SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 12
Download to read offline
Peter Bornedal, General Lecture, 203
• Kant lived in the Prussian city Königsberg his entire life. He never traveled, and
                              is famous for his methodic and rigorous lifestyle and high work ethics. He would
                              begin his lecture-schedule seven o’clock in the morning (and was so popular with
                              students that they had to arrive an hour early to secure themselves a seat). As he
                              raised to fame, scholars from all over Europe would travel to Königsberg to see
                              him lecturing. It is said that the lectures that preceded the work we are reading,
                              Grounding of a Metaphysics of Morals, were so gripping to the audience that they
                              felt they were listening to a revelation.
                              • After work, Kant would have his famous afternoon walk, being so punctual
                              about this exercise that the German writer Heinrich Heine once quipped that the
                              wives of Königsberg adjusted their clocks after him passing by.
                              • Kant was never married; nor did he have – as far as we know – any kind of
                              romantic relationship. This methodic, monotonous, and rigorous life might indicate
                              a rather dry personality, but apparently he was not. Anecdote has is that Kant
                              was an entertaining, engaging, and witty conversationalist. He seems to have
                              been popular as a guest in the better society, and seems to have had a good
                              sense of humor – although we admittedly do not find much humor in his
                              philosophical work.


• Kant is undoubtedly regarded as one, if not the greatest, of
Germany’s philosophers. He has dealt with almost all
aspects of philosophy and even science. His three so-called
“Critiques” – Critique of Pure Reason, Critique of Practical
Reason, and Critique of Judgment – deal respectively with
the three most important branches of philosophy:
Knowledge/Mind, Ethics/Morals, and Aesthetics. Besides
these works, he wrote important treatises about physics,
astronomy, logic, religion, anthropology, politics, and                                      Kant
education.                                                           Kant Lecturing
• Kant wrote on Ethics and Morals in four different works. His first preliminary       Quotations:
study is the Grounding of a Metaphysics of Morals (1785), which we read.
Thereupon follows his Critique of Practical Reason (1788). About ten years later       Even if there never have
he publishes his Metaphysics of Morals (1797), and finally one year later his          been action springing
Anthropology from a Pragmatic point of view (1798).                                    from       such      pure
• In the three first works, moral behavior has a strictly ideal formulation. Kant      sources, the question
wants to set up moral principles that are ideal, meaning they are not meant to         at issue here is not
describe actual human behavior. In the last work, ethical behavior is studied from     whether this or that has
a practical perspective, meaning that he studies actual human behavior – not           happened but that
ideal principles that ought to regulate human behavior. The first three works deal     reason of itself and
with ethics from a metaphysical point of view, while the last work deals with          independently of all
ethics from an anthropological.                                                        experience commands
• When one studies metaphysics of moral, one sets out to determine the general         what ought to happen.
and universal principles that have to guide moral action, whether or not people        (Kant, ibid., p. 19)
actually follow these principles.
                                                                                       They      [philosophers
• We can illustrate the idea with a couple of examples taken from Kant himself.        advocating self-interest
Kant says: “even if there has never existed a sincere friend, sincerity in             and self-love as basic
friendship is an idea that is still required of every man.” Or “even if an unselfish
act has never been performed, unselfishness is still the ideal for moral action.”      human motives] have
                                                                                       spoken with sincere
• So, even if the motives for our actions are impure and selfish, Kant’s moral         regret as to the frailty
theory prevails, because it deals with what ought to be the case. Moral law does       and impurity of human
not depend on experience, but on reason. Moral principles must be grounded in          nature, which they
pure a priori concepts, not mixed with anything empirical.                             think is noble enough
• Kant claims that even if ideal moral principles are rarely or never carried out,     to take as its precept
we always presuppose these principles. For example, 1) when we lament how              an idea so worthy of
corruptible and dishonest the human being is, we spontaneously presuppose              respect but yet is too
integrity and honesty as ideal regulatory principles – principles that ought to        weak to follow his ideal
regulate human behavior; 2) in the image we form of God as all-benevolent, we          reason, which should
presuppose ideal moral principles. God is in his essence, what we can only             legislate for human
strive to be in our existence. We cannot be all-benevolent like God, but we can
set up benevolence as an ideal, and we do so in the image we form of God.              nature. (Kant, ibid., p.
                                                                                       19)
• The upshot is, we may not believe in the actual execution of ideal moral
principles; still, Kant insists, we always presuppose that they ought to exist.
According to Kant, we are endowed with two
                                                                          essentially different kinds of knowledge:
                                                                          scientific knowledge and moral knowledge.
• The reason why we so often do not follow ideal                          Scientific knowledge studies the laws of nature
regulatory principles, which we ought to follow, is that we               of the external world; moral knowledge studies
as humans have a free will. If we were objects, we would                  the laws of freedom of the internal world. In
not have a choice. A stone cannot decide whether or not it
wants to follow the laws of nature, but as subjects we can                Scientific knowledge one studies causes. In
choose not the follow the laws of morals. Because of our                  Moral knowledge one studies motives. Both
freedom of the will, the metaphysical ethical laws Kant                   kinds of knowledge have their own kinds of a
deduces as applying specifically to human beings are not                  priori laws. In his work, Critique of Practical
laws of nature, but laws of freedom.
                                                                          Reason, Kant states.
• In his work, Critique of Pure Reason, Kant had been                     “Two things fill the mind with ever new and increasing
studying the ‘laws of nature.’ These he would separate in                 admiration and reverence, the more often and more steadily
an empirical part and a rational part. The empirical part
would consist of sensations, and the rational part of the                 one reflects one them: the starry heavens above me and the
so-called categories of understanding. The categories                     moral law within me. I do not need to search for them and
were in themselves abstract or pure, and they acquired an                 merely conjecture them as though they were veiled in obscurity
empirical content before they could be applied to and                     or in the transcendent region beyond my horizon; I see them
make sense of the world of appearances.                                   before me and connect them immediately with the
• Without getting into Kant’s epistemological work, we                    consciousness of my existence. The first begins from the place I
notice that when Kant in his ethical work studies so-called               occupy in the external world of sense { . . . ] the second begins
‘laws of freedom,’ also these laws have an empirical and                  from my invisible self, my personality, and presents me in a
rational part. Addressing the empirical part, one studies                 world with has true infinity but which can be discovered only by
how people actually behave (like in Anthropology,
Psychology, Sociology, or History). Addressing the rational               the understanding, and I cognize that my connection with that
part, one studies how people ideally ought to behave (like                world [ . . . ] is not merely contingent, as in the first case, but
in Metaphysics of Morals).                                                universal and necessary. The first view of a countless multitude
• We can set the Kantian distinctions up in this table:                   of worlds annihilates, as it were, my importance as an animal
                                                                          creature, which must give back to the planet (a mere speck in
                      Empirical part (Sensations)                         the universe) the matter from which it came. The second, on the
Laws of nature -- Physics                                                 contrary, infinitely raises my worth as an intelligence by my
                     Rational part (Categories)
                                                                          personality, in which the moral law reveals to me a life
Empirical part (How people actually do behave)                            independent of animality and even of the whole sensible
Laws of freedom -- Ethics                                                 world.” (Kant: Critique of Practical Reason, Cambridge
                     Rational part (How people ideally ought to behave)   University Press; p. 133-34.)
• That a moral imperative is a priori implies that it applies to all peoples in all histories, and under all
circumstances, whether or not they live by it or obey it. It is a priori because it is already part of our rational
constitution; Kant therefore only “deduces” (i.e., he articulates and makes explicit) what is already there as
implicitly known. The result of the ‘deduction,’ the abstract moral law, can therefore also not be an object for
discussion or negotiation. Universal moral law is part of our implicit rational knowledge, which we as such ‘know’
is true as rational beings.
• Kant starts his deduction of pure morals by asserting such an unconditional moral law (something we all
‘know’ is true when it is made explicit to us): “There is no possibility of thinking of anything at all in the
world, or even out of it, which can be regarded as good without qualification, expect a good will.” (Kant,
Grounding of a Metaphysics of Moral, p. 7.)
• This is Kant’s first example of an unconditional moral law: the good will. Notice here that Kant does not
suggest any specific quality as moral, as numerous other moral philosophers have done, such as honor,
generosity, self-control, intelligence, courage, perseverance, fortune, wealth, etc. Only the good will can qualify
as moral law, because without the background-motivation of a ‘good will’ all the qualities mentioned above –
generosity, self-control, intelligence, etc. – can be abused, or may have been executed for selfish purposes.
• Two examples: A) If a man is generous because he expects something in return, he is generous for selfish
purposes, not out of a purely good will. B) A villain in perfect self-control is not a virtuous man acting with ‘good
will,’ but rather a more dangerous villain. The same applies if he is courageous, intelligent, etc.
• Therefore Kant continues that a good will is good not because it effects some end, or achieves some personal
benefit or profit. It must be “good in itself”: “A good will is good not because of what it effects or
accomplishes, nor because of its fitness to attain some proposed end; it is good only through its willing,
i.e., it is good in itself.” [ . . . ] “[The will] is not merely good as a means to some further end, but is good
in itself.” (Kant, ibid., p. 7 & 9.)
• Because we have a “freedom of the will” we can influence and direct our will; we can choose between willing
an action that is a means to some further end, or willing an action that is good in itself.
• If we act with an unconditional good will, even if our action achieves nothing, or perhaps achieves the
 opposite of what we intended, our action has a moral content. The ‘good will’ shall “shine by its own light as
 something which has its full power in itself.” (Kant, ibid., p. 8.)
 • It seems that intention has become the quintessential criteria for the morality of an action; it seems as if,
 insofar as we act with the intention to do good, our action has moral content.
 • Is now a ‘good will’ identical to ‘good intentions’? – Well, not quite! -- And why not? – Because the
 definition would be redundant and meaningless! One cannot explain a good will with good intentions,
 because it is the same thing. Kant wants to deduce universal moral principles, he wants to know what is
 inherent in exhibiting ‘good will.’ If a ‘good will’ simply were to have ‘good intentions,’ he would still need to
 explain what is inherent is exhibiting ‘good intentions.’ His problem would not have been solved; it would
 not have gone away.
 • Furthermore, if a ‘good will’ were reducible to ‘good intentions,’ we would be referring to a psychologically
 determined ‘good will’ rooted in a compassionate subject. But the moral principle cannot be determined
 from neither individual psychology, nor from compassion. The moral principle is formal and universal, never
 concrete and individual; and it is rooted in reason, never passions.
 • The upshot is, forget the compassionate subject – the ‘warm heart,’ as Nietzsche often puts it in his
 somewhat misunderstood mockery of Kantian positions.

