SlideShare ist ein Scribd-Unternehmen logo
1 von 422
Downloaden Sie, um offline zu lesen
the invention of capitalism 
Michael Perelman
the invention of capitalism
This page intentionally left blank
THE INVENTION OF CAPITALISM 
Classical Political Economy and the 
Secret History of Primitive Accumulation 
michael perelman 
Duke University Press • Durham & London 2000
∫ 2000 Duke University Press 
All rights reserved 
Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper $ 
Typeset in Trump Mediaeval by Keystone Typesetting, Inc. 
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data appear 
on the last printed page of this book.
Contents 
Introduction: Dark Designs 1 
1 The Enduring Importance of Primitive Accumulation 13 
2 The Theory of Primitive Accumulation 25 
3 Primitive Accumulation and the Game Laws 38 
4 The Social Division of Labor and Household Production 59 
5 Elaborating the Model of Primitive Accumulation 92 
6 The Dawn of Political Economy 124 
7 Sir James Steuart’s Secret History of Primitive Accumulation 139 
8 Adam Smith’s Charming Obfuscation of Class 171 
9 The Revisionist History of Professor Adam Smith 196 
10 Adam Smith and the Ideological Role of the Colonies 229 
11 Benjamin Franklin and the Smithian Ideology of Slavery and Wage 
Labor 254 
12 The Classics as Cossacks: Classical Political Economy versus the 
Working Class 280 
13 The Counterattack 321 
14 Notes on Development 352 
Conclusion 369 
References 371 
Index 407
This page intentionally left blank
the invention of capitalism
This page intentionally left blank
Introduction: Dark Designs 
In order to develop the laws of bourgeois economy . . . it is not necessary to write 
the real history of the relations of production. But the correct observation and 
deduction of these laws . . . always leads to primary equations . . . which point 
toward a past lying behind the system. These indications . . . then offer the key to 
understanding the past—a work in its own right.—Karl Marx, Grundrisse 
Preface 
In the development of a theory, the invisible of a visible field is not generally 
anything whatever outside and foreign to the visible defined by that field. The 
invisible is defined by the visible as its invisible, its forbidden vision: the invisible 
is not therefore simply what is outside the visible (to return to the spatial meta-phor), 
the outer darkness of exclusion—but the inner darkness of exclusion, inside 
the visible itself.—Louis Althusser, ‘‘From Capital to Marx’s Philosophy’’ 
The Laissez-faire Message of Classical Political Economy 
Classical political economy, the core works of economic literature from 
the time of William Petty through that of David Ricardo, presents an 
imposing facade. The towering figures of early political economy forged a 
new way of thinking systematically about economic affairs in the late 
seventeenth and early eighteenth centuries with little more than the writ-ings 
of business people and moral philosophers to guide them. Every one, 
from Karl Marx, who created the term ‘‘classical political economy,’’ to 
modern-day conservatives, recognizes the enormous intellectual achieve-ment 
of these early economists. 
For more than two centuries, successive generations of economists 
have been grinding out texts to demonstrate how these early theorists 
discovered that markets provide the most efficient method for organizing 
production. An uncompromising advocacy of laissez-faire is, ostensibly, 
the intended lesson of classical political economy. 
Most contemporary readers of Adam Smith, David Ricardo, and the 
other classical political economists accept their work at face value, as-suming 
these early writers to be uncompromising advocates of laissez-
2 
faire. For the most part, even many Marxists accept this interpretation of 
classical political economy. Alongside their work on pure economic the-ory, 
the classical political economists engaged in a parallel project: to pro-mote 
the forcible reconstruction of society into a purely market-oriented 
system. While economic historians may debate the depth of involvement 
in market activities at the time, the incontestable fact remains that most 
people in Britain did not enthusiastically engage in wage labor—at least so 
long as they had an alternative. 
To make sure that people accepted wage labor, the classical political 
economists actively advocated measures to deprive people of their tradi-tional 
means of support. The brutal acts associated with the process of 
stripping the majority of the people of the means of producing for them-selves 
might seem far removed from the laissez-faire reputation of clas-sical 
political economy. In reality, the dispossession of the majority of 
small-scale producers and the construction of laissez-faire are closely con-nected, 
so much so that Marx, or at least his translators, labeled this 
expropriation of the masses as ‘‘primitive accumulation.’’ 
The very sound of the expression, primitive accumulation, drips with 
poignant echoes of human consequences. The word ‘‘primitive,’’ first of 
all, suggests a brutality lacking in the subtleties of more modern forms of 
exploitation. It also implies that primitive accumulation was prior to the 
form of accumulation that people generally associate with capitalism. 
Finally, it hints at something that we might associate with ‘‘primitive’’ 
parts of the world, where capital accumulation has not advanced as far as 
elsewhere. 
The second term, accumulation, reminds us that the primary focus of 
the process was the accumulation of capital and wealth by a small sector of 
society, or as Marx (1977, 739–40) described it, ‘‘the conquest of the world 
of social wealth. It is the extension of the area of exploited human material 
and, at the same time, the extension of the indirect and direct sway of the 
capitalist.’’ Certainly, at least in the early stages of capitalism, primitive 
accumulation was a central element in the accumulation process. 
Although many modern scholars acknowledge the pervasive nature 
of primitive accumulation during the time that the classical political 
economists wrote, nobody to my knowledge has recognized the com-plicity 
of the classical political economists. They strongly advocated pol-icies 
that furthered the process of primitive accumulation, often through 
subterfuge. 
While energetically promoting their laissez-faire ideology, they cham-pioned 
time and time again policies that flew in the face of their laissez-
introduction 3 
faire principles, especially their analysis of the role of small-scale, rural 
producers. As we will see, the underlying development strategy of the 
classical political economists was consistent with a crude proto-Marxian 
model of primitive accumulation, which concluded that nonmarket 
forces might be required to speed up the process of capitalist assimilation 
in the countryside. This model also explains why most of the classical 
political economists expressed positions diametrically opposed to the 
theories usually credited to them. 
The Secret History of Primitive Accumulation 
Perhaps because so much of what the classical economists wrote about 
traditional systems of agricultural production was divorced from their 
seemingly more timeless remarks about pure theory, later readers have 
passed over such portions of their works in haste. Although this aspect of 
classical political economy might have seemed to fall outside the core of 
the subject, I argue that these interventionist recommendations were a 
significant element in the overall thrust of their works. Specifically, clas-sical 
political economy advocated restricting the viability of traditional 
occupations in the countryside to coerce people to work for wages. 
Chapter 1, which deals with the history of primitive accumulation, 
demonstrates the classical political economists’ keen interest in driving 
rural workers from the countryside and into factories, compelling work-ers 
to do the bidding of those who would like to employ them, and eradi-cating 
any sign of sloth. 
The vitality of these rural producers generally rested on a careful com-bination 
of industrial and agricultural pursuits. Despite the efficiency of 
this arrangement, classical political economy was intent on throttling 
small producers. Classical political economists often justified their posi-tion 
in terms of the efficiency of the division of labor. They called for 
measures that would actively promote the separation of agriculture and 
industry. As we shall see, Marx’s concept of the social division of labor is 
very important in this respect. In contrast to Smith’s exclusive emphasis 
on the division of labor—the arrangement of work within the firm—Marx 
suggested that we also examine the deployment of resources between 
individual firms and households—the social division of labor. 
Classical political economists paid virtually no attention to the social 
division of labor in their theoretical works. For example, although Smith 
offered a detailed description of the division of labor in his famous pin 
factory, he did not bother to extend his discussion. What does it mean that
4 
society is partitioned in such a way that the pin industry purchases its 
metals or fuels instead of producing them itself? How does such an ar-rangement 
originate? Could such changes in the pattern of industries 
make a difference in an economy, even if technology were unchanging? 
These questions were so distant from the purview of classical political 
economy that more than two centuries later, Ronald Coase won a Nobel 
Prize for bringing them to the attention of mainstream economists. Fol-lowing 
in the wake of Coase, a group of modern economists developed the 
new institutionalist school of economics (see Perelman 1991a), which 
contends that economic forces naturally arrange themselves into some 
optimal pattern. Like many other economists, the new institutionalist 
school takes pride in locating anticipations of its work in classical politi-cal 
economy, especially in the thought of Smith. Even though the new 
institutionalist school concerns itself with the social division of labor, its 
theories are of no use in analyzing the coercive nature of primitive ac-cumulation, 
since this school sees the economy arranging itself through 
voluntary contracts. 
Chapter 2 concentrates on the theory of primitive accumulation. Most 
discussions of primitive accumulation address the subject as a shorthand 
expression for describing the brutality of the initial burst of capitalism. In 
contrast, this chapter makes the case for treating primitive accumulation 
as an essential theoretical concept in analyzing the ongoing process of 
capitalist accumulation. 
I suspected that the continuing silence about the social division of labor 
might have something important to reveal. Following this line of inves-tigation, 
I looked at what classical political economy had to say about the 
peasantry and self-sufficient agriculturalists. Here again, the pattern was 
consistent. 
The classical political economists were unwilling to trust market forces 
to determine the social division of labor because they found the tenacity of 
traditional rural producers to be distasteful. Rather than contending that 
market forces should determine the fate of these small-scale producers, 
classical political economy called for state interventions of one sort or 
another to hobble these people’s ability to produce for their own needs. 
These policy recommendations amounted to a blatant manipulation of 
the social division of labor. 
We cannot justify such policies on the basis of efficiency. If efficiency 
were of great importance to them, the classical political economists would 
not have ignored the law permitting the gentry to ride across small farm-ers’ 
fields in pursuit of foxes while forbidding the farmers from ridding 
their land of game that might eat the crops. As we shall see in Chapter 3,
introduction 5 
these Game Laws destroyed an enormous share of the total agricultural 
produce. 
