of science
Philosophy of sciencePhilosophy of science
Philosophy of science
 
Applebaum (2013) interrelationship of phenomenological philosophy & psychology
Applebaum (2013) interrelationship of phenomenological philosophy & psychologyApplebaum (2013) interrelationship of phenomenological philosophy & psychology
Applebaum (2013) interrelationship of phenomenological philosophy & psychology
 
Laszlo-garai-theoretical-psycology-vygotskian-writings
 Laszlo-garai-theoretical-psycology-vygotskian-writings Laszlo-garai-theoretical-psycology-vygotskian-writings
Laszlo-garai-theoretical-psycology-vygotskian-writings
 
Sophia speaks presentation
Sophia speaks presentationSophia speaks presentation
Sophia speaks presentation
 
UNDERSTANDING PHILOSOPHICAL ANALYSIS USING NIGERIAN DEMOCRACY AS A CASE STUDY
UNDERSTANDING PHILOSOPHICAL ANALYSIS USING NIGERIAN DEMOCRACY AS A CASE STUDYUNDERSTANDING PHILOSOPHICAL ANALYSIS USING NIGERIAN DEMOCRACY AS A CASE STUDY
UNDERSTANDING PHILOSOPHICAL ANALYSIS USING NIGERIAN DEMOCRACY AS A CASE STUDY
 

Mehr von Franco Bressan (16)

1317856
13178561317856
1317856
 
1316975
13169751316975
1316975
 
1315741
13157411315741
1315741
 
1316244
13162441316244
1316244
 
29404
2940429404
29404
 
Paty,m 1997d unverslde-cienc
Paty,m 1997d unverslde-ciencPaty,m 1997d unverslde-cienc
Paty,m 1997d unverslde-cienc
 
Fragoso5
Fragoso5Fragoso5
Fragoso5
 
Deleuze luiz
Deleuze luizDeleuze luiz
Deleuze luiz
 
01 02 03_marcelo
01 02 03_marcelo01 02 03_marcelo
01 02 03_marcelo
 
18394
1839418394
18394
 
2004 033 33001014010_p9_disc_ofe
2004 033 33001014010_p9_disc_ofe2004 033 33001014010_p9_disc_ofe
2004 033 33001014010_p9_disc_ofe
 
Hz242 a
Hz242 aHz242 a
Hz242 a
 
Sens public f_caprio_substancia_liberdade_e_existencia
Sens public f_caprio_substancia_liberdade_e_existenciaSens public f_caprio_substancia_liberdade_e_existencia
Sens public f_caprio_substancia_liberdade_e_existencia
 
M16yg
M16ygM16yg
M16yg
 
Ed. 1 tjdft_ed._abt
Ed. 1 tjdft_ed._abtEd. 1 tjdft_ed._abt
Ed. 1 tjdft_ed._abt
 
Ais machine learning
Ais machine learningAis machine learning
Ais machine learning
 