Forget the following equation:
        The ‘Warm Heart’/the Compassionate Subject = Good Intentions = Good Will → Moral Action
Apply instead the following deduction:
        Freedom of the Will  Respect for Universal Law  Duty toward Maxims Prescribed by Law
                                       Good Will  Moral Action
• Let us first explain what is meant by the statement above
• What is it to ‘act from duty’? – It is 1) to act, not just according to a law, but also for the sake of a law that
transcends the individual (that is, for the sake of a formal principle, not a psychological principle, like the ‘warm
heart’). 2) it is to act contrary to inclinations (desires, self-interests, personal benefits, profit, etc.). 3) It is to
adopt an action because reason commands of us this course of action (not because passions or compassions
urge us on).
• What is a maxim? – A maxim is a brief articulation of an instruction that the individual follows in his action.
• What is Law? – Law is the set of imperatives prescribing moral actions. Moral Laws are always categorical,
meaning that they are not up for discussion or negotiation. Metaphorically speaking, moral laws are as if carved
in stone, like the Ten Commandments Moses brings down from Mount Sinai. However, the Ten Commandments
are divine rules of conduct, while Kant’s categorical imperatives are rational rules of conduct.
• In order to illustrate his principle, ‘acting from duty,’ Kant gives us four different examples of action, where only
the last has moral content. One is contrary to duty; two are in accordance with duty but are still performed
because of self-interests; only the last is performed ‘from duty’ and ‘contrary to inclination.’ Only the last
qualifies as truly moral. The four examples are the following:
1) Some actions are contrary to duty, and performed out of self-interest and inclination, like stealing, cheating,
lying, etc. Obviously, they are not moral.
2) Other actions are performed according to duty, but because of some mediate self-interest. A person pays his
taxes on time according to duty, but he knows that he thus avoid fines, and society gives him back various
social benefits. He acts according to duty, but not from a duty free of self-interest, and is thus not a true moral
subject.
3) Other actions are performed according to duty, but because of some immediate self-interest. If a man does
not commit suicide, he acts according to duty, but if he loves his live, he also acts according to inclination. He
never contemplated suicide since he is happy and everything is going well. Thus, he preserves his life
according to duty, but not from a duty free of self-interest, and is thus not a true moral subject.
4) Finally, there are actions, which are in accordance with duty, and moreover, are performed from duty contrary
to inclination. These are true moral actions, whose maxims constitute the subject as moral.
• Whether one acts ‘according to’ or ‘from’           • In this Kantian definition, there is no room for the ‘warm
duty, one acts out of respect for Law. But only       heart.’ If a ‘warmhearted’ man enjoys spreading joy and
actions done ‘from duty’ have moral content,          happiness around, he is acting according to duty (and
because they are done ‘for the sake of’ duty,         certainly, nobody blames him), but his action has the
without considerations of inclinations or             characteristics of the third case above: he acts according to
personal benefits.                                    duty, but also according to immediate inclination.
• They are done out of nothing but pure               Therefore, his action has no true moral content.
respect for Law.                                      • If on the contrary, this man, in his personal life carries
• Notice that a so-called ‘good will’ is a rational   great sorrows, but nonetheless still has the power to
will to respect Law, with no other motives than       benefit and spread joy among others, then his action is
respect for Law.                                      performed from duty contrary to inclination, and it has a
                                                      true moral content.
“Duty is the necessity of an action done out          “If adversity and hopeless sorrow have completely
of respect for the law. [ . . . ] Hence there is      taken away the taste for life, if an unfortunate man,
nothing left which can determine the will             strong in soul and more indignant at his fate than
except objectively the law and subjectively           despondent or dejected, wishes for death and yet
pure respect for this practical law, i.e. the         preserves his life without loving it – not from inclination
will can be subjectively determined by the            or fear, but from duty – then his maxim indeed has a
maxim that I should follow such a law even            moral content.” [ . . . ] “Even though no inclination
if all my inclinations are thereby thwarted. [        moves him any longer, he nevertheless tears himself
. . . ] The pre-eminent good which is called          from this deadly insensibility and performs the action
moral can consist in nothing but the                  without any inclination at all, but solely from duty –
representation of the law in itself.” (Kant,          then for the first time his action has genuine moral
ibid., p. 12-13).                                     worth.” (Kant, ibid., p. 10 & 11)
• We have learnt that to act with a ‘good will’ is to act from, ‘for the sake of,’ duty in respect for Law and nothing
but Law. From this deduction, Kant formulates his famous categorical imperative. In its first formulation, it reads:
“Since I have deprived the will of every impulse that might arise for it from obeying any particular law,
there is nothing left to serve the will as principle except the universal conformity of its actions to law as
such, i.e., I should never act except in such a way that I can also will that my maxim should become a
universal law.” (Kant, ibid., p. 14.)
• Kant’s example: “when I am in distress, may I make a promise with the intention of not keeping it.” In other
words, is it okay under some circumstances to lie? – Now, one might argue that a person should avoid lying,
because it would be detrimental to him in the long run. A lying shopkeeper would eventually be exposed, and
thus loose customers. The argument presupposes that one should be truthful because of some ends or
consequences; it presupposes a so-called ‘hypothetical imperative,’ an if-then relation: if I don’t lie, then my
business will thrive, and I will prosper: if I do so and so, then I will achieve this or that.
• Therefore, a hypothetical imperative is not ‘categorical.’ it is not unconditional, universal, and absolute. A
‘categorical imperative’ is asserted out of respect for Law, without other concerns. A hypothetical imperative is
asserted out of concerns for benefits or profits. It does not determine the moral content of an act.
• So, now we ask again, but from the perspective of the categorical imperative, is it okay under some
circumstances to lie? – The answer is still ‘no,’ but with a different explanation. Observing the categorical
imperative, I avoid lying because of respect for universal Law. My reason tells me that lying cannot be accepted
as universal Law. My reason tells me that if I will lying as universal Law, then I will everybody to lie, and then it
is no longer possible to make promises at all. Under the obligation of a universal law to lie, every promise is a
contradiction in terms. “I immediately become aware that I can indeed will the lie but can not at all will a
universal law to lie. For by such a law there would really be no promises at all, since in vain would my
willing future actions be professed to other people who would not believe what I professed, or if they
overhastily did believe, then they would pay me back in like coin.” (Kant, ibid., p. 15).
• If now I do not will a universal law to lie, then I must admit that neither do I will my first proposal: may I make a
promise with the intention not to keep it. I must reject this proposal. Therefore, when one ‘respects law,’ one
does not respect a particular law, but a law requesting universal validity in an action.
Imperatives says that something would be good to do or to refrain from doing, but they say it to a will that
does not always therefore do something simply because it has been represented to the will as something
good to do. That is practically good which determines the will by means of representations or reason and
hence not by subjective causes, but objectively, i.e.. on grounds valid for every rational being as such.
(Kant , ibid., p. 24).
• What is here established is that we have wills, meaning that we have the choice to follow a rational decision or
not. If purely subjective interests determine this choice, it is not a moral choice, but if our will be governed by
objective moral laws, then we are following, not personal interests, but an imperative.
• We can only rationally choose moral imperatives, because our wills in themselves are not moral, rational, or
objective. We are not gods, and we have no holy wills, we have only human wills. If we were gods, we would
not need moral imperatives.
• In the categorical imperative, the so-called maxim of the action (i.e., the instruction as articulated to the
subject describing the action) should conform to universal law. In this conformity the maxim makes itself into a
universal law. This correspondence or conformity is alone what is necessary by the imperative, therefore there
is only one imperative and it reads (in two different versions):
Act only according to that maxim whereby you can at the same time will that it should become a
universal law. [ . . . ] Act as if the maxim of your action were to become through your will a universal law
of nature. ( Kant, ibid., p. 30)
• An example of Kant’s: A suicidal man! – Is he allowed or not to take his own life according to the categorical
imperative? His duty to himself is to preserve his life. If he decides to commit suicide he does so because it is
an easy way out of a life of suffering. Thus he commits suicide out of self-love. “I end my life out of self-love’”
becomes the maxim of his action. Now he must ask himself whether this maxim could become “a universal law
of nature.” Here he realizes that ‘suicide from self-love’ could never be a universal law of nature, because it
would imply a contradiction. If his maxim is universalized, self-love, which normally is to preserve life, is
determined as destruction of life, and we are under a universal obligation to destroy our lives – which is absurd.
Human Autonomy as Moral Imperative
• Even if I tell a lie, I presuppose that one has an universal moral obligation to tell the truth, because I calculate
and expect that the one to whom I lie believes I tell the truth. I tell the lie believing in universal law; I just don’t
apply this universal law to myself.
• In that case, I am using my fellow human being as a means to further my personal ends. While lying I recognize
that I am using the other person merely as a means.
• This cannot be permitted, because in all cases where I use another rational being for my own ends, the maxims
of the actions cannot be universalized. The maxim, ‘I shall use another rational being in order to further my own
end,’ cannot become an “universal law of nature,” because we would then place ourselves under a universal
obligation to deprive ourselves of our rationality; that is, our free will to rationally choose different courses of action
– and again, that is absurd. A rational being is characterized by its ability to make choices, according to the
“practical law of freedom.” If I deprive a person of this ability, I deprive him of the “freedom of his will.”
• The categorical imperative therefore has another famous formulation, namely that one must always use another
rational being as an end in himself, never as a means (it Is often referred to as Kant’s “Principle of Humanity”):
“Rational nature exists as an end in itself. [ . . . ] The practical imperative will thus be as follows: so act as
to treat humanity, whether in your own person or in that of any other, always at the same time as an end
and never merely as a means.” . . . “Persons must exist as ends in themselves. [ . . . ] Such an end is one for
which there can be substituted no other end to which such beings should serve merely as means, for
otherwise nothing at all of absolute value would be found anywhere.” (Kant, ibid., p. 36).