Chapter 3 describes the extraordinary history of the Game Laws. Al-though 
the origin of the Game Laws was feudal, their application and 
their ferocity peaked during the Industrial Revolution. They were a useful 
instrument to separate rural people from a major source of sustenance, 
adding considerable weight to the pressures to accept wage labor. They 
also incited many poor people in the countryside to rebel. 
Chapter 4 discusses the relationship between primitive accumulation 
and the social division of labor from the standpoint of self-provisioning. 
Chapter 5 analyzes classical political economy’s implicit proto-Marxian 
theory of primitive accumulation. In addition, it discusses the pattern of 
practical measures that altered the social division of labor to the detri-ment 
of independent and small-scale producers. This chapter also dis-cusses 
how classical political economy applied the calculus of primitive 
accumulation. It details the relationship between early classical political 
economy and the rural population with an eye toward efforts to create a 
capitalistic social division of labor. It demonstrates the continual impor-tance 
that classical political economy placed on the process of primitive 
accumulation. 
The Secret History of Classical Political Economy 
Why has the social division of labor as an aspect of primitive accumula-tion 
gone unnoticed for so long by so many students of classical political 
economy? True, the classical political economists generally maintained 
their silence regarding primitive accumulation when discussing matters 
of pure economic theory—although they were not absolutely consistent 
in this regard. 
Because of the novelty of their subject, these writers were not entirely 
in control of their own ideas. Specifically, I found that classical political 
economy openly expressed its dissatisfaction with the existing social divi-sion 
of labor quite clearly in diaries, letters, and more practical writings 
about contemporary affairs. This discovery led me to give a substantially 
new reading to the history of classical political economy. 
In their unguarded moments, the intuition of the classical political 
economists led them to openly express important insights of which they 
may have been only vaguely, if at all, aware. As a result, they let the idea of 
the social division of labor surface from time to time even in their more 
theoretical works. The subject typically cropped up when they were ac-knowledging 
that the market seemed incapable of engaging the rural pop-
6 
ulation fast enough to suit them—or more to the point, that people were 
resisting wage labor. Much of this discussion touched on what we now 
call primitive accumulation. 
Although these slips flew in the face of the laissez-faire theory of classi-cal 
political economy, they add much to the value of that literature. In-deed, 
if classical political economy were nothing more than a conscious 
attempt to come to grips with and justify the emerging forces of capital-ism, 
it would have far less contemporary interest. 
Just as a psychologist might detect a crucial revelation in a seemingly 
offhand remark of a patient, from time to time classical political economy 
discloses to us insights into its program that the classical political econo-mists 
would not consciously welcome. These insights will reinforce the 
conclusions that we draw from their diaries, letters, and more practical 
writings. 
The Invention of Capitalism is novel in four major respects. First, it 
addresses the question of what determines the social division of labor, the 
division of society into independent firms and industries from the per-spective 
of classical political economy. It also develops the theoretical 
implications of primitive accumulation. Third, this book offers a signifi-cantly 
different interpretation of classical political economy, demonstrat-ing 
that this school of thought supported the process of primitive ac-cumulation. 
Finally, it analyzes the role of primitive accumulation in the 
work of Marx. All of these threads come together in helping us to under-stand 
how modern capitalism developed and the role of classical political 
economy in furthering this process. 
On Reading Classical Political Economy 
Modern economists sometimes present classical political economy as a 
polestar by which we can fix our bearings and, in rare cases, guide our-selves 
toward the future. This approach is disingenuous. Despite the in-valuable 
lessons that we can learn from studying classical political econ-omy, 
economists rarely read this literature with an eye to the future or 
even the past. 
All too often, seemingly open-minded reviews of the past are merely a 
means to justify preexisting views of the present. Some readers delight in 
discovering in classical political economy anticipations of recent techni-cal 
refinements, such as the theory of utility maximization. Others use 
the classics to cast their contemporaries in an unfavorable light. John 
Maynard Keynes, for example, contrasted the common sense of the mer-
introduction 7 
cantilists with the irrelevant elegance of Professor Pigou. Still other read-ers 
find the emphasis of the classics on dynamics, growth, or capital ac-cumulation 
attractive. 
In using classical political economy as a polestar, many economists 
represent it as if it were a uniform theory accepted by all. Of course, 
classical political economy was never a fixed body in space, but a hetero-geneous 
collection of literature written over a period of about 100 years. If 
fixity does appear, it is only in the eye of the beholder. Even if many 
readers do acknowledge the diversity of the literature, they single out a 
select group of classical political economists as its stars. In general, they 
portray classical political economy as orbiting around a point somewhere 
between Smith and Ricardo. Some hold it to be closer to one or the other, 
but whatever its center, there is a general consensus as to what con-stitutes 
the canonical literature. 
In reality, we lack objective standards for selecting the stars of classi-cal 
political economy. Writing about the entertainment industry, Moshe 
Adler (1985, 208) has described a process whereby stars can emerge, even 
when they do not significantly differ in talent from lesser lights: 
The phenomenon of stars exists where consumption requires knowl-edge. 
. . . As an example, consider listening to music. Appreciation 
increases with knowledge. But how does one know about music? By 
listening to it, and by discussing it with other persons who know 
about it. [We are] better off patronizing the same artist as others 
do. . . . Stardom is a market device to economize on learning. 
Economists studying the selection of technologies have found a simi-lar 
phenomenon. In the early stages of the development of a technology, 
seemingly trivial accidents can determine which of several technological 
paths is chosen. Once industry becomes locked into a particular tech-nological 
standard, it may continue to follow that line of development 
even though hindsight shows that the neglected paths might have been 
superior (see Arthur 1989). 
A similar process is at work in the study of classical political economy, 
notwithstanding the significant variations that exist in the talents of early 
political economists. Once the status of a book is initially elevated, stu-dents 
are drawn into giving it a deeper consideration. A tradition gradu-ally 
builds up around what becomes treated as almost sacred texts. 
Readers of these canonical works are brought into a multidimensional 
dialogue that includes the authors under study, their times, and the col-lective 
experience of earlier generations of readers of these texts. In this
8 
sense, ‘‘the real life of an author emanates from his readers, disciples, 
commentators, opponents, critics. An author has no other existence’’ 
(Prezzolini 1967, 190; see also Latour 1987, 40). 
By working and reworking these texts, each successive generation finds 
new levels of meaning, some of which probably eluded even the political 
economists who created them. As a result, these works acquire a cumula-tive 
force—albeit highly symbolic—that calls new generations to confront 
them once again. This process reinforces the stature of the ‘‘founders’’ of 
political economy, thereby confirming their status as ‘‘stars.’’ Moreover, 
the erection of this solid structure of scholarship facilitates analysis by 
providing a cognitive map of the territory, allowing future researchers to 
navigate with more confidence. 
Smith’s Wealth of Nations, as we shall see, was not a particularly influ-ential 
book until a generation after its publication. Once opinion leaders 
found the book useful in promoting their desired political outcomes, its 
popularity soared. Only then did Smith become a polestar of classical 
political economy, and his work a reference point by which all others are 
judged. Because of this flawed selection process, most histories of the 
period studiously analyze Smith and Ricardo, along with a handful of 
supposedly secondary figures. Other equally deserving economists gener-ally 
escape notice altogether. 
This book proposes a new reading—a new cosmology so to speak—that 
remaps classical political economy. Here, the center is nearer to Sir James 
Steuart and Edward Gibbon Wakefield than to Smith and Ricardo. From 
this perspective, Adam Smith appears less like the sun than a moon, a 
lesser body whose light is largely reflected from other sources. 
This alternative cosmology is not an arbitrary rearrangement of the 
stars. It highlights important lessons from classical political economy. 
Within this context, Adam Smith becomes less original. His importance 
appears to emanate from the vigor of his ideological project of advocating 
laissez-faire and obfuscating all information that might cast doubt on his 
ideology. Others, such as Edward Gibbon Wakefield and John Rae, took a 
more realistic view about the nature of accumulation, but later econo-mists 
set their analyses aside to create the impression of a humanitarian 
heritage of political economy. 
Judging from the literature of the history of economic thought, it is clear 
this view of history has succeeded mightily. The Invention of Capitalism 
represents a plea to correct this legacy of error and omission. From this 
perspective we can see that, for all its heterogeneity, classical political 
economy did manage to compress much of the varied experience of its day 
into a compact body of literature that reflects the history of relations of
introduction 9 
production. Hence, the study of classical political economy provides an ef-fective 
vantage point for the study of the history of relations of production. 
Chapter 6 analyzes the role of primitive accumulation in the works of 
such early economists as Sir William Petty, Richard Cantillon, and the 
Physiocrats. 
Chapter 7 concentrates on the important work of Steuart, by far the 
most interesting and the most incisive theorist of primitive accumulation 
and the social division of labor prior to Marx. Besides seeing the implica-tions 
of primitive accumulation more clearly than the other classical po-litical 
economists, Steuart stood alone in his willingness to write openly 
and honestly about the subject. This characteristic explains the compara-tive 
obscurity of his reputation. 
Next, chapters 8 through 10 are devoted exclusively to Smith, who 
attempted to develop an alternative to Steuart. According to Smithian 
theory, the social division of labor would evolve in a satisfactory manner 
without recourse to outside intervention. This chapter demonstrates that 
even Smith’s celebrated discussion of the invisible hand was developed as 
a means of avoiding the challenge that primitive accumulation posed for 
his system. By showing that the social division of labor would evolve 
without recourse to outside intervention, Smith had hoped to put the 
question of primitive accumulation to rest. Although Smith’s theory was 
accepted as such, practice continued in a different manner. In fact, Smith 
himself advocated practices that were not in accordance with his theory. 
This chapter also indicates that Smith was far more interested in chang-ing 
human behavior than he was with matters of economic development. 
Chapter 9 examines how Smith attempted to distort history, sociology, 
and psychology to provide confirmation of this theory of the naturally 
evolving social division of labor. 