Logic of expression_intro

  • 1. Introduction Spinoza and the problem of expression The reading of Spinoza that Gilles Deleuze presents in Expressionism in Philosophy1 is both challenging and controversial: challenging from the point of view of the complexity with which it engages the ideas of Spinoza; and controversial from the point of view of the extent to which it serves to redeploy Spinoza within the context of Deleuze’s own philosophical project. While closely examining his reading of Spinoza, the present work focuses on the more controversial issue of Deleuze’s Spinozism, or the way in which Deleuze redeploys Spinoza, or the Spinozist concepts that he extracts from Spinoza’s philosophy, in his project of constructing a philosophy of difference. Deleuze’s Spinozism is examined in relation to both Expressionism in Philosophy and Difference and Repetition,2 and to the seminars that Deleuze gave on Spinoza.3 What is proposed therefore is a Deleuzian reading of Expressionism in Philosophy that positions itself within the trajectory of the development of Deleuze’s philosophy. Deleuze’s reading of Spinoza is explicated within the context of contemporary French Spinoza studies, particularly in relation to the work of Martial Gueroult and Pierre Macherey. However, it is in relation to Hegel’s interpretation of Spinoza and the position that Hegel assigns to Spinoza in both the dialectical progression of the history of philosophy and the development of his dialectical logic that Deleuze strategically redeploys Spinoza. The process of actualization determined by the Hegelian dialectical logic in relation to the history of philosophy is determinately linear and progressive, insofar as it is predominantly preoccupied with overcoming moments of discontinuity, an example of which would be the system of the philosophy of Spinoza, each of which is ‘at the centre of the necessity of an evolutionary process’, which determines ‘the continuation of “history”’.4 1 Gilles Deleuze, Expressionism in Philosophy, Spinoza, trans. M. Joughin (New York, 1992). 2 Gilles Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, trans. P. Patton (New York, 1994). 3 Gilles Deleuze’s seminars on Spinoza, entitled ‘sur Spinoza’, given between 1971 and 1987 at the Université Paris VIII Vincennes and Vincennes St-Denis, have been published on the internet at URL <http://www.webdeleuze.com>. 4 Juliette Simont, Essai sur la quantité, la qualité, la relation chez Kant, Hegel, Deleuze. Les ‘fleurs noires’ de la logique philosophique (Paris, 1997), p. 230. Simont also writes that ‘the continuity of history is the form or the method of deciphering the actual
  • 2. 2 The Logic of Expression In ‘Spinoza et la méthode de Gueroult’, when reviewing Gueroult’s two- volume study of Spinoza,5 Deleuze details those elements of Gueroult’s method of engagement with Spinoza that he considers to have had a profound effect both on contemporary Spinoza studies, and also on the role of the history of philosophy in the contemporary practice of philosophy in general. He argues that ‘Gueroult renewed the history of philosophy by a structural–genetic method, which he had elaborated well before structuralism imposed itself in other domains. Such a structure is defined by an order of reasons, the reasons being differential and generative elements of the corresponding system, veritable philosophemes which only exist in their relations with each other’.6 ‘Gueroult’s admirable book’, he continues, ‘has a double importance, both from the point of view of the general method that it puts to work, and from the point of view of his Spinozism, which does not represent one application of this method among others but rather constitutes the most adequate, the most saturated, the most exhaustive term or object concluding the series on Descartes, Malebranche and Leibniz. This book founds the veritable scientific study of Spinozism’.7 This characterization of the method of Gueroult actually outlines Deleuze’s own philosophical project in Expressionism in Philosophy. It is there that Deleuze undertakes the project of renewing the history of philosophy in relation to Spinoza. The structural–genetic criteria that Deleuze deploys are determined according to a logic of expression, which is elaborated in Difference and Repetition in relation to the differential calculus as a logic of different/ciation. The ‘differential and generative elements’ of this logic exist solely in the differential relations that they have with each other. Expressionism in Philosophy is also doubly important, not only insofar as it too advocates the ‘scientific study of Spinozism’, in particular Spinoza’s relation to mathematics and the differential calculus of Leibniz, but also insofar as it is the final text of a series of works on figures in the history of philosophy: Hume, Nietzsche, Bergson,8 which constitutes Deleuze’s project of renewing the history of philosophy by constructing an alternative lineage in the history of philosophy. With this series of texts Deleuze proposes a new way of reading the figures of the history of philosophy, ‘neither as the possessors of a truth whose reactualization is being attempted, nor as the objects of an infinite “deconstruction”, nor as the occupants of a privileged enclave accessible only to connections of the historian’s reading, the individuation of the systems of which is the material or the discontinuous content’ (p. 231). All citations quoted from French language texts are my translations, unless otherwise indicated. 5 Martial Gueroult, Spinoza (t. I–II, Paris, 1968–74). 6 Deleuze, ‘Spinoza et la méthode générale de Gueroult’, Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale, 74 (1969), p. 426. 7 Ibid., p. 437. 8 Deleuze later returns to this series with a text on Leibniz.