• According to this formulation of the categorical imperative, one always has a duty to use both oneself and
another person as ends in themselves, never as means. Kant’s suicidal man is for example using himself as a
‘means’ – which is not permitted:
“If he destroys himself in order to escape from a difficult situation, then he is making use of his person
merely as a means so as to maintain a tolerable condition till the end of his life. Man, however, is not a
thing and hence is not something to be used merely as a means; he must in all his actions always be
regarded as an end in himself.” (Kant, ibid., p. 36).
• In his ‘deductions’ of the moral imperatives, Kant
 The Kingdom of Ends:     presupposes that Man is capable of self-legislation – that is,
Kant as the First Human   we are able to give laws to ourselves, which we are able
                          thereupon to follow.
  Rights Philosopher      • We are able to make laws and choose to follow them
                          thanks to our free will. We are not subjected to natural laws
                          (in which case we are without choice in moral matters), but
                          to ‘practical laws of freedom.’
                          • This freedom from natural laws in the human being must
                          be preserved. Humans can only be subjected to ‘practical
                          laws,’ and these laws are always of their own making. They
                          are self-legislative and are thus testimonies of our free will.
                          • If therefore ‘practical laws’ are fashioned as ‘natural laws’
                          it indicates a perversion of reason, and a violation of human
                          freedom.
                          • If a dictator dictates laws as if they were laws of nature,
                          his maxim cannot be universalized, because it contradicts
                          human freedom as such. The human being is a priori free or
                          autonomous. This freedom cannot be violated.
                          • Because of this fundamental autonomy, humans must
                          never be deprived of their freedom to make rational
                          decisions. They must always be treated as ends, and we
                          must legislate as if we all belonged to a “Kingdom of Ends,”
                          a society where we are free and have equal rights.
                          • There can be no ‘scientific proof’ of this deduction,
                          because it transcend the bounds of possible experience. It
                          belongs to the noumenal, not to the phenomenal, world. It
                          transcends the apparent world. Still, it nevertheless has
                          existence as “regulative idea.”