Chapter 10 continues with the work of Adam Smith, who based much 
of his theory on the experience of the colonies. Although Smith made 
great use of the colonial experience, the colonials did not take him nearly 
as seriously as the English did. The reason is not hard to fathom. In har-nessing 
the story of the colonies to his ideological cart, Smith did not do 
justice to the actual situation in the colonies. By tracing his analysis of the 
colonies, this chapter delves deeper into the manner in which Smith pur-posely 
obscured the nature of the social division of labor. 
Chapter 11 continues the study of Smithian theory and practice by 
comparing Smith with his friend Benjamin Franklin. This genial Ameri-can 
was a man of practice rather than theory, yet his practical analysis 
greatly influenced the theory of his day. Franklin’s role is especially key to 
Smith’s theory of colonial development.
10 
Chapter 12 continues the analysis of the relationship of classical politi-cal 
economy and primitive accumulation into the age of David Ricardo and 
Thomas Robert Malthus. By reading their works and those of their contem-poraries 
in terms of their relationship to political economy, we provide a 
new twist to the different interpretation of classical political economy. 
This chapter reveals that despite the adherence to the doctrine of laissez-faire 
in theory, classical political economists maintained a strong interest 
in promoting policies that furthered primitive accumulation. 
Chapter 13 investigates the reaction against Smith, beginning with the 
relatively unknown work of Robert Gourlay and the development of his 
ideas in the practical school of Wakefield, the systemic colonizer who 
stressed that the social division of labor should be organized for the pur-pose 
of capitalist development. The chapter concludes with an analysis of 
John Rae. 
Chapter 14 discusses the commonality between Smith and such later 
revolutionary leaders as Vladimir Ilyich Lenin and Mao Tse-Tung. 
Dark Designs 
Classical political economy is the product of a stormy period, distin-guished 
by the emergence of capitalist social relations. These truly mo-mentous 
changes of the time do not seem to appear in the great theoretical 
works of the time. Indeed, the classical political economists displayed 
little interest in conveying information about the great conflicts between 
capital and labor, or between capital and early precapitalist relations in 
the countryside. Nonetheless, these matters were of great importance to 
classical political economy. 
While we catch an occasional glimpse of primitive accumulation in the 
canonical works of classical political economy, for the most part, we must 
read of the glaring conflicts indirectly. Our tactic is to approach classical 
political economy in the way that children learn to view a solar eclipse: by 
punching a small hole in a piece of paper held above another piece. The 
dark design that appears on the lower paper is the shadow of an eclipse, 
albeit with some refraction. The classical political economists made this 
indirect approach necessary because they were generally successful in 
obscuring the role of primitive accumulation in their theoretical texts. 
Yet, as mentioned earlier, when we turn to their letters, diaries, and more 
policy-oriented works, the importance of primitive accumulation be-comes 
far clearer. 
We can push our analogy of classical political economy and solar 
eclipses a bit further. Both represent rare and fascinating events. Past
introduction 11 
peoples have superstitiously interpreted solar eclipses as signs of im-pending 
epochal change. Similarly, the titans of political economy were 
thought to have been able to see over the heads of their contemporaries 
into the future. In this sense, their theories foreshadowed coming changes 
in the structure of society. 
Both phenomena, planetary configurations found millions of miles 
away and the social changes of a century or more ago, reflect important 
forces that still shape our lives. Specifically, the struggle against self-provisioning 
is not confined to the distant past. It continues to this day 
(see Perelman 1991b). In effect, we can look at the eclipse of precapitalist 
production relations in much the same fashion, with one major exception: 
in the case of a solar eclipse, the brilliance of the source can destroy our 
vision. In the case of classical political economy, the source has attempted 
to obscure our vision. 
Revising Classical Political Economy 
Our classical forbearers may have been bright, but they were also fallible 
human beings. They were certainly not wholly disinterested observers. 
Their theories were intended to advance their own interests or those of the 
groups with whom they identified. These interests colored their works, 
whether or not they realized this influence themselves. 
In regard to the struggle over primitive accumulation, these writers 
seem to have been intentionally obscure insofar as they could, lest they 
undermine their claim to generality for their theory. The struggle against 
the self-provisioning of rural people cast only a light shadow across the 
pages of classical political economy, a glimpse of an all-but-forgotten 
way of life obliterated by the process of primitive accumulation. Conse-quently, 
this process has largely gone unnoticed by modern readers of 
classical political economy. 
Although we find ourselves reduced to studying the shadows of this 
struggle, the attempt is still worth the effort. Indeed, we will see that 
classical political economy conforms to a consistent pattern of almost 
always supporting positions that would work to harness small-scale agri-cultural 
producers to the interests of capital. 
This book may be controversial in that it contradicts the commonly 
accepted theory that classical political economy offered its unconditional 
support for the doctrine of laissez-faire. It questions the relative impor-tance 
of the almost universally admired Smith and makes the case that 
Smith and other classical authors sought to promote the process of primi-tive 
accumulation. This rereading suggests that classical political econ-
12 
omy followed a different project, one that contradicts the standard inter-pretation 
of classical political economy. 
Before turning to the main body of this work, I wish to append a caveat 
about my imagery of the eclipse. By studying the shadows cast by the 
classics, we must keep in mind that such images have fewer dimensions 
than the object under study. One dimension that disappears from the 
perspective of classical political economy concerns the social relations 
between labor and capital. Writing from the comfortable heights of their 
elevated social position, the classical political economists interpreted 
working-class organization as mere disorder. Because of this insensitivity, 
a work such as this one is necessarily imbalanced. Much attention is 
given to the efforts of capital to control labor, but little is devoted to the 
reverse. I leave the reader with the responsibility of estimating the actual 
balance of forces. 
I hope that this book succeeds in making three points. First, primitive 
accumulation was an important force in capitalist development. Second, 
primitive accumulation cannot be relegated to a precapitalist past or even 
some imagined moment when feudal society suddenly became capitalist. 
Primitive accumulation played a continuing role in capitalist develop-ment. 
Third, classical political economy was concerned with promoting 
primitive accumulation in order to foster capitalist development, even 
though the logic of primitive accumulation was in direct conflict with 
the classical political economists’ purported adherence to the values of 
laissez-faire. 
I recognize that the seeds of capitalism had been planted long before the 
age of classical political economy, but never before and nowhere else had 
the process of capital accumulation become so intense. Hopefully, The 
Invention of Capitalism will throw light on the origins of that intensity.
chapter 1 The Enduring Importance 
of Primitive Accumulation 
Common fields and pastures kept alive a vigorous co-operative spirit in the com-munity; 
enclosures starved it. In champion [sic] country people had to work to-gether 
amicably, to agree upon crop rotations, stints of common pasture, the up-keep 
and improvement of their grazings and meadows, the clearing of the ditches, 
the fencing of the fields. They toiled side by side in the fields, and they walked 
together from field to village, from farm to heath, morning, afternoon and evening. 
They all depended on common resources for their fuel, for bedding, and fodder for 
their stock, and by pooling so many of the necessities of livelihood they were 
disciplined from early youth to submit to the rules and customs of the community. 
After enclosure, when every man could fence his own piece of territory and warn 
his neighbours off, the discipline of sharing things fairly with one’s neighbours was 
relaxed, and every household became an island unto itself. This was the great 
revolution in men’s lives, greater than all the economic changes following en-closure. 
Yet few people living in this world bequeathed to us by the enclosing and 
improving farmer are capable of gauging the full significance of a way of life that is 
now lost.—Joan Thirsk, ‘‘Enclosing and Engrossing’’ 
Compulsion and the Creation of a Working Class 
The brutal process of separating people from their means of providing for 
themselves, known as primitive accumulation, caused enormous hard-ships 
for the common people. This same primitive accumulation pro-vided 
a basis for capitalist development. Joan Thirsk, one of the most 
knowledgeable historians of early British agriculture, describes above the 
nature of some of the harshest social and personal transformations associ-ated 
with the enclosures. 
Some people denounced this expropriation. Marx (1977, 928) echoed 
their sentiment, charging: ‘‘The expropriation of the direct producers was 
accomplished by means of the most merciless barbarianism, and under 
the stimulus of the most infamous, the most sordid, the most petty and 
the most odious of passions.’’ 
Formally, this dispossession was perfectly legal. After all, the peasants 
did not have property rights in the narrow sense. They only had tradi-
14 
tional rights. As markets evolved, first land-hungry gentry and later the 
bourgeoisie used the state to create a legal structure to abrogate these 
traditional rights (Tigar and Levy 1977). 
Simple dispossession from the commons was a necessary, but not al-ways 
sufficient condition to harness rural people to the labor market. 
Even after the enclosures, laborers retained privileges in ‘‘the shrubs, 
woods, undergrowth, stone quarries and gravel pits, thereby obtaining 
fuel for cooking and wood for animal life, crab apples and cob nuts from 
the hedgerows, brambles, tansy and other wild herbs from any other little 
patch of waste. . . . Almost every living thing in the parish however insig-nificant 
could be turned to some good use by the frugal peasant-labourer 
or his wife’’ (Everitt 1967, 405). 
To the extent that the traditional economy might be able to remain 
intact despite the loss of the commons, a supply of labor satisfactory to 
capital might not be forthcoming. As a result, the level of real wages 
would be higher, thereby impeding the process of accumulation. Not sur-prisingly, 
one by one, these traditional rights also disappeared. In the eyes 
of the bourgeoisie, ‘‘property became absolute property: all the tolerated 
‘rights’ that the peasantry had acquired or preserved . . . were now re-jected’’ 
(Foucault 1979, 85). 
Primitive accumulation cut through traditional lifeways like scissors. 
The first blade served to undermine the ability of people to provide for 
themselves. The other blade was a system of stern measures required to 
keep people from finding alternative survival strategies outside the sys-tem 
of wage labor. A host of oftentimes brutal laws designed to under-mine 
whatever resistance people maintained against the demands of wage 
labor accompanied the dispossession of the peasants’ rights, even before 
capitalism had become a significant economic force. 