  • 3. Spinoza and the problem of expression 3 the erudite historian, but as interlocutors’ directly implicated in ‘the construction and experimentation of new [modes] of thought’.9 In ‘The encounter with Spinoza’, Macherey critiques Deleuze’s reading of Spinoza by questioning whether it is ‘consistent with the original sense of the work he purports to analyze, or does it rather misrepresent Spinoza’s philosophy’.10 Macherey maintains that Deleuze attempts to ‘introduce a new version of Spinozism that [is] at variance, if not completely at odds, with the model of demonstrative rationality explicitly adopted by Spinoza himself’.11 Macherey is one of the most respected of contemporary Spinoza scholars in France, whose five- volume study of the Ethics, entitled Introduction à l’Ethique de Spinoza,12 attempts, by extracting the persistent difficulties of Spinozism, to establish an internal coherence to the system of the text. However, it is in relation to Hegel’s interpretation of Spinoza that Macherey first distinguished himself as a Spinoza scholar of repute. Chapter 1 examines his first major work on Spinoza, Hegel ou Spinoza,13 which challenges the influence of Hegel’s reading of Spinoza by stressing the degree to which Spinoza eludes the grasp of the Hegelian dialectical progression of the history of philosophy. Macherey argues that Hegel provides a defensive misreading of Spinoza, and that he had to ‘misread him’ in order to maintain his teleological subjective idealism. The suggestion being that Spinoza’s philosophy represents, not a moment that can be simply sublated and subsumed within the dialectical progression of the history of philosophy, but rather an alternative point of view for the development of a philosophy that overcomes Hegelian idealism. Deleuze also considers Spinoza’s philosophy to resist the totalizing effects of the dialectic. Indeed, Deleuze demonstrates, by means of Spinoza, that a more complex philosophy antedates Hegel’s which cannot be supplanted by it. Spinoza therefore becomes a significant figure in Deleuze’s project of tracing an alternative lineage in the history of philosophy, which, by distancing itself from Hegelian idealism, culminates in the construction of a philosophy of difference. Rather than attempting to determine the elements of Deleuze already in Hegel,14 or the adequacy of the Hegelian elements in Deleuze,15 or elaborating a Deleuzian 9 Manola Antonioli, Deleuze et l’histoire de la philosophie (Paris, 1999), p. 10. 10 Pierre Macherey, ‘The encounter with Spinoza’, trans. M. Joughin, in Paul Patton (ed.), Deleuze, A Critical Reader (Oxford and Cambridge, 1996), p. 142. 11 Ibid., p. 141. 12 Pierre Macherey, Introduction à l’Ethique de Spinoza (t. I–V, Paris, 1994–98). 13 Pierre Macherey, Hegel ou Spinoza (Paris, 1979). 14 Pierre Verstraten recognizes in ‘the thought of Hegel … an unexpected premonition of that of Deleuze’, see ‘La question du negative chez Deleuze’, Gilles Deleuze (Paris, 1998), p. 176. 15 Is Deleuze’s Hegel perhaps too Kojèvian? See Simont, p. 276.
  • 4. 4 The Logic of Expression Hegel or a Hegelian Deleuze,17 or, on the contrary, claiming that ‘no encounter is 16 possible’,18 an alternative approach to the determination of the relation between Deleuze and Hegel is to read their respective interpretations of Spinoza, and the role that they each assign to Spinoza in the development of their respective philosophical projects, together, alongside of each other, and also in direct relation to each other. This strategy entails examining those points of convergence between the elements of their respective interpretations of Spinoza, in order then to determine what sets them radically apart. It is in the logic of the relations established between the elements of their respective interpretations of Spinoza that this radical difference is manifested, and it is by means of the determination of this difference in logic between their respective interpretations of Spinoza that the difference in the logic of their respective philosophical projects in general is determined. Spinoza’s role in this strategy is demonstrated in chapter 2 by differentiating Deleuze’s interpretation of the geometrical example of Spinoza’s Letter XII (on the problem of the infinite) from that which Hegel presents in the Science of Logic.19 Both Hegel and Deleuze each position the geometrical example at different stages in the early development of the differential calculus. By demonstrating the relation between ‘the differential point of view of the infinitesimal calculus’ and the differential calculus of contemporary mathematics, it is argued in chapter 3 that Deleuze effectively bypasses the methods of the differential calculus which Hegel uses to support the development of the dialectical logic. By exploiting the implications of the differential point of view of the infinitesimal calculus in his interpretation of the physics of bodies in the second part of the Ethics, Deleuze is able to read the system of the Ethics as a whole as determined according to the logic of different/ciation. The explication of this reading strategy is what constitutes the Deleuzian reading of Expressionism in Philosophy that is undertaken in the present work. This strategy of reading the Ethics as determined according to a logic of different/ciation marks not only the originality of Deleuze’s interpretation of Spinoza, but also one of the points where Deleuze can be considered to depart from the Cartesian and Hegelian Spinoza familiar to scholars 16 Juliette Simont actually argues that Deleuze’s Hegel is perhaps too ‘Hegelian’, ‘a terribly Hegelian Hegel’, and proposes instead another Hegel, ‘the other Hegel’, who ‘is perhaps too Deleuzian, or is only possible when read across Deleuze’ (Ibid., p. 297). 