More Related Content

What's hot

Metaphysics
MetaphysicsMetaphysics
Metaphysicssatu12
 
Ontology Powerpoint
Ontology PowerpointOntology Powerpoint
Ontology PowerpointARH_Miller
 
Ch2ppt velasquez12
Ch2ppt velasquez12Ch2ppt velasquez12
Ch2ppt velasquez12dborcoman
 
Biografi Immanuel Kant - Seorang Filsuf
Biografi Immanuel Kant - Seorang FilsufBiografi Immanuel Kant - Seorang Filsuf
Biografi Immanuel Kant - Seorang FilsufTeuku Ichsan
 
Classic and Modern Philosophy: Rationalism and Empicism
Classic and Modern Philosophy: Rationalism and EmpicismClassic and Modern Philosophy: Rationalism and Empicism
Classic and Modern Philosophy: Rationalism and EmpicismMusfera Nara Vadia
 
The branches of philosophy pdf
The branches of philosophy pdfThe branches of philosophy pdf
The branches of philosophy pdfMary Lee Harsha
 
Ch1ppt velasquez12
Ch1ppt velasquez12Ch1ppt velasquez12
Ch1ppt velasquez12dborcoman
 
L4 critique of pure reason
L4 critique of pure reasonL4 critique of pure reason
L4 critique of pure reasonArnel Rivera
 
History of Western modern Philosophy
History of Western modern PhilosophyHistory of Western modern Philosophy
History of Western modern PhilosophySyed Noman Ali
 
Empiricist epistemology – Hume & Kant
Empiricist epistemology – Hume & KantEmpiricist epistemology – Hume & Kant
Empiricist epistemology – Hume & KantAimee Hoover-Miller
 
George wilhelm friedrich hegel
George wilhelm friedrich hegelGeorge wilhelm friedrich hegel
George wilhelm friedrich hegelHaleh Esmailian
 
Philosophy of Mind & Cognitive Psychology
Philosophy of Mind & Cognitive PsychologyPhilosophy of Mind & Cognitive Psychology
Philosophy of Mind & Cognitive Psychologypiero scaruffi
 
Philosophy of mind - Edward Feser - Philosophical terms
Philosophy of mind - Edward Feser - Philosophical termsPhilosophy of mind - Edward Feser - Philosophical terms
Philosophy of mind - Edward Feser - Philosophical termsAmith hillshow
 

What's hot (20)

Metaphysics
MetaphysicsMetaphysics
Metaphysics
 
History of philosophy_and_philosophers
History of philosophy_and_philosophersHistory of philosophy_and_philosophers
History of philosophy_and_philosophers
 
Ontology Powerpoint
Ontology PowerpointOntology Powerpoint
Ontology Powerpoint
 
Ch2ppt velasquez12
Ch2ppt velasquez12Ch2ppt velasquez12
Ch2ppt velasquez12
 
Waller ch 04
Waller ch 04Waller ch 04
Waller ch 04
 
Philosophy of Man
Philosophy of ManPhilosophy of Man
Philosophy of Man
 
Biografi Immanuel Kant - Seorang Filsuf
Biografi Immanuel Kant - Seorang FilsufBiografi Immanuel Kant - Seorang Filsuf
Biografi Immanuel Kant - Seorang Filsuf
 
Metaphysics
MetaphysicsMetaphysics
Metaphysics
 
SPINOZA'S PHILOSOPHY
SPINOZA'S PHILOSOPHYSPINOZA'S PHILOSOPHY
SPINOZA'S PHILOSOPHY
 
Classic and Modern Philosophy: Rationalism and Empicism
Classic and Modern Philosophy: Rationalism and EmpicismClassic and Modern Philosophy: Rationalism and Empicism
Classic and Modern Philosophy: Rationalism and Empicism
 
The branches of philosophy pdf
The branches of philosophy pdfThe branches of philosophy pdf
The branches of philosophy pdf
 
Ch1ppt velasquez12
Ch1ppt velasquez12Ch1ppt velasquez12
Ch1ppt velasquez12
 
L4 critique of pure reason
L4 critique of pure reasonL4 critique of pure reason
L4 critique of pure reason
 
History of Western modern Philosophy
History of Western modern PhilosophyHistory of Western modern Philosophy
History of Western modern Philosophy
 
Western Understanding of Man
Western Understanding of ManWestern Understanding of Man
Western Understanding of Man
 
Empiricist epistemology – Hume & Kant
Empiricist epistemology – Hume & KantEmpiricist epistemology – Hume & Kant
Empiricist epistemology – Hume & Kant
 
Descartes lecture 10
Descartes lecture 10Descartes lecture 10
Descartes lecture 10
 
George wilhelm friedrich hegel
George wilhelm friedrich hegelGeorge wilhelm friedrich hegel
George wilhelm friedrich hegel
 
Philosophy of Mind & Cognitive Psychology
Philosophy of Mind & Cognitive PsychologyPhilosophy of Mind & Cognitive Psychology
Philosophy of Mind & Cognitive Psychology
 
Philosophy of mind - Edward Feser - Philosophical terms
Philosophy of mind - Edward Feser - Philosophical termsPhilosophy of mind - Edward Feser - Philosophical terms
Philosophy of mind - Edward Feser - Philosophical terms
 

Viewers also liked

Tiago Dos Santos project THIS IS ME
Tiago Dos Santos project THIS IS METiago Dos Santos project THIS IS ME
Tiago Dos Santos project THIS IS METiago Miguel
 
Part one of pitch presentation
Part one of pitch presentationPart one of pitch presentation
Part one of pitch presentationLea Valley Media
 
Emerce Ehrm gordon lokenberg think web act mobile in recruitment
Emerce Ehrm gordon lokenberg think web act mobile in recruitmentEmerce Ehrm gordon lokenberg think web act mobile in recruitment
Emerce Ehrm gordon lokenberg think web act mobile in recruitmentGordon Lokenberg
 