For example, beginning with the Tudors, England enacted a series of 
stern measures to prevent peasants from drifting into vagrancy or falling 
back onto welfare systems. According to a 1572 statute, beggars over the 
age of fourteen were to be severely flogged and branded with a red-hot iron 
on the left ear unless someone was willing to take them into service for 
two years. Repeat offenders over eighteen were to be executed unless 
someone would take them into service. Third offenses automatically re-sulted 
in execution (Marx 1977, 896ff.; Marx 1974, 736; Mantoux 1961, 
432). Similar statutes appeared almost simultaneously during the early 
sixteenth century in England, the Low Countries, and Zurich (LeRoy 
Ladurie 1974, 137). Eventually, the majority of workers, lacking any alter-native, 
had little choice but to work for wages at something close to 
subsistence level.
importance of primitive accumulation 15 
In the wake of primitive accumulation, the wage relationship became a 
seemingly voluntary affair. Workers needed employment and employers 
wanted workers. In reality, of course, the underlying process was far from 
voluntary. As Foucault (1979, 222) argues: 
Historically, the process by which the bourgeoisie became the politi-cally 
dominant class in the course of the 18th Century was masked by 
the establishment of an explicitly coded and formally egalitarian 
juridical framework, made possible by the organization of a parlia-mentary, 
representative regime. But the development and generaliza-tion 
of disciplinary mechanisms constituted the other, dark side of 
these processes . . . supported by these tiny, everyday, physical mech-anisms, 
by all those systems of micro-power that are essentially non-egalitarian. 
Indeed, the history of the recruitment of labor is an uninterrupted story of 
coercion either through the brute force of poverty or more direct regula-tion, 
which made a continuation of the old ways impossible (Moore 1951). 
Of course, the extractions common to traditional relatively self-sufficient 
household economy kept many people at or just above the subsistence 
level, but for many the market was a step backward. The disorienting 
introduction of the individualistic ways of the market cut people off 
from their traditional networks and created a sense of dehumanization 
(see Kuczynski 1967, 70). A purported need for discipline justified the 
harsh measures that the poor endured. Indeed, writers of every persuasion 
shared an obsessional concern with the creation of a disciplined labor 
force (Furniss 1965; Appleby 1978). Supporters of such measures typically 
defended their position by invoking the need to civilize workers or stamp 
out sloth and indolence. Yet capital required these measures to conquer 
the household economy in order to be able to extract a greater mass of 
surplus value. In fact, almost everyone close to the process of primitive 
accumulation, whether a friend or foe of labor, agreed with Charles Hall’s 
(1805, 144) verdict that ‘‘if they were not poor, they would not submit 
to employments’’—at least so long as their remuneration were held low 
enough to create substantial profits. 
Employers were quick to perceive the relationship between poverty and 
the chance to earn handsome profits. Ambrose Crowley, for example, set 
up his factory in the north rather than the midlands, for there ‘‘the cuntry 
is verry poore and populous soe workmen must of necessity increase’’ 
(cited in Pollard 1965, 197). This process was cumulative. An increase in 
poverty begat more population, which in turn created further poverty, and 
so on. In this regard, Marx (1865, 72) noted that the level of wages in the
16 
agricultural districts of England varied according to the particular condi-tions 
under which the peasantry had emerged from serfdom. The more 
impoverished the serfs, the lower their descendants’ wages would be. 
Classical Political Economy and the War on Sloth 
The classical political economists joined in the chorus of those condemn-ing 
the sloth and indolence of the poor. Although they applauded the 
leisure activities of the rich, they denounced all behavior on the part of the 
less fortunate that did not yield a maximum of work effort. 
Consider the case of Francis Hutcheson—‘‘the never to be forgotten 
Dr. Hutcheson,’’ as his student, Adam Smith, later described him in a 
letter to Dr. Archibald Davidson (reprinted in Mossner and Ross 1977, 
309)—the same Francis Hutcheson whose Short Introduction to Moral 
Philosophy in Three Books (1742) seems to have served as a model for 
the economic sections of Smith’s Glasgow lectures (see Scott 1965, 235, 
240). A later work, his System of Moral Philosophy, exemplifies Dr. 
Hutcheson’s contributions to that noble field of moral philosophy. After a 
few brief notes on the need to raise prices, Hutcheson (1755, 2:318–19) 
mused: ‘‘If a people have not acquired an habit of industry, the cheapness 
of all the necessaries of life encourages sloth. The best remedy is to raise 
the demand for all necessaries. . . . Sloth should be punished by tempo-rary 
servitude at least.’’ The menacing ‘‘at least’’ in this citation suggests 
that the never-to-be-forgotten professor might have had even sterner med-icine 
in mind than mere temporary servitude. What else might the good 
doctor recommend to earnest students of moral philosophy in the event 
that temporary servitude proved inadequate in shunting people off to the 
workplace? 
This attitude, of course, is not unique to classical political economy. We 
might ask, was there ever a nation in which the rich found the poor to be 
sufficiently industrious? The universal howl of ‘‘sloth and indolence’’ can 
be heard as far away as nineteenth-century Japan, to cite one example (see 
T. Smith 1966, 120). However, no country seems to have gone as far as 
England in its war on sloth. Indeed, writers of the time charged that a want 
of discipline was responsible for criminality as well as disease. By the late 
eighteenth century, even hospitals came to be regarded as a proper me-dium 
to instill discipline (see Ignatieff 1978, 61ff.). 
Almost poetically, Thomas Mun (1664, 193) railed against ‘‘the general 
leprosy of our piping, potting, feasting, fashions, and misspending of our 
time in idleness and pleasure.’’ Josiah Tucker (1776a, 44–45) employed a 
military metaphor to make a similar point:
importance of primitive accumulation 17 
In a word, the only possible Means of preventing a Rival Nation from 
running away with your Trade, is to prevent your own People from 
being more idle and vicious than they are. . . . So the only War, which 
can be attended with Success in that Respect, is a War against Vice 
and Idleness; a War, whose Forces must consist of—not Fleets and 
Armies—but such judicious Taxes and Wise regulations, as will turn 
the Passion of private Self-Love into the Channel of Public Good. 
Primitive Accumulation and the Eradication of Holidays 
Although their standard of living may not have been particularly lavish, 
the people of precapitalistic northern Europe, like most traditional peo-ple, 
enjoyed a great deal of free time (see Ashton 1972, 204; see also 
V. Smith 1992; Wisman 1989). The common people maintained innumer-able 
religious holidays that punctuated the tempo of work. Joan Thirsk 
estimated that in the sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries, about 
one-third of the working days, including Sundays, were spent in leisure 
(cited in K. Thomas 1964, 63; see also Wilensky 1961). Karl Kautsky (1899, 
107) offered a much more extravagant estimate that 204 annual holidays 
were celebrated in medieval Lower Bavaria. 
Despite these frequent holidays, the peasants still managed to produce a 
significant surplus. In English feudal society, for example, the peasants 
survived even though the gentry was powerful enough to extract some-thing 
on the order of 50 percent of the produce (see Postan 1966, 603). As 
markets evolved, the claims on the peasants’ labors multiplied. For in-stance, 
in southern France, rents appear to have grown from about one-fourth 
of the yield in 1540 to one-half by 1665 (LeRoy Ladurie 1974, 117). 
Although people increasingly had to curtail their leisure in order to meet 
the growing demands of nonproducers, many observers still railed against 
the excessive celebration of holidays. Protestant clergy were especially 
vocal in this regard (Hill 1967, 145–218; see also Marx 1977, 387; Freuden-berger 
and Cummins 1976). Even as late as the 1830s, we hear the com-plaint 
that the Irish working year contained only 200 days after all holidays 
had been subtracted (Great Britain 1840, 570; cited in Mokyr 1983, 222). 
Time, in a market society, is money. As Sir Henry Pollexfen (1700, 45; 
cited in Furniss 1965, 44) calculated: ‘‘For if but 2 million of working 
people at 6d. a day comes to 500,000£ which upon due inquiry whence our 
riches must arise, will appear to be so much lost to the nation by every 
holiday that is kept.’’ 
Zeal in the suppression of religious festivals was not an indication that 
representatives of capital took working-class devotion lightly. In some
18 
rural districts of nineteenth-century England, tending to one’s garden on 
the Sabbath was a punishable offense. Some workers were even impris-oned 
for this crime (Marx 1977, 375–76n). Piety, however, also had its 
limits. The same worker might be charged with breach of contract should 
he prefer to attend church on the Sabbath rather than report for work 
when called to do so (ibid.). 
In France, where capital was slower to take charge, the eradication of 
holidays was likewise slower. Tobias Smollett (1766, 38) complained of 
the French: ‘‘Very nearly half of their time, which might be profitably 
employed in the exercise of industry, is lost to themselves and the com-munity, 
in attendance upon the different exhibitions of religious mum-mery.’’ 
Voltaire called for the shifting of holidays to the following Sunday. 
Since Sunday was a day of rest in any case, employers could enjoy approxi-mately 
forty additional working days per year. This proposal caused the 
naive Abbe Baudeau to wonder about the wisdom of intensifying work 
when the countryside was already burdened with an excess population 
(cited in Weulersse 1959, 28). How could the dispossessed be employed? 
Of course, changes in the religious practices of Europe were not induced 
by a shortage of people but by people’s willingness to conform to the needs 
of capital. For example, the leaders of the French Revolution, who prided 
themselves on their rationality, decreed a ten-day week with only a single 
day off. Classical political economists enthusiastically joined in the con-demnation 
of the celebration of an excessive number of holidays (see 
Cantillon 1755, 95; Senior 1831, 9). The suppression of religious holidays 
was but a small part of the larger process of primitive accumulation. 