17 Catherine Malabou, in ‘Who’s afraid of Hegelian Wolves?’ (Patton, Deleuze, A Critical Reader), argues that ‘doing justice to Deleuze’s finely wrought thinking concerning affirmation implies, in my opinion, affirming Hegel’s role in it’ (p. 136). 18 Manola Antonioli, in Deleuze et l’histoire de la philosophie, argues that ‘with Hegel … no encounter is possible: the recourse to the negative and to contradiction is irreconcilable with the affirmative presuppositions of the Deleuzian philosophy, there is nothing “to put together” between Deleuze and Hegel’ (p. 80). 19 G.W.F. Hegel, Hegel’s Science of Logic, trans. A.V. Miller (London, 1969), p. 251.
  • 5. Spinoza and the problem of expression 5 working in the field of Spinoza studies by tracing an alternative lineage in the history of philosophy between Spinoza’s ontology and the mathematics of Leibniz. One of the recurring critiques of Deleuze’s reading of Spinoza in Expressionism in Philosophy is that the Deleuzian concepts inspired by Spinozist ideas are nowhere to be found in the text of the Ethics. Macherey conducts his critique of Expressionism in Philosophy in ‘The encounter with Spinoza’ by disputing such Deleuzian concepts, in particular the concept of ‘joyful passive affections’, which is addressed in chapter 7, and the concept of ‘expression’, which is addressed in chapter 10. In quality and quantity in the philosophy of Spinoza, Charles Ramond disputes Deleuze’s use of the concept of ‘intensive quantity’ in Expressionism in Philosophy. He argues that ‘we can … only be surprised to see Deleuze make the notion of “intensive quantity” the foundation of his interpretation of Spinoza’s theory of the essence of singular things, as if Spinoza had effectively supported such a position’. In relation to the concept of ‘intensity’ and to that of ‘intensive parts’ Ramond argues that: ‘According to Deleuze, Spinoza locates, by using the notion of “intensity”, “a long Scholastic tradition”, of which only “Scotism”, without more precision, is evoked’; and that ‘When Deleuze … declares that, in Spinoza, “modal essences are … intensive parts”, he utters an assertion strictly incomprehensible within the framework of Spinozism’.20 However, these Deleuzian concepts are, more often than not, considered and criticized for themselves, independently of the context which supports their exposition because of its extremely technical character. It is by means of these concepts in Expressionism in Philosophy that Deleuze shifts the reading of the philosophy of Spinoza onto an entirely different terrain. Rather than reading the philosophy of Spinoza either solely in relation to Descartes, or simply as one stage in the dialectical progression of the history of philosophy, Deleuze reads the philosophy of Spinoza insofar as it contributes to the construction of an alternative lineage in the history of philosophy, which features the work of Duns Scotus, in particular the concept of formal distinction, the concept of the univocity of being and the concept of individuality. Deleuze does not read Spinoza as a Scotist, but rather, by reading Scotus alongside of Spinoza, he examines Spinoza’s reformulation of these Scotist concepts in order to develop those aspects of Spinoza’s philosophy that are specifically Anticartesian. The mechanism by means of which Deleuze does this is elaborated in chapter 4. This Anticartesian reading of Spinoza provides the framework for the development of a reading of Spinoza that challenges the Hegelian concept of the dialectical progression of the history of philosophy. The Deleuzian domain of engagement with Spinoza is determined therefore by deterritorializing a fairly traditional reading of Spinoza from a particularly 20 Charles Ramond, qualité et quantité dans la philosophie de Spinoza (Paris, 1995), p. 201.
  • 6. 6 The Logic of Expression Cartesian and Hegelian point of view, to that of a more Scotist and even Leibnizian point of view, thereby determining an alternative lineage in the history of philosophy. Deleuze considers Spinoza’s Ethics to have given expression to the concept of individuality, whose themes can be found scattered among several other authors of the seventeenth century: for Deleuze’s purposes most notably in the work of Duns Scotus. In relation to the concept of individuality, the Hegelian categories of quantity, quality and relation, which articulate differences in the distances or dimensions of things (quantity), in their nature (quality), and in their order (relation), are considered by Deleuze to be antedated by the three different dimensions of the individual as presented by Spinoza, namely relation, power (quantity), and mode (quality). The individual is characterized as relation insofar as there is a composition of individuals in relation to one another, or amongst themselves. In chapter 2 it is argued that the infinitesimal calculus puts into play a certain type of relation for Deleuze – the differential relation – which is characteristic of the compositional relations between individuals. The characterization of the individual as power (potentia) indicates the individual’s capacity to compose new relations with other individuals. The concept of potentia, which is translated by the concept of power as force