10-Foot 2 Inches: Designing Apps for Up-Close & Afar with Jenna Marino, Patri...
10-Foot 2 Inches: Designing Apps for Up-Close & Afar with Jenna Marino, Patri...10-Foot 2 Inches: Designing Apps for Up-Close & Afar with Jenna Marino, Patri...
10-Foot 2 Inches: Designing Apps for Up-Close & Afar with Jenna Marino, Patri...FITC
 
Parenting 1 proverbs 042810
Parenting 1 proverbs 042810Parenting 1 proverbs 042810
Parenting 1 proverbs 042810Alan Shelby
 
Now That You’re Near
Now That You’re NearNow That You’re Near
Now That You’re NearBart Lulu
 

Viewers also liked (7)

Tiago Dos Santos project THIS IS ME
Tiago Dos Santos project THIS IS METiago Dos Santos project THIS IS ME
Tiago Dos Santos project THIS IS ME
 
Part one of pitch presentation
Part one of pitch presentationPart one of pitch presentation
Part one of pitch presentation
 
Emerce Ehrm gordon lokenberg think web act mobile in recruitment
Emerce Ehrm gordon lokenberg think web act mobile in recruitmentEmerce Ehrm gordon lokenberg think web act mobile in recruitment
Emerce Ehrm gordon lokenberg think web act mobile in recruitment
 
10-Foot 2 Inches: Designing Apps for Up-Close & Afar with Jenna Marino, Patri...
10-Foot 2 Inches: Designing Apps for Up-Close & Afar with Jenna Marino, Patri...10-Foot 2 Inches: Designing Apps for Up-Close & Afar with Jenna Marino, Patri...
10-Foot 2 Inches: Designing Apps for Up-Close & Afar with Jenna Marino, Patri...
 
Parenting 1 proverbs 042810
Parenting 1 proverbs 042810Parenting 1 proverbs 042810
Parenting 1 proverbs 042810
 
Now That You’re Near
Now That You’re NearNow That You’re Near
Now That You’re Near
 
Presentatie Tib 22 April 2008
Presentatie Tib 22 April 2008Presentatie Tib 22 April 2008
Presentatie Tib 22 April 2008
 

Similar to View content 0509.210.01 - intro

kant- a renowned western political theorist
kant- a renowned western political theoristkant- a renowned western political theorist
kant- a renowned western political theoristMaryamSiddiqaLodhiLe
 
René Descartes.docx
René Descartes.docxRené Descartes.docx
René Descartes.docxLaYirFan
 
Phil – 10 into to philosophy lecture 13 - kant
Phil – 10 into to philosophy   lecture 13 - kantPhil – 10 into to philosophy   lecture 13 - kant
Phil – 10 into to philosophy lecture 13 - kantWilliamParkhurst
 
CHAPTER 4The Nature of Substance, Reality, and Mind Idealism,.docx
CHAPTER 4The Nature of Substance, Reality, and Mind Idealism,.docxCHAPTER 4The Nature of Substance, Reality, and Mind Idealism,.docx
CHAPTER 4The Nature of Substance, Reality, and Mind Idealism,.docxchristinemaritza
 
Mahmoud sayed mohamed 7 converted
Mahmoud sayed mohamed 7 convertedMahmoud sayed mohamed 7 converted
Mahmoud sayed mohamed 7 convertedaskrnasef
 
LIFE HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF IMMANUAL KANT.pptx
LIFE HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF IMMANUAL KANT.pptxLIFE HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF IMMANUAL KANT.pptx
LIFE HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF IMMANUAL KANT.pptxMusratbashir1
 
PHIL 212 Introductory Ethics Module 3Meta-ethical Questions.docx
PHIL 212 Introductory Ethics  Module 3Meta-ethical Questions.docxPHIL 212 Introductory Ethics  Module 3Meta-ethical Questions.docx
PHIL 212 Introductory Ethics Module 3Meta-ethical Questions.docxmattjtoni51554
 
Deontology and business ethics chap t 3
Deontology and business ethics chap t 3Deontology and business ethics chap t 3
Deontology and business ethics chap t 3ong ahhuat
 
Business Ethics - Metaphysics of Morals by Immanuel Kant
Business Ethics -  Metaphysics of Morals by Immanuel KantBusiness Ethics -  Metaphysics of Morals by Immanuel Kant
Business Ethics - Metaphysics of Morals by Immanuel KantMufaddal Nullwala
 
Lecture 3_FrommGreeks to modern science.pptx
Lecture 3_FrommGreeks to modern science.pptxLecture 3_FrommGreeks to modern science.pptx
Lecture 3_FrommGreeks to modern science.pptxAidanaSharipova1
 
kant - neetu/amanda/abdul
kant - neetu/amanda/abdulkant - neetu/amanda/abdul
kant - neetu/amanda/abdulabdulkamali
 

Similar to View content 0509.210.01 - intro (15)

About immanuel kant
About immanuel kantAbout immanuel kant
About immanuel kant
 
DEONTOLOGY.pptx
DEONTOLOGY.pptxDEONTOLOGY.pptx
DEONTOLOGY.pptx
 
kant- a renowned western political theorist
kant- a renowned western political theoristkant- a renowned western political theorist
kant- a renowned western political theorist
 
René Descartes.docx
René Descartes.docxRené Descartes.docx
René Descartes.docx
 
Phil – 10 into to philosophy lecture 13 - kant
Phil – 10 into to philosophy   lecture 13 - kantPhil – 10 into to philosophy   lecture 13 - kant
Phil – 10 into to philosophy lecture 13 - kant
 
CHAPTER 4The Nature of Substance, Reality, and Mind Idealism,.docx
CHAPTER 4The Nature of Substance, Reality, and Mind Idealism,.docxCHAPTER 4The Nature of Substance, Reality, and Mind Idealism,.docx
CHAPTER 4The Nature of Substance, Reality, and Mind Idealism,.docx
 
Mahmoud sayed mohamed 7 converted
Mahmoud sayed mohamed 7 convertedMahmoud sayed mohamed 7 converted
Mahmoud sayed mohamed 7 converted
 
LIFE HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF IMMANUAL KANT.pptx
LIFE HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF IMMANUAL KANT.pptxLIFE HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF IMMANUAL KANT.pptx
LIFE HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF IMMANUAL KANT.pptx
 
PHIL 212 Introductory Ethics Module 3Meta-ethical Questions.docx
PHIL 212 Introductory Ethics  Module 3Meta-ethical Questions.docxPHIL 212 Introductory Ethics  Module 3Meta-ethical Questions.docx
PHIL 212 Introductory Ethics Module 3Meta-ethical Questions.docx
 
Deontology and business ethics chap t 3
Deontology and business ethics chap t 3Deontology and business ethics chap t 3
Deontology and business ethics chap t 3
 
Business Ethics - Metaphysics of Morals by Immanuel Kant
Business Ethics -  Metaphysics of Morals by Immanuel KantBusiness Ethics -  Metaphysics of Morals by Immanuel Kant
Business Ethics - Metaphysics of Morals by Immanuel Kant
 