Classical Political Economy and the Ideal Working Day 
Once capital began to dislodge the traditional moorings of society, the 
bourgeoisie sought every possible opportunity to engage people in produc-tive 
work that would turn a profit for employers. Accordingly, classical 
political economists advocated actions to shape society around the logic 
of accumulation in order to strengthen the dependency on wage labor. 
In the utopia of early classical political economy, the poor would work 
every waking hour. One writer suggested that the footmen of the gentry 
could rise early to employ their idle hours making fishing nets along with 
‘‘disbanded soldiers, poor prisoners, widows and orphans, all poor trades-men, 
artificers, and labourers, their wives, children, and servants’’ (Puckle 
1700, 2:380; cited in Appleby 1976, 501). 
Joseph Townsend (1786, 442) proposed that when farm workers re-turned 
in the evenings from threshing or ploughing, ‘‘they might card,
importance of primitive accumulation 19 
they might spin, or they might knit.’’ Many were concerned that chil-dren’s 
time might go to waste. William Temple called for the addition of 
four-year-old children to the labor force. Anticipating modern Skinnerian 
psychology, Temple (1770, 266; see also Furniss 1965, 114–15) speculated, 
‘‘for by these means, we hope that the rising generation will be so habitu-ated 
to constant employment that it would at length prove agreeable and 
entertaining to them.’’ Not to be outdone, John Locke, often seen as a 
philosopher of liberty, called for the commencement of work at the ripe 
age of three (Cranston 1957, 425). 
Others called for new institutional arrangements to ensure a steadily 
increasing flow of wage labor. Fletcher of Saltoun recommended perpetual 
slavery as the appropriate fate of all who would fail to respond to less 
harsh measures to integrate them into the labor force (see Marx 1977, 
882). Hutcheson, as we have seen, followed suit. Always the idealist, 
Bishop George Berkeley (1740, 456) preferred that such slavery be limited 
to ‘‘a certain term of years.’’ 
No source of labor was to be overlooked. For example, in a movement 
that Foucault has termed ‘‘the great confinement,’’ institutions were 
founded to take charge indiscriminately of the sick, criminal, and poor 
(Foucault 1965, 38–65). The purpose was not to better the conditions of 
the inmates but rather to force them to contribute more to the national 
wealth (for a selection of citations that reflect more charitably on the early 
political economists, see Wiles 1968). 
Occasionally, writers of the time found signs of progress. By 1723, 
Daniel Defoe (1724–26, 86; see also 493) was delighted to discover that so 
much progress had taken place in Norwich that ‘‘the very children after 
four or five years of age, could every one earn their own bread.’’ 
For classical political economy such edifying scenes of hard labor were 
not common enough. To his credit, Jean-Baptiste Say (1821, 50–51; see 
also Ricardo 1951–73, 8:184), generally a strong proponent of capitalist 
development, penned one of the few protests of the state of affairs in 
Britain in a letter to Robert Malthus: 
I shall not attempt to point out the parts of this picture which apply to 
your country, Sir. . . . But if social life [a term that Say used almost like 
the social division of labor] were a galley, in which after rowing with 
all their strength for sixteen hours out of the twenty-four, they might 
indeed be excused for disliking social life. . . . I maintain no other 
doctrine when I say that the utility of productions is no longer worth 
the productive services, at the rate at which we are compelled to pay 
for them.
20 
Sadly, no other classical political economist was willing to side with Say 
in this regard. 
Bentham and Laissez-faire Authoritarianism 
Classical political economy frequently couched its recommendations in a 
rhetoric of individual liberty, but its conception of liberty was far from all-encompassing. 
Liberty, for capital, depended on the hard work of common 
people. 
Lionel Robbins (1981, 8), a strong proponent of market society, also 
alluded to this authoritarian side of laissez-faire, noting, ‘‘the necessity of 
a framework of law and an apparatus of enforcement is an essential part of 
the concept of a free society.’’ Earlier, he wrote, ‘‘If there be any ‘invisible 
hand’ in a non-collectivist order, it operates only in a framework of delib-erately 
contrived law and order’’ (Robbins 1939, 6; see also Samuels 1966). 
Within this contrived law and order, workers found their rights to orga-nize 
unions and even to act politically severely restricted. The entire 
judicial edifice was erected with an eye toward making ownership of capi-tal 
more profitable (Tigar and Levy 1977). 
Max Weber (1921, 108; see also Perelman 1991a, chap. 3) once observed 
that rational accounting methods are ‘‘associated with the social phe-nomena 
of ‘shop discipline’ and appropriation of the means of production, 
and that means: with the existence of a ‘system of domination’ [Herr-schaftsverhältniss].’’ 
Similarly, the rational accounting system of politi-cal 
economy required a ‘‘system of domination,’’ albeit on a grander scale. 
Weber concluded, ‘‘No special proof is necessary to show that military 
discipline is the ideal model for the modern capitalist factory’’ (1156). 
In this sense, we may see Jeremy Bentham, rather than Smith, as the 
archetypal representative of classical political economy. Indeed, Ben-tham’s 
dogmatic advocacy of laissez-faire far exceeded that of Smith. For 
example, after Smith made the case for a government role in controlling 
interest rates, Bentham (1787b, 133) caustically rebuked him with the 
words, ‘‘To prevent our doing mischief to one another, it is but too neces-sary 
to put bridles into our mouths.’’ 
Although Bentham theoretically championed laissez-faire in the name 
of freedom, he was intent on subordinating all aspects of life to the in-terests 
of accumulation. Bentham limited his passionate concern with 
laissez-faire to those who conformed to the norms of a capitalist society; a 
jarring confrontation with state power was to be the lot of the rest. Accord-ing 
to Bentham, ‘‘Property—not the institution of property, but the consti-tution 
of property—has become an end in itself’’ (Bentham 1952, 1:117).
importance of primitive accumulation 21 
Bentham was absolutely clear about the need for this ‘‘constitution of 
property.’’ He realized that even though control over labor is a major 
source of wealth, labor stubbornly resists the will of the capitalist. In 
Bentham’s (1822, 430) inimitable language: 
Human beings are the most powerful instruments of production, and 
therefore everyone becomes anxious to employ the services of his 
fellows in multiplying his own comforts. Hence the intense and uni-versal 
thirst for power; the equally prevalent hatred of subjection. 
Each man therefore meets with an obstinate resistance to his own 
will, and this naturally engenders antipathy toward beings who thus 
baffle and contravene his wishes. 
Bentham never acknowledged any contradiction between his advocacy of 
laissez-faire and his proposals for managing labor. For him: ‘‘Between 
wealth and power, the connexion is most close and intimate: so intimate, 
indeed, that the disentanglement of them, even in the imagination, is a 
matter of no small difficulty. They are each of them respectively an in-strument 
of the production of the other’’ (Bentham 1962, 48; cited in 
Macpherson 1987, 88–89). 
Bentham understood that the struggles to subdue the poor would spill 
over into every aspect of life. He hoped to turn these struggles into profit 
for himself and, to a lesser extent, others of his class. Given labor’s natural 
resistance to creating wealth for those who exploited them, unfree labor 
held an obvious attraction for Bentham. He designed detailed plans for his 
fabled Panopticon, a prison engineered for maximum control of inmates 
in order to profit from their labor. 
In a 1798 companion piece to his design for the Panopticon, Pauper 
Management Improved, Bentham proposed a National Charity Company 
modeled after the East India Company—a privately owned, joint stock 
company partially subsidized by the government. It was to have absolute 
authority over the ‘‘whole body of the burdensome poor,’’ starting with 
250 industry houses accommodating a half million people and expanding 
to 500 houses for one million people (Bentham n.d., 369; cited in Him-melfarb 
1985, 78). 
Bentham planned to profit handsomely from these inmates, especially 
those born in the houses, since they would then have to work as appren-tices 
within the company. He rhapsodized, ‘‘So many industry-houses, so 
many crucibles, in which dross of this kind [the poor] is converted into 
sterling’’ (cited in Himmelfarb 1985, 80). A strict regimen, unremitting 
supervision and discipline, and economies of diet, dress, and lodging 
would make profits possible. Jeremy Bentham, vigorous advocate of free-
22 
dom of commerce that he was, dreamed of the profits that would accrue 
from the use of inmate labor: 
What hold can another manufacturer have upon his workmen, equal 
to what my manufacturer would have upon his? What other master is 
there that can reduce his workmen, if idle, to a situation next to 
starving, without suffering them to go elsewhere? What other master 
is there whose men can never get drunk unless he chooses that they 
should do so. And who, so far from being able to raise their wages by 
combination, are obliged to take whatever pittance he thinks it most 
his interest to allow? (see also Ignatieff 1978, 110; Foucault 1979) 
According to classical political economy, all social conditions and all 
social institutions were to be judged merely on the basis of their effect on 
the production of wealth. In this spirit, Bentham recommended that chil-dren 
be put to work at four instead of fourteen, bragging that they would 
thereby be spared the loss of those ‘‘ten precious years in which nothing is 
done! Nothing for industry! Nothing for improvement, moral or intellec-tual!’’ 
(cited in Himmelfarb 1985, 81). 
Bentham went even further, intent on subordinating every facet of hu-man 
existence to the profit motive. He even wanted to promote the ‘‘gen-tlest 
of all revolutions,’’ the sexual revolution. In this regard, Bentham 
was not the least concerned with furthering the bounds of human free-dom, 
but with ensuring that the inmates would have as many offspring as 
possible (ibid., 83). Bentham was even planning to call himself the ‘‘Sub- 
Regulus of the Poor.’’ Unfortunately, because of lack of government sup-port, 
his plans came to naught. As he complained in his memoirs, ‘‘But for 
George the Third, all the prisoners in England would, years ago, have been 
made under my management’’ (Bentham 1830–31, 96). 
Alas, Bentham never succeeded in his personal goals. Perhaps he was 
too greedy. Perhaps his methods were too crude. Instead, as we shall see, 
capitalism found more subtle methods for harnessing labor. As a result, 
today we remember Bentham as a valiant defender of the ideals of laissez-faire 
rather than as the Sub-Regulus of the Poor. 