or capacity, is different to that of potestas, which is translated by power in the juridico–political sense of the term,21 insofar as it expresses that which an individual body can do, and which is verified by joy. Composition therefore refers not only to the characteristic relations between individuals, but also to the capacity or potential to create these kinds of relations, the mechanism of which is determined as operating according to the logic of different/ciation, and is elaborated in chapter 3. The third dimension of the individual is characterized as mode, which Deleuze considers to be expressive of the Scotist concept of an ‘intrinsic mode’. Deleuze’s characterization of the ‘intrinsic mode’ of an individual as the ‘intensive part’, or singular modal essence, of an individual, or of its corresponding finite existing mode, is elaborated in chapter 4. The mechanism by means of which intensive parts are distinguished not only from one another, but also from the extensive parts corresponding to them, is determined as operating according to the logic of different/ciation. The question of how the intensive parts of different individuals are differentiated from one another as more or less powerful is then investigated in chapter 5. Chapter 6 raises the question of whether the power, or capacity, of an individual, which Deleuze characterizes as its power to act, should be understood to be fixed or variable, and 21 Eugene Holland notes that Martial Gueroult, in his two-volume study of Spinoza, is one of the first to demonstrate the importance of the distinction between potentia and potestas in Spinoza (Holland, ‘Spinoza and Marx’, Cultural Logic, 2.1 (Fall, 1998), §29). For a thorough examination of the social and political implications of this distinction in relation to Spinoza see Antonio Negri, The Savage Anomaly: the power of Spinoza’s metaphysics and politics, trans. M. Hardt (Minneapolis, 1991).
  • 7. Spinoza and the problem of expression 7 how such a power to act is implicated in the transformations of the characteristic relations determinative of an individual. Deleuze’s disputed distinction of passions into joyful passive affections and sad passive affections is elaborated in chapter 7, as is the manner by means of which joyful passive affections are pivotal in determining the transition from inadequate ideas of the imagination to adequate ideas of reason. Chapter 8 investigates in detail the mechanism by means of which joyful passive affections are implicated in the dynamic changes or transformations of the characteristic relations determinative of an individual by mapping the mathematical concept of accumulation onto the ontological concept of the accumulation of joyful passive affections, such that there are ‘correspondences without resemblance’ that ‘are of a structural–genetic nature’22 between them, that is, insofar as both are determined as operating according to the logic of different/ciation. The distinction between the duration of an individual, or of its finite modal existence, and its eternity is investigated in chapter 9, where the thesis that occupies the fifth part of the Ethics which deals with the relation between death and the eternity of the soul according to the third kind of knowledge, and which is often mistaken for a discussion advocating the immortality of the soul, is developed. That which concerns the concept of eternity in the Ethics has interested scholars and commentators since the earliest interpretations of Spinoza, which were used either to reinforce piety by espousing one’s opposition to Spinoza’s atheism, or, on the contrary, and more rarely, to justify one’s pantheism by defending Spinozism.23 These studies often took the form of demonstrating that the thesis on eternity in part five was incoherent with that of the preceding parts of the Ethics, notably with the principle of parallelism. This aspect of the Ethics is still widely disputed among scholars working in the field of Spinoza studies. My contention is that Deleuze’s argument from powers, which is explicated in chapter 9 according to the logic of different/ciation, demonstrates an alternative approach that allows a better comprehension of the coherence between the different parts of the Ethics. The logic of different/ciation is therefore determinative not only of the mechanism by means of which joyful passive affections operate in Deleuze’s reading of the Ethics, but it is also the logic that is determinative of Deleuze’s reading of the system of the Ethics as a whole. The project of the present work is to develop an understanding of Deleuze’s Spinoza by providing a Deleuzian reading of Expressionism in Philosophy, which involves not only determining the mechanism of operation of the logic of 22 Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, p. 184. 23 For an account of the multiple conflicting readings of Spinoza’s early interpreters see Frederick C. Beiser, The fate of reason: German philosophy from Kant to Fichte (Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1987).