Lecture 3_FrommGreeks to modern science.pptx
Lecture 3_FrommGreeks to modern science.pptxLecture 3_FrommGreeks to modern science.pptx
Lecture 3_FrommGreeks to modern science.pptx
 
homework
homeworkhomework
homework
 
kant - neetu/amanda/abdul
kant - neetu/amanda/abdulkant - neetu/amanda/abdul
kant - neetu/amanda/abdul
 
neetu - kant
neetu - kantneetu - kant
neetu - kant
 

View content 0509.210.01 - intro

  • 1. Peter Bornedal, General Lecture, 203
  • 2. • Kant lived in the Prussian city Königsberg his entire life. He never traveled, and is famous for his methodic and rigorous lifestyle and high work ethics. He would begin his lecture-schedule seven o’clock in the morning (and was so popular with students that they had to arrive an hour early to secure themselves a seat). As he raised to fame, scholars from all over Europe would travel to Königsberg to see him lecturing. It is said that the lectures that preceded the work we are reading, Grounding of a Metaphysics of Morals, were so gripping to the audience that they felt they were listening to a revelation. • After work, Kant would have his famous afternoon walk, being so punctual about this exercise that the German writer Heinrich Heine once quipped that the wives of Königsberg adjusted their clocks after him passing by. • Kant was never married; nor did he have – as far as we know – any kind of romantic relationship. This methodic, monotonous, and rigorous life might indicate a rather dry personality, but apparently he was not. Anecdote has is that Kant was an entertaining, engaging, and witty conversationalist. He seems to have been popular as a guest in the better society, and seems to have had a good sense of humor – although we admittedly do not find much humor in his philosophical work. • Kant is undoubtedly regarded as one, if not the greatest, of Germany’s philosophers. He has dealt with almost all aspects of philosophy and even science. His three so-called “Critiques” – Critique of Pure Reason, Critique of Practical Reason, and Critique of Judgment – deal respectively with the three most important branches of philosophy: Knowledge/Mind, Ethics/Morals, and Aesthetics. Besides these works, he wrote important treatises about physics, astronomy, logic, religion, anthropology, politics, and Kant education. Kant Lecturing
  • 3. • Kant wrote on Ethics and Morals in four different works. His first preliminary Quotations: study is the Grounding of a Metaphysics of Morals (1785), which we read. Thereupon follows his Critique of Practical Reason (1788). About ten years later Even if there never have he publishes his Metaphysics of Morals (1797), and finally one year later his been action springing Anthropology from a Pragmatic point of view (1798). from such pure • In the three first works, moral behavior has a strictly ideal formulation. Kant sources, the question wants to set up moral principles that are ideal, meaning they are not meant to at issue here is not describe actual human behavior. In the last work, ethical behavior is studied from whether this or that has a practical perspective, meaning that he studies actual human behavior – not happened but that ideal principles that ought to regulate human behavior. The first three works deal reason of itself and with ethics from a metaphysical point of view, while the last work deals with independently of all ethics from an anthropological. experience commands • When one studies metaphysics of moral, one sets out to determine the general what ought to happen. and universal principles that have to guide moral action, whether or not people (Kant, ibid., p. 19) actually follow these principles. They [philosophers • We can illustrate the idea with a couple of examples taken from Kant himself. advocating self-interest Kant says: “even if there has never existed a sincere friend, sincerity in and self-love as basic friendship is an idea that is still required of every man.” Or “even if an unselfish act has never been performed, unselfishness is still the ideal for moral action.” human motives] have spoken with sincere • So, even if the motives for our actions are impure and selfish, Kant’s moral regret as to the frailty theory prevails, because it deals with what ought to be the case. Moral law does and impurity of human not depend on experience, but on reason. Moral principles must be grounded in nature, which they pure a priori concepts, not mixed with anything empirical. think is noble enough • Kant claims that even if ideal moral principles are rarely or never carried out, to take as its precept we always presuppose these principles. For example, 1) when we lament how an idea so worthy of corruptible and dishonest the human being is, we spontaneously presuppose respect but yet is too integrity and honesty as ideal regulatory principles – principles that ought to weak to follow his ideal regulate human behavior; 2) in the image we form of God as all-benevolent, we reason, which should presuppose ideal moral principles. God is in his essence, what we can only legislate for human strive to be in our existence. We cannot be all-benevolent like God, but we can set up benevolence as an ideal, and we do so in the image we form of God. nature. (Kant, ibid., p. 19) • The upshot is, we may not believe in the actual execution of ideal moral principles; still, Kant insists, we always presuppose that they ought to exist.
  • 4. According to Kant, we are endowed with two essentially different kinds of knowledge: scientific knowledge and moral knowledge. • The reason why we so often do not follow ideal Scientific knowledge studies the laws of nature regulatory principles, which we ought to follow, is that we of the external world; moral knowledge studies as humans have a free will. If we were objects, we would the laws of freedom of the internal world. In not have a choice. A stone cannot decide whether or not it wants to follow the laws of nature, but as subjects we can Scientific knowledge one studies causes. In choose not the follow the laws of morals. Because of our Moral knowledge one studies motives. Both freedom of the will, the metaphysical ethical laws Kant kinds of knowledge have their own kinds of a deduces as applying specifically to human beings are not priori laws. In his work, Critique of Practical laws of nature, but laws of freedom. Reason, Kant states. • In his work, Critique of Pure Reason, Kant had been “Two things fill the mind with ever new and increasing studying the ‘laws of nature.’ These he would separate in admiration and reverence, the more often and more steadily an empirical part and a rational part. The empirical part would consist of sensations, and the rational part of the one reflects one them: the starry heavens above me and the so-called categories of understanding. The categories moral law within me. I do not need to search for them and were in themselves abstract or pure, and they acquired an merely conjecture them as though they were veiled in obscurity empirical content before they could be applied to and or in the transcendent region beyond my horizon; I see them make sense of the world of appearances. before me and connect them immediately with the • Without getting into Kant’s epistemological work, we consciousness of my existence. The first begins from the place I notice that when Kant in his ethical work studies so-called occupy in the external world of sense { . . . ] the second begins ‘laws of freedom,’ also these laws have an empirical and from my invisible self, my personality, and presents me in a rational part. Addressing the empirical part, one studies world with has true infinity but which can be discovered only by how people actually behave (like in Anthropology, Psychology, Sociology, or History). Addressing the rational the understanding, and I cognize that my connection with that part, one studies how people ideally ought to behave (like world [ . . . ] is not merely contingent, as in the first case, but in Metaphysics of Morals). universal and necessary. The first view of a countless multitude • We can set the Kantian distinctions up in this table: of worlds annihilates, as it were, my importance as an animal creature, which must give back to the planet (a mere speck in Empirical part (Sensations) the universe) the matter from which it came. The second, on the Laws of nature -- Physics contrary, infinitely raises my worth as an intelligence by my Rational part (Categories) personality, in which the moral law reveals to me a life Empirical part (How people actually do behave) independent of animality and even of the whole sensible Laws of freedom -- Ethics world.” (Kant: Critique of Practical Reason, Cambridge Rational part (How people ideally ought to behave) University Press; p. 133-34.)