Victory 
Classical political economists were generally more coy about their inten-tions 
than Bentham. Despite their antipathy to indolence and sloth, they 
covered themselves with a flurry of rhetoric about natural liberties. On 
closer examination, we find that the notion of the system of natural liber-ties 
was considerably more flexible than it appeared. Let us turn once
importance of primitive accumulation 23 
again to Francis Hutcheson, who taught Smith about the virtue of natural 
liberty. He contended that ‘‘it is the one great design of civil laws to 
strengthen by political sanctions the several laws of nature. . . . The pop-ulace 
needs to be taught, and engaged by laws, into the best methods 
of managing their own affairs and exercising mechanic art’’ (Hutcheson 
1749, 273; emphasis added). In effect, Hutcheson realized that once primi-tive 
accumulation had taken place, the appeal of formal slavery dimin-ished. 
Extramarket forces of all sorts would become unnecessary, since 
the market itself would ensure that the working class remained in a con-tinual 
state of deprivation. Patrick Colquhoun (1815, 110), a London po-lice 
magistrate, noted: 
Poverty is that state and condition in society where the individual 
has no surplus labour in store, or, in other words, no property or 
means of subsistence but what is derived from the constant exercise 
of industry in the various occupations of life. Poverty is therefore 
a most necessary and indispensable ingredient in society, without 
which nations and communities could not exist in a state of civiliza-tion. 
It is the lot of man. It is the source of wealth, since without 
poverty, there could be no labour; there could be no riches, no re-finement, 
no comfort, and no benefit to those who may be possessed 
of wealth. 
Or, as Marx (1865, 55–56) phrased it: ‘‘We find on the market a set of 
buyers, possessed of land, machinery, raw materials, and the means of 
subsistence, all of them, save land, the products of labour, and on the 
other hand, a set of sellers who have nothing to sell except their labouring 
power, their working arms and brains.’’ 
Later political economists disregarded the compulsion required to force 
labor into the market, blithely assuming that the market alone was suffi-cient 
to guarantee the advancement of the accumulation process without 
the aid of extramarket forces. Workers at the time generally understood 
the strategic importance of measures to foster primitive accumulation. In 
this spirit, Thomas Spence, a courageous working-class advocate, pro-claimed 
that ‘‘it is childish . . . to expect . . . to see anything else than the 
utmost screwing and grinding of the poor, till you quite overturn the 
present system of landed property’’ (cited in E. P. Thompson 1963, 805). 
The system, however, was not overturned, but instead grew stronger. 
Workers were forced to surrender more and more of their traditional peri-ods 
of leisure (see Hill 1967; Reid 1976, 76–101). The working day was 
lengthened (Hammond and Hammond 1919, 5–7). The working class, in 
the person of Spence, cried out: ‘‘Instead of working only six days a week
24 
we are obliged to work at the rate of eight or nine and yet can hardly 
subsist . . . and still the cry is work—work—ye are idle. . . . We, God help us, 
have fallen under the hardest set of masters that have ever existed’’ (cited 
in Kemp-Ashraf 1966, 277; see also Tawney 1926, esp. 223). This state-ment 
was eloquent enough to earn its author a sentence of three years’ 
imprisonment after its publication in 1803—a result typical of the fate of 
those who challenged the capitalist order. Whenever the working class 
and its friends effectively protested against capitalism, the silent compul-sion 
of capital (Marx 1977, 899) gave way to compulsory silence. 
Spence’s silencing was not completely effective. Although some merely 
wrote him off as a ‘‘radical crank’’ (Knox 1977, 73), more recent studies 
have demonstrated that Spence deserves a more respectful reception 
(Kemp-Ashraf 1966). Indeed, Spence’s biographer asserts that Owenism 
and the subsequent heritage of British socialism stands in direct line of 
descent from Spence’s critique of capitalism (Rudkin 1966, 191ff.). Jour-nalists 
of the time agreed with this evaluation (see Halevy 1961, 44n). 
Unfortunately, the Spences of the world were unable to reverse or even 
impede the process of primitive accumulation. 
No society went so far as the British in terms of primitive accumula-tion. 
This aspect of capitalist development is all but forgotten today. In-stead, 
separated by two centuries, contemporary economists such as Mil-ton 
Friedman (1962) gloss over the dark side of capitalism, ignoring the 
requisite subordination, while celebrating the freedom to dispose of one’s 
property. These modern economists, as we shall see, are very much mis-taken 
in their interpretation of the evolution of the so-called free market.
chapter 2 The Theory of Primitive Accumulation 
Analytical Preliminaries 
Although primitive accumulation was a central concern to classical polit-ical 
economists, the study of this concept began in confusion and later 
settled into an unfortunate obscurity. The seemingly Marxian expression, 
‘‘primitive accumulation,’’ originally began with Adam Smith’s (Smith 
1976, 2.3, 277) assertion that ‘‘the accumulation of stock must, in the 
nature of things, be previous to the division of labour.’’ 
Smith’s approach to original accumulation is odd, to say the least. Cer-tainly, 
the division of labor is to be found throughout history. It even 
exists in insect societies (see Morely 1954). Yet Smith would have us 
believe that the division of labor had to wait for ‘‘the accumulation of 
stock,’’ his code word for capital. Such an idea is patently false. How could 
we interpret the division of labor in an anthill or a beehive as a conse-quence 
of the accumulation of stock? 
Marx translated Smith’s word, ‘‘previous’’ as ‘‘ursprünglich’’ (Marx and 
Engels 1973, 33:741), which Marx’s English translators, in turn, rendered 
as ‘‘primitive.’’ In the process, Marx rejected Smith’s otherworldly con-ception 
of previous accumulation. He chided Smith for attempting to 
explain the present existence of class by reference to a mythical past that 
lies beyond our ability to challenge it. Marx insisted, ‘‘Primitive accumu-lation 
plays approximately the same role in political economy as original 
sin does in theology’’ (1977, 873). Marx’s analogy is apt. Both original sin 
and original accumulation divert our attention away from the present to a 
mythical past, which supposedly explains the misfortunes that people 
suffer today. 
In other words, any theory based on either original sin or original ac-cumulation 
is both excessively and insufficiently historical. It is exces-sively 
historical because it situates the subject in a remote past, discon-nected 
from contemporary society. It is insufficiently historical because 
it relies on a mythical treatment of the past. Etienne Balibar’s (1988, 49) 
expression, ‘‘ahistorical historicism, or the historicity without history in
26 
Marx’s thought,’’ is an appropriate characterization of this part of Marx’s 
work. 
To underscore his distance from Smith, Marx prefixed the pejorative 
‘‘so-called’’ to the title of the final part of the first volume of Capital, 
which he devoted to the study of primitive accumulation. Marx, in es-sence, 
dismissed Smith’s mythical ‘‘previous’’ accumulation, in order to 
call attention to the actual historical experience. In contrast to the ‘‘so-called’’ 
primitive accumulation, Marx analyzed in detail the brutality of 
the actual historical experience of separating people from their means of 
production in an effort to lay bare the origin of the capitalist system. 
The Historical Basis of Primitive Accumulation 
The contrast between Smith’s scanty treatment of previous accumulation 
and Marx’s extensive documentation of the subject is striking. Marx’s 
(1977, 915) survey of primitive accumulation carries us through a several-centuries- 
long process, in which a small group of people brutally expropri-ated 
the means of production from the people of precapitalist society 
around the globe: 
The discovery of gold and silver in America, the extirpation, enslave-ment 
and entombment in mines of the indigenous population of that 
continent, the beginnings of the conquest and plunder of India, and 
the conversion of Africa into a preserve for the commercial hunting of 
blackskins, are all things which characterize the dawn of the era of 
capitalist production. These idyllic proceedings are the chief mo-ments 
of primitive accumulation. 
Marx did not limit his interpretation of primitive accumulation to iso-lated 
pockets of the world. The fruits of primitive accumulation are fun-gible. 
For example, he insisted that ‘‘a great deal of capital, which appears 
today in the United States without any birth-certificate, was yesterday, in 
England, the capitalized blood of children’’ (ibid., 920). 
According to Smith, economic development progressed through the 
voluntary acts of the participants. Marx (ibid., 926), in contrast, believed 
that ‘‘capital comes dripping from head to toe, from every pore, with blood 
and dirt.’’ Workers were ‘‘tortured by grotesquely terroristic laws into 
accepting the discipline necessary for the system of wage-labour’’ (ibid., 
899). Where Smith scrupulously avoided any analysis of social relations, 
Marx produced an elaborate study of the connection between the develop-ment 
of capitalistic social relations and so-called primitive accumulation. 
In later years, Marx displayed an impatience with those who failed to
theory of primitive accumulation 27 
ground their treatment of primitive accumulation in concrete historical 
analysis. For example, he chastised Nikolai Mikhailovsky’s suprahis-torical 
presentation of primitive accumulation, in which the latter me-chanically 
extrapolated Russia’s future from Marx’s analysis of the Euro-pean 
experience of primitive accumulation (letter to the editorial board of 
Otechestvenniye Zapitski, November 1877, in Marx and Engels 1975, 
291–94). 
Granted that primitive accumulation is a historical process rather than 
a mythical event, a further question arises: Why does this process, or at 
least most accounts of Marx’s treatment of it, seem to stop so abruptly 
with the establishment of a capitalist society? Marx himself offered few 
examples of primitive accumulation that occurred in the nineteenth cen-tury 
outside of colonial lands. 