  • 8. 8 The Logic of Expression different/ciation in Expressionism in Philosophy, but also involves positioning Deleuze’s Spinoza, and the logic with which it is explicated, within the context of the development of Deleuze’s wider philosophical project. Such a Deleuzian reading of Expressionism in Philosophy is therefore important for the determination of the way in which Spinoza becomes for Deleuze a significant figure in his project of tracing an alternative lineage in the history of philosophy, and serves well to situate Expressionism in Philosophy within the context of Deleuze’s project of constructing a philosophy of difference. The context of this dual Deleuzian project is explicated in chapter 10 in relation to Deleuze’s other major text from the same period, Difference and Repetition. It is in Difference and Repetition, in relation to the Scotist concept of the univocity of being, that Deleuze specifically positions Spinoza as a significant figure in the project of tracing an alternative lineage in the history of philosophy. He argues that there are ‘three principal moments in the history of the philosophical elaboration of the univocity of being’,24 which he locates respectively in the work of Scotus, Spinoza and Nietzsche. My argument in chapter 10 is that this alternative lineage in the history of philosophy only makes sense in relation to the demands of a concept of temporality that is determined according to the logic of different/ciation. In What is Philosophy?, Deleuze claims that ‘philosophy is the discipline that involves creating concepts’.25 The manner by means of which concepts are created is determined by the encounters between the concepts belonging to philosophies of the past which generate the problems of which the new concepts are the solution. The concepts of philosophies of the past, to which Deleuze refers, are determined in relation to the history of philosophy and include, for example, the Scotist concept of univocity, the Spinozist concept of Substance as immanent cause, and the Nietzschean concept of the eternal return. It is by means of the encounters between these concepts (of the past) that, on the one hand, new concepts are created, and that, on the other hand, the problem, onto which each of these concepts (of the past) is grafted, is generated. The determination of these concepts (of the past) and of the manner by means of which the encounters between them create new concepts and generate problems is explicated in chapter 10 according to the logic of different/ciation. The concept of expression and the concept of intensity are two other concepts whose explication is pivotal in determining the manner by means of which Deleuze reads the Ethics in Expressionism in Philosophy. What is expression? And what is the relation between Spinoza’s Ethics and the concept of expression explicated by Deleuze in Expressionism in Philosophy? These questions are addressed in chapter 10 where I contend that it is in relation to the concept of expression that the logic 24 Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, p. 39. 25 Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, What is Philosophy?, trans. H. Tomlinson and G. Burchell (New York, 1994), p. 5.
  • 9. Spinoza and the problem of expression 9 of different/ciation is explicated in the text of Expressionism in Philosophy as a logic of expression. It is according to the logic of expression that the Spinozist concept of Substance as immanent cause and the Nietzschean concept of the eternal return are problematized in relation to one another in Difference and Repetition, thereby creating the Deleuzian concept of intensity. It is by means of the development of the problematic relation between the Deleuzian concept of intensity, which is determined according to the logic of expression, and the concept of intensity determined rather by the Hegelian dialectical logic, that the logic of expression is determined as an alternative to the Hegelian dialectical logic. Insofar as the logic of expression is determined as the logic according to which the philosophy of difference is constructed, it functions not only as an alternative to the Hegelian dialectical logic, but it is also determined as the logic according to which the philosophy of difference functions as an alternative to the dialectical philosophy determined by the Hegelian dialectical logic. Deleuze’s reading of Spinoza in Expressionism in Philosophy therefore redeploys Spinoza in relation to an alternative lineage in the history of philosophy in order to mobilize his philosophy of difference as an alternative to the dialectical philosophy determined by the Hegelian dialectical logic. While acknowledging some of the problematical elements of Deleuze’s challenging interpretation of Spinoza, the central focus of the work remains an examination of the manner by means of which Spinoza is mobilized by Deleuze in his project of constructing a philosophy of difference. The reading of Deleuze’s philosophy that is presented in the present work is therefore resolutely partial. Neither the implications of Deleuze’s Spinozism for understanding his other works, nor the extent to which these are influenced by his Spinozism is treated in any great detail. Indeed when certain of these texts are nevertheless referred to, it is solely in order to better determine the schema of problematization associated with the development of the logic of expression in Expressionism in Philosophy, or serves merely to suggest the implications of such a development for Deleuze’s subsequent works. As for the latter, rather than suggesting in detail the full range of potential implications, that which is suggested is solely the manner by means of which these implications are determined, that is, that they too are determinable according to the logic of expression. For example, the present work concludes by suggesting the implications of the logic of expression for determining an understanding of the relation between, what Deleuze and Guattari refer to in What is Philosophy? as, a philosophy’s plane of immanence, and the concepts created by this philosophy that are distributed over this plane.