  • 5. • That a moral imperative is a priori implies that it applies to all peoples in all histories, and under all circumstances, whether or not they live by it or obey it. It is a priori because it is already part of our rational constitution; Kant therefore only “deduces” (i.e., he articulates and makes explicit) what is already there as implicitly known. The result of the ‘deduction,’ the abstract moral law, can therefore also not be an object for discussion or negotiation. Universal moral law is part of our implicit rational knowledge, which we as such ‘know’ is true as rational beings. • Kant starts his deduction of pure morals by asserting such an unconditional moral law (something we all ‘know’ is true when it is made explicit to us): “There is no possibility of thinking of anything at all in the world, or even out of it, which can be regarded as good without qualification, expect a good will.” (Kant, Grounding of a Metaphysics of Moral, p. 7.) • This is Kant’s first example of an unconditional moral law: the good will. Notice here that Kant does not suggest any specific quality as moral, as numerous other moral philosophers have done, such as honor, generosity, self-control, intelligence, courage, perseverance, fortune, wealth, etc. Only the good will can qualify as moral law, because without the background-motivation of a ‘good will’ all the qualities mentioned above – generosity, self-control, intelligence, etc. – can be abused, or may have been executed for selfish purposes. • Two examples: A) If a man is generous because he expects something in return, he is generous for selfish purposes, not out of a purely good will. B) A villain in perfect self-control is not a virtuous man acting with ‘good will,’ but rather a more dangerous villain. The same applies if he is courageous, intelligent, etc. • Therefore Kant continues that a good will is good not because it effects some end, or achieves some personal benefit or profit. It must be “good in itself”: “A good will is good not because of what it effects or accomplishes, nor because of its fitness to attain some proposed end; it is good only through its willing, i.e., it is good in itself.” [ . . . ] “[The will] is not merely good as a means to some further end, but is good in itself.” (Kant, ibid., p. 7 & 9.) • Because we have a “freedom of the will” we can influence and direct our will; we can choose between willing an action that is a means to some further end, or willing an action that is good in itself.
  • 6. • If we act with an unconditional good will, even if our action achieves nothing, or perhaps achieves the opposite of what we intended, our action has a moral content. The ‘good will’ shall “shine by its own light as something which has its full power in itself.” (Kant, ibid., p. 8.) • It seems that intention has become the quintessential criteria for the morality of an action; it seems as if, insofar as we act with the intention to do good, our action has moral content. • Is now a ‘good will’ identical to ‘good intentions’? – Well, not quite! -- And why not? – Because the definition would be redundant and meaningless! One cannot explain a good will with good intentions, because it is the same thing. Kant wants to deduce universal moral principles, he wants to know what is inherent in exhibiting ‘good will.’ If a ‘good will’ simply were to have ‘good intentions,’ he would still need to explain what is inherent is exhibiting ‘good intentions.’ His problem would not have been solved; it would not have gone away. • Furthermore, if a ‘good will’ were reducible to ‘good intentions,’ we would be referring to a psychologically determined ‘good will’ rooted in a compassionate subject. But the moral principle cannot be determined from neither individual psychology, nor from compassion. The moral principle is formal and universal, never concrete and individual; and it is rooted in reason, never passions. • The upshot is, forget the compassionate subject – the ‘warm heart,’ as Nietzsche often puts it in his somewhat misunderstood mockery of Kantian positions. Forget the following equation: The ‘Warm Heart’/the Compassionate Subject = Good Intentions = Good Will → Moral Action Apply instead the following deduction: Freedom of the Will  Respect for Universal Law  Duty toward Maxims Prescribed by Law  Good Will  Moral Action
  • 7. • Let us first explain what is meant by the statement above • What is it to ‘act from duty’? – It is 1) to act, not just according to a law, but also for the sake of a law that transcends the individual (that is, for the sake of a formal principle, not a psychological principle, like the ‘warm heart’). 2) it is to act contrary to inclinations (desires, self-interests, personal benefits, profit, etc.). 3) It is to adopt an action because reason commands of us this course of action (not because passions or compassions urge us on). • What is a maxim? – A maxim is a brief articulation of an instruction that the individual follows in his action. • What is Law? – Law is the set of imperatives prescribing moral actions. Moral Laws are always categorical, meaning that they are not up for discussion or negotiation. Metaphorically speaking, moral laws are as if carved in stone, like the Ten Commandments Moses brings down from Mount Sinai. However, the Ten Commandments are divine rules of conduct, while Kant’s categorical imperatives are rational rules of conduct. • In order to illustrate his principle, ‘acting from duty,’ Kant gives us four different examples of action, where only the last has moral content. One is contrary to duty; two are in accordance with duty but are still performed because of self-interests; only the last is performed ‘from duty’ and ‘contrary to inclination.’ Only the last qualifies as truly moral. The four examples are the following: 1) Some actions are contrary to duty, and performed out of self-interest and inclination, like stealing, cheating, lying, etc. Obviously, they are not moral. 2) Other actions are performed according to duty, but because of some mediate self-interest. A person pays his taxes on time according to duty, but he knows that he thus avoid fines, and society gives him back various social benefits. He acts according to duty, but not from a duty free of self-interest, and is thus not a true moral subject. 3) Other actions are performed according to duty, but because of some immediate self-interest. If a man does not commit suicide, he acts according to duty, but if he loves his live, he also acts according to inclination. He never contemplated suicide since he is happy and everything is going well. Thus, he preserves his life according to duty, but not from a duty free of self-interest, and is thus not a true moral subject. 4) Finally, there are actions, which are in accordance with duty, and moreover, are performed from duty contrary to inclination. These are true moral actions, whose maxims constitute the subject as moral.
  • 8. • Whether one acts ‘according to’ or ‘from’ • In this Kantian definition, there is no room for the ‘warm duty, one acts out of respect for Law. But only heart.’ If a ‘warmhearted’ man enjoys spreading joy and actions done ‘from duty’ have moral content, happiness around, he is acting according to duty (and because they are done ‘for the sake of’ duty, certainly, nobody blames him), but his action has the without considerations of inclinations or characteristics of the third case above: he acts according to personal benefits. duty, but also according to immediate inclination. • They are done out of nothing but pure Therefore, his action has no true moral content. respect for Law. • If on the contrary, this man, in his personal life carries • Notice that a so-called ‘good will’ is a rational great sorrows, but nonetheless still has the power to will to respect Law, with no other motives than benefit and spread joy among others, then his action is respect for Law. performed from duty contrary to inclination, and it has a true moral content. “Duty is the necessity of an action done out “If adversity and hopeless sorrow have completely of respect for the law. [ . . . ] Hence there is taken away the taste for life, if an unfortunate man, nothing left which can determine the will strong in soul and more indignant at his fate than except objectively the law and subjectively despondent or dejected, wishes for death and yet pure respect for this practical law, i.e. the preserves his life without loving it – not from inclination will can be subjectively determined by the or fear, but from duty – then his maxim indeed has a maxim that I should follow such a law even moral content.” [ . . . ] “Even though no inclination if all my inclinations are thereby thwarted. [ moves him any longer, he nevertheless tears himself . . . ] The pre-eminent good which is called from this deadly insensibility and performs the action moral can consist in nothing but the without any inclination at all, but solely from duty – representation of the law in itself.” (Kant, then for the first time his action has genuine moral ibid., p. 12-13). worth.” (Kant, ibid., p. 10 & 11)