In his letter to Otechestvenniye Zapitski, Marx seemed to take an al-most 
Smithian position, diminishing the importance of primitive accu-mulation 
by relegating it to a distant past. Marx even denigrated his chap-ter 
in Capital on primitive accumulation as ‘‘this historical sketch,’’ 
insisting that it ‘‘does not claim to do more than trace the path by which 
in Western Europe, the capitalist economy emerged from the womb of 
the feudal economic system. It therefore describes the historical process 
which by divorcing workers from their means of production converts 
them into wage workers’’ (ibid., 293). We must read this letter in its politi-cal 
context. Marx was upset that Mikhailovsky was attempting to use the 
chapter on primitive accumulation to convey the impression that Russia’s 
future would be mechanically determined by the ‘‘inexorable laws’’ of 
capitalism (ibid.). Marx was certain that, although the nature of capital 
might be unchanged, the specifics of Russian and western European devel-opment 
would be quite different. Consequently, he wanted to point out to 
Mikhailovsky the mistake of thinking that one could mechanically ‘‘pre-dict’’ 
the Russian outcome on the basis of western European experiences. 
At times, Marx did propose a theoretical stance that would seem to 
confine the importance of primitive accumulation to the historical past. 
Lucio Colletti (1979, 130) singles out the following extended passage from 
the Grundrisse: 
The conditions which form its [capital’s] point of departure in pro-duction— 
the condition that the capitalist, in order to posit himself as 
capital, must bring values into circulation which he created with his 
own labour—or by some other means, excepting only already avail-able, 
previous wage labour—belongs among the antediluvian condi-tions 
of capital, belongs to its historic presuppositions, which, pre-
28 
cisely as such historic presuppositions, are past and gone, and hence 
belong to the history of its formation, but in no way to its contempo-rary 
history, i.e., not to the real system of the mode of production 
ruled by it. While e.g., the flight of serfs to the cities is one of the 
historic conditions and presuppositions of urbanism, it is not a condi-tion, 
not a moment of the reality of developed cities but belongs 
rather to their past presuppositions, to the presuppositions of their 
becoming which are suspended in their being. The conditions and 
presuppositions of the becoming, or the arising, of capital presuppose 
precisely that it is not yet in being but merely in becoming; they 
therefore disappear as real capital arises, capital which itself, on the 
basis of its own reality, posits the conditions for its realization. (Marx 
1974, 459–60) 
In Capital, the same idea appears with a similar wording, except for the 
elimination of some of the more baroque Hegelesque terminology (Marx 
1977, 775). Taken very simply, Marx seems to have been suggesting that 
the initial separation of workers from the means of production was a nec-essary 
historical event for the establishment of capitalism. In short, prim-itive 
accumulation was an essential component of what Engels (1894, 
217) called the ‘‘great division of labor between the masses discharging 
simple manual labour and the few privileged persons directing labour,’’ 
but it was irrelevant to the ongoing process of capitalism. In Capital, 
Marx also generally appears to restrict the action of primitive accumula-tion 
to a short period in which traditional economies converted to capital-ism. 
As he wrote in Capital: ‘‘The different moments of primitive ac-cumulation 
can be assigned in particular to Spain, Portugal, Holland, 
France and England, in more or less chronological order. These different 
moments are systematically combined together at the end of the seven-teenth 
century in England’’ (Marx 1977, 915). 
Was Smith then correct after all in relegating primitive accumulation to 
the past—at least in the societies of advanced capitalism? We will see that 
the answer is an emphatic no. 
The Coexistence of Primitive and Capitalist Accumulation 
Despite Marx’s words to the contrary, the overall presentation of the first 
volume of Capital suggests that he rejected Smith’s approach of assigning 
primitive accumulation to a distant past. Indeed, the material in his part 
8, ‘‘The So-Called Primitive Accumulation,’’ does not appear to be quali-
theory of primitive accumulation 29 
tatively different from what is found in the previous chapter, ‘‘The Gen-eral 
Theory of Capitalist Accumulation.’’ 
When Marx’s study of primitive accumulation finally reached the sub-ject 
of Edward Gibbon Wakefield, Marx did not qualify his appreciation of 
the father of modern colonial theory by limiting its relevance to an earlier 
England. Instead, he insisted that Wakefield offered significant insights 
into the England where Marx lived and worked (Marx 1977, 940; see also 
Marx 1853, 498). 
Read in this light, Marx’s letter to Mikhailovsky is also consistent with 
the idea that the importance of primitive accumulation was not what it 
taught about backward societies, but about the most advanced ones. In 
spite of the presumptions of some authors to prove otherwise (see, for 
example, Foster-Carter 1978, esp. 229), Marx (1976, 400n) himself, refer-ring 
to the institutions of Mexico, contended that the ‘‘nature of capital 
remains the same in its developed as in its undeveloped forms.’’ 
Even so, the presentation in Capital still does suggest a temporal cleav-age 
between the initial moment of primitive accumulation, when capital-ists 
accumulated by virtue of direct force, and the era of capitalist ac-cumulation, 
when capitalists accumulated surplus value in the market. 
This dichotomy might appeal to our common sense; still, it is itself rather 
ahistorical. 
In conclusion, at some times, Marx’s analysis of primitive accumula-tion 
sometimes seems to be a process that ceased with the establishment 
of capitalism. At other times, it seems to be more of an ongoing process. 
What then is the source of this confusion? 
The Primacy of Capitalist Accumulation in Capital 
Why was Marx not more explicit about the continuity of primitive ac-cumulation? 
To answer this question, recall the purpose of Marx’s ex-position 
of primitive accumulation. On a theoretical level, Marx was at-tempting 
to debunk Smith’s theology of previous accumulation, which 
suggested that capitalists’ commanding position was due to their past 
savings. 
In the process, he was attempting to lay bare the historical origins of 
market relations. He intended this historical analysis to refute the con-tention 
of classical political economy that markets supposedly work 
fairly because invisible hands somehow intelligently guide the world to-ward 
inevitable prosperity and even a higher level of culture. 
Marx’s depiction of primitive accumulation conveyed an overriding
30 
sense of the unfairness of that altogether brutal experience. Yet, this por-trayal 
stood in contradiction to the main thrust of Capital. After all, 
Marx’s primary message was that the seemingly fair and objective rule of 
capital necessarily leads to exploitation. 
Although Marx accepted that markets were progressive in the long run, 
insofar as they prepared the ground for socialism, he was convinced that 
allegedly impartial market forces produced more cruelty than the crude 
and arbitrary methods of primitive accumulation. To emphasize primi-tive 
accumulation would have undermined Marx’s critique of capitalism. 
Marx would not have wished his readers to believe that measures to 
eliminate ‘‘unjust’’ instances of primitive accumulation might suffice to 
bring about a good society. To have stressed the continuing influence of 
primitive accumulation would have risked throwing readers off track. 
Certainly, Marx did not want his readers to conclude that the ills of so-ciety 
resulted from unjust actions that were unrelated to the essence of a 
market society. 
On the contrary, Marx insisted that the law of supply and demand, not 
primitive accumulation, was responsible for the better part of the horrible 
conditions that the working class experienced. As a result, he subordi-nated 
his insights about primitive accumulation to a more telling critique 
of capitalism; namely, that, once capitalism had taken hold, capitalists 
learned that purely market pressures were more effective in exploiting 
labor than the brutal act of primitive accumulation. In this sense, Marx’s 
relegation of primitive accumulation to the historical past made sense. By 
calling attention to the consequences of the market’s unique logic, he was 
reinforcing his basic contention that piecemeal reforms would be inade-quate. 
In this vein, Marx (1977, 899–900) wrote: 
It is not enough that the conditions of labour are concentrated at one 
pole of society in the shape of capital, while at the other pole are 
grouped masses of men who have nothing to sell but their labour-power. 
Nor is it enough that they are compelled to sell themselves 
voluntarily. The advance of capitalist production develops a working 
class which by education, tradition and habit looks upon the require-ments 
of that mode of production as self-evident natural laws. The 
organization of the capitalist process of production, once it is fully 
developed, breaks down all resistance. The constant generation of a 
relative surplus population keeps the law of the supply and demand of 
labour, and therefore wages, within narrow limits which correspond 
to capital’s valorization requirements. The silent compulsion of eco-nomic 
relations sets the seal on the domination of the capitalist over
theory of primitive accumulation 31 
the worker. Direct extra-economic force is still of course used, but 
only in exceptional cases. In the ordinary run of things, the worker 
can be left to the ‘‘natural laws of production,’’ i.e., it is possible to 
rely on his dependence on capital, which springs from the conditions 
of production themselves, and is guaranteed in perpetuity by them. It 
is otherwise during the historical genesis of capitalist production. 
The rising bourgeoisie needs the power of the state, and uses it to 
‘‘regulate’’ wages, i.e., to force them into the limits suitable to make a 
profit, to lengthen the working day, and to keep the worker himself at 
his normal level of dependence. This is an essential aspect of so-called 
primitive accumulation. (emphasis added) 
The force of the ‘‘silent compulsion’’ is more effective than the crude 
methods of primitive accumulation: 
the pretensions of capital in its embryonic state, in its state of becom-ing, 
when it cannot yet use the sheer force of economic relations to 
secure its right to absorb a sufficient quantity of surplus labour, but 
must be aided by the power of the state. . . . Centuries are required 
before the ‘‘free’’ worker, owing to the greater development of the 
capitalist mode of production, makes a voluntary agreement, i.e. is 
compelled by social conditions to sell the whole of his active life. 
(ibid., 382) 
Again, in describing the centralization of capital, Marx (1981, 3:609) 
noted how effectively market forces had replaced primitive accumula-tion: 
‘‘Profits and losses that result from fluctuations in the price of . . . 
ownership titles, and also their centralization in the hands of railway 
magnates . . . now appears in place of labour as the original source of 
capital ownership, as well as taking the place of brute force.’’ 
Marx (ibid., 354) also made the connection between market forces 
and primitive accumulation when he discussed the tendency of the rate 
of profit to fall: ‘‘This is simply the divorce of the conditions of labour 
from the producers raised to a higher power. . . . It is in fact this divorce 
between the conditions of labour on the one hand and the producers on 
the other that forms the concept of capital, as this arises with primitive 
accumulation.’’ 