  • 9. • We have learnt that to act with a ‘good will’ is to act from, ‘for the sake of,’ duty in respect for Law and nothing but Law. From this deduction, Kant formulates his famous categorical imperative. In its first formulation, it reads: “Since I have deprived the will of every impulse that might arise for it from obeying any particular law, there is nothing left to serve the will as principle except the universal conformity of its actions to law as such, i.e., I should never act except in such a way that I can also will that my maxim should become a universal law.” (Kant, ibid., p. 14.) • Kant’s example: “when I am in distress, may I make a promise with the intention of not keeping it.” In other words, is it okay under some circumstances to lie? – Now, one might argue that a person should avoid lying, because it would be detrimental to him in the long run. A lying shopkeeper would eventually be exposed, and thus loose customers. The argument presupposes that one should be truthful because of some ends or consequences; it presupposes a so-called ‘hypothetical imperative,’ an if-then relation: if I don’t lie, then my business will thrive, and I will prosper: if I do so and so, then I will achieve this or that. • Therefore, a hypothetical imperative is not ‘categorical.’ it is not unconditional, universal, and absolute. A ‘categorical imperative’ is asserted out of respect for Law, without other concerns. A hypothetical imperative is asserted out of concerns for benefits or profits. It does not determine the moral content of an act. • So, now we ask again, but from the perspective of the categorical imperative, is it okay under some circumstances to lie? – The answer is still ‘no,’ but with a different explanation. Observing the categorical imperative, I avoid lying because of respect for universal Law. My reason tells me that lying cannot be accepted as universal Law. My reason tells me that if I will lying as universal Law, then I will everybody to lie, and then it is no longer possible to make promises at all. Under the obligation of a universal law to lie, every promise is a contradiction in terms. “I immediately become aware that I can indeed will the lie but can not at all will a universal law to lie. For by such a law there would really be no promises at all, since in vain would my willing future actions be professed to other people who would not believe what I professed, or if they overhastily did believe, then they would pay me back in like coin.” (Kant, ibid., p. 15). • If now I do not will a universal law to lie, then I must admit that neither do I will my first proposal: may I make a promise with the intention not to keep it. I must reject this proposal. Therefore, when one ‘respects law,’ one does not respect a particular law, but a law requesting universal validity in an action.
  • 10. Imperatives says that something would be good to do or to refrain from doing, but they say it to a will that does not always therefore do something simply because it has been represented to the will as something good to do. That is practically good which determines the will by means of representations or reason and hence not by subjective causes, but objectively, i.e.. on grounds valid for every rational being as such. (Kant , ibid., p. 24). • What is here established is that we have wills, meaning that we have the choice to follow a rational decision or not. If purely subjective interests determine this choice, it is not a moral choice, but if our will be governed by objective moral laws, then we are following, not personal interests, but an imperative. • We can only rationally choose moral imperatives, because our wills in themselves are not moral, rational, or objective. We are not gods, and we have no holy wills, we have only human wills. If we were gods, we would not need moral imperatives. • In the categorical imperative, the so-called maxim of the action (i.e., the instruction as articulated to the subject describing the action) should conform to universal law. In this conformity the maxim makes itself into a universal law. This correspondence or conformity is alone what is necessary by the imperative, therefore there is only one imperative and it reads (in two different versions): Act only according to that maxim whereby you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law. [ . . . ] Act as if the maxim of your action were to become through your will a universal law of nature. ( Kant, ibid., p. 30) • An example of Kant’s: A suicidal man! – Is he allowed or not to take his own life according to the categorical imperative? His duty to himself is to preserve his life. If he decides to commit suicide he does so because it is an easy way out of a life of suffering. Thus he commits suicide out of self-love. “I end my life out of self-love’” becomes the maxim of his action. Now he must ask himself whether this maxim could become “a universal law of nature.” Here he realizes that ‘suicide from self-love’ could never be a universal law of nature, because it would imply a contradiction. If his maxim is universalized, self-love, which normally is to preserve life, is determined as destruction of life, and we are under a universal obligation to destroy our lives – which is absurd.
  • 11. Human Autonomy as Moral Imperative • Even if I tell a lie, I presuppose that one has an universal moral obligation to tell the truth, because I calculate and expect that the one to whom I lie believes I tell the truth. I tell the lie believing in universal law; I just don’t apply this universal law to myself. • In that case, I am using my fellow human being as a means to further my personal ends. While lying I recognize that I am using the other person merely as a means. • This cannot be permitted, because in all cases where I use another rational being for my own ends, the maxims of the actions cannot be universalized. The maxim, ‘I shall use another rational being in order to further my own end,’ cannot become an “universal law of nature,” because we would then place ourselves under a universal obligation to deprive ourselves of our rationality; that is, our free will to rationally choose different courses of action – and again, that is absurd. A rational being is characterized by its ability to make choices, according to the “practical law of freedom.” If I deprive a person of this ability, I deprive him of the “freedom of his will.” • The categorical imperative therefore has another famous formulation, namely that one must always use another rational being as an end in himself, never as a means (it Is often referred to as Kant’s “Principle of Humanity”): “Rational nature exists as an end in itself. [ . . . ] The practical imperative will thus be as follows: so act as to treat humanity, whether in your own person or in that of any other, always at the same time as an end and never merely as a means.” . . . “Persons must exist as ends in themselves. [ . . . ] Such an end is one for which there can be substituted no other end to which such beings should serve merely as means, for otherwise nothing at all of absolute value would be found anywhere.” (Kant, ibid., p. 36). • According to this formulation of the categorical imperative, one always has a duty to use both oneself and another person as ends in themselves, never as means. Kant’s suicidal man is for example using himself as a ‘means’ – which is not permitted: “If he destroys himself in order to escape from a difficult situation, then he is making use of his person merely as a means so as to maintain a tolerable condition till the end of his life. Man, however, is not a thing and hence is not something to be used merely as a means; he must in all his actions always be regarded as an end in himself.” (Kant, ibid., p. 36).
  • 12. • In his ‘deductions’ of the moral imperatives, Kant The Kingdom of Ends: presupposes that Man is capable of self-legislation – that is, Kant as the First Human we are able to give laws to ourselves, which we are able thereupon to follow. Rights Philosopher • We are able to make laws and choose to follow them thanks to our free will. We are not subjected to natural laws (in which case we are without choice in moral matters), but to ‘practical laws of freedom.’ • This freedom from natural laws in the human being must be preserved. Humans can only be subjected to ‘practical laws,’ and these laws are always of their own making. They are self-legislative and are thus testimonies of our free will. • If therefore ‘practical laws’ are fashioned as ‘natural laws’ it indicates a perversion of reason, and a violation of human freedom. • If a dictator dictates laws as if they were laws of nature, his maxim cannot be universalized, because it contradicts human freedom as such. The human being is a priori free or autonomous. This freedom cannot be violated. • Because of this fundamental autonomy, humans must never be deprived of their freedom to make rational decisions. They must always be treated as ends, and we must legislate as if we all belonged to a “Kingdom of Ends,” a society where we are free and have equal rights. • There can be no ‘scientific proof’ of this deduction, because it transcend the bounds of possible experience. It belongs to the noumenal, not to the phenomenal, world. It transcends the apparent world. Still, it nevertheless has existence as “regulative idea.”