Here, Marx (ibid., 348) referred to ‘‘expropriating the final residue of 
direct producers who still have something left to expropriate.’’ This note 
is important because it indicates that Marx realized the ongoing nature of 
primitive accumulation, although as I argue he wanted to suppress its 
importance to highlight the ‘‘silent compulsion’’ of the market.
32 
Judging by his words, Marx was also careful to avoid confusing such 
‘‘financial primitive accumulation’’ with primitive accumulation proper. 
Marx (ibid., 570–71) noted: 
Conceptions that still had a certain meaning at a less developed state of 
capitalist production now become completely meaningless. Success 
and failure lead in both cases to the centralization of capitals and hence 
to expropriation on the most enormous scale. Expropriation now ex-tends 
here from the immediate producers to the small and medium 
capitalists themselves. Expropriation is the starting-point of the capi-talist 
mode of production, whose goal it is to carry it through to com-pletion, 
and even in the last instance to expropriate all individuals. 
No matter what his strategic reasons, Marx seems to have downplayed 
the role of primitive accumulation in order to focus on modern capitalist 
accumulation. Although he succeeded in that respect, this ahistoricity 
obscures our understanding of the early process of capitalist development. 
Specifically, by relegating primitive accumulation to the precapitalistic 
past, we lose sight of the twofold time dimension of primitive accumula-tion. 
First, as we shall emphasize later, the separation of people from their 
traditional means of production occurred over time as capital gradually 
required additional workers to join the labor force. Second, the process of 
primitive accumulation was a matter of degree. All-out primitive accu-mulation 
would not be in the best interests of capital. Instead, capital 
would manipulate the extent to which workers relied on self-provisioning 
in order to maximize its advantage. 
The Theoretical Context of Primitive Accumulation 
Marx’s presentation of primitive accumulation had the unfortunate con-sequence 
of divorcing the process from political economy. Peter Cressey 
and John MacInnes (1980, 18) made a similar point, noting: 
Marx argues that primitive accumulation was a process irreducible to 
the categories of political economy and explicable only in terms of 
struggle and ultimately force. At first sight it appears that historical 
analysis of primitive accumulation explains the initial ‘‘formal’’ sub-ordination 
of labour, in that the workplace capitalist simply appropri-ates 
(formally) a production process bequeathed by pre-capitalist so-ciety. 
[Ultimately, the] . . . concept of the formal subordination of 
labour, like Smith’s concept of previous accumulation, is not derived 
from history but from political economy.
theory of primitive accumulation 33 
Etienne Balibar’s analysis of Marx’s use of the term proletariat rein-forces 
our case for looking at the concept of primitive accumulation more 
closely. Balibar noted that Marx’s Capital rarely mentions the proletariat, 
but generally refers to the working class. In the first edition of the first 
volume, the term only appears in the dedication to Wilhelm Wolff and the 
two final sections on ‘‘The General Law of Capitalist Accumulation,’’ 
which concerned the law of population and the process of primitive ac-cumulation. 
On only one occasion do the proletarian and the capitalist confront each 
other directly in Capital. Balibar (1988, 19–20) concluded, ‘‘These pas-sages 
have in common their insistence upon the insecurity characteristic 
of the proletarian condition.’’ On a more general level, Balibar claimed 
that Marx’s use of the term proletariat seemed to be intended to infer that 
the condition of the working class was unstable, that it perpetuated the 
violence associated with the transition to capitalism, and that the situa-tion 
is historically untenable (ibid.). 
Following Balibar, we might interpret the notion of the proletariat as an 
abstract concept to describe the situation of people displaced from their 
traditional livelihoods by primitive accumulation. The concept of the 
proletariat abstracts from any of the specific conditions that affected these 
people, with the exception of their lack of control over the means of 
production, which sets the stage for the introduction of capitalist forces. 
Both Balibar’s reading of the use of the word proletariat and my own un-derstanding 
of Marx’s treatment of primitive accumulation suggest that 
Marx obscured the phenomena of primitive accumulation in order to fo-cus 
attention on the working of markets. By relegating the relevance of 
primitive accumulation to the historical process of proletarianization, we 
ignore the centrality of the ongoing process of primitive accumulation in 
shaping the conditions of the working class. 
I am convinced that we can benefit from a closer look at primitive 
accumulation, without losing sight of Marx’s invaluable analysis of mar-ket 
forces. In the process of investigating this subject, I will attempt to 
reintegrate primitive accumulation into the structure of political econ-omy, 
especially classical political economy. 
Acknowledging the Scope of Primitive Accumulation 
In reality, primitive accumulation did not suddenly occur just before the 
transition to European capitalism. Nor was it confined to the countryside 
of western Europe. Primitive accumulation may be seen as occurring even 
well before the age of capitalism.
34 
For example, land was already scarce for the majority of people during 
the Middle Ages. According to M. M. Postan (1966, 622–23): 
about one-half of the peasant population had holdings insufficient to 
maintain their families at the bare minimum of subsistence. This 
meant that in order to subsist the average smallholder had to supple-ment 
his income in other ways. . . . [I]ndustrial and trading activities 
might sustain entire villages of smallholders. . . . Most of the oppor-tunities 
for employment must, however, have lain in agriculture. . . . 
[I]n almost all the villages some villagers worked for others. 
Other factors reinforced the pressure of land scarcity. For example, the 
twelfth-century Danes levied tribute from the British. This extortion was 
not primitive accumulation, since it was not intended to coerce workers 
into the labor market and foster market relations. However, it did impel 
Britain to monetize its economy in a way that bore some resemblance 
to primitive accumulation (Sohn-Rethel 1978, 107). Similarly, medieval 
usury, often simply dismissed as a parasitic intrusion into the economy, 
prodded the economy to advance (Marx 1967, 3:596–97). 
The process of primitive accumulation does not merely extend back-ward 
before the epoch of classical political economy. It lasted well into 
more modern times. In England, as well as in the other countries of ad-vanced 
capitalism, the conversion of small-scale farmers into proletarians 
continued throughout the nineteenth century and into the twentieth. 
This transformation involved more than the ‘‘silent compulsion’’ of mar-ket 
forces. In the case of the destruction of small-scale farming in the 
United States, the federal government was central in developing the trans-portation 
and research systems that tipped the balance in favor of large-scale 
agriculture (see Perelman 1977; 1991b). 
The continuity of primitive accumulation stands in stark contrast to its 
usual image as the one-time destruction of the peasant economy, the 
immediate effect of which was to create a society with capitalists on the 
one side and workers on the other. This perception is understandable, but 
misleading. Indeed, on the eve of capitalism, the majority of people were 
peasants or at least had some connection to farming. 
Moreover, primitive accumulation was not limited to agriculture. It 
extended across many, if not all, sectors of the economy (Berg 1986, 70). It 
took place in the city as well as the countryside. After all, urban people 
still provide for themselves directly in a multitude of ways other than the 
growing of food. Depriving people of these means of provision forces a 
greater dependence on the market just as surely as restricting their access 
to the means of food production.
theory of primitive accumulation 35 
Take a relatively modern example. Packing people into crowded urban 
quarters left little space for doing laundry. As a result, people become de-pendent 
on commercial laundries. After World War II, the ability of the 
typical U.S. family to produce for its own needs continued to diminish, 
despite the widespread availability of household appliances, such as wash-ing 
machines, that should have made many types of self-provisioning 
easier. Likewise, Paul Sweezy (1980, 13) interprets Japan’s huge enter-tainment 
sector as a partial result of people being forced to live in such 
cramped quarters that they are unable to socialize in their homes. 
The need to purchase such services compels people to sell more labor. 
We see the impact of this pressure reflected in the recent increase in the 
number of women in the labor force. Gabriel Kolko (1978, 267) calculates 
that the share of life years available for wage labor for the average adult 
has expanded from 39 percent in 1900 to 44.4 percent in 1970, despite 
rising education levels, better child labor laws, and a shorter workweek. 
Since that time, work has demanded a rapidly escalating share of the 
typical family’s time. Juliet Schor (1991, 29) estimates that the average 
person worked 163 more hours in 1987 than in 1969. 
This process can feed on itself. Because people have to earn more wages 
to compensate for the increased difficulty of providing for certain of their 
own needs, they have less time to do other sorts of work on their own, 
inducing families to transfer still more labor from the household to the 
commercial sector. Child care centers are an obvious outcome of this 
process. In addition, the fast-food industry is predicated on the difficulty 
of working a job and performing a multitude of other household chores in 
the same day. 
The foregoing discussion suggests that wage labor and nonwage labor 
are, indeed, inextricably linked. The analysis of one category necessitates 
consideration of the other. As we shall see later, the concept of the social 
division of labor enhances our understanding of this mutual interplay 
of wage and nonwage labor. For now, we need only keep in mind our 
modern-day examples of goods and services that were once produced 
within the household, which became commodities sold by commercial 
firms. 
This new arrangement is related, at least in part, to the pattern of own-ership 
of the means of creating these goods and services in the household. 
Formally, the lack of ownership of a workspace for doing laundry is no 
different from the lack of ownership of the parcel of land on which a 
household once grew its own food. In either case, the denial of ownership 
to a particular means of production creates a change in the mix of wage 
and nonwage labor.
36 
Ignoring Balibar’s warning about the careless use of the word prole-tariat, 
we could interpret this restructuring of the life of a modern house-hold 
as a contemporary variant of the process of primitive accumula-tion, 
whereby the mass of people working for wages has increased. In this 
sense, the concept of primitive accumulation is closely bound up with 
that of the social division of labor. 
Classical Political Economy and Primitive Accumulation 
Even though Marx muted his analysis of the continuing nature of primi-tive 
accumulation, he was abundantly clear that primitive accumulation 
resulted in momentous changes in social relations that were central to 
creation of the capitalist system (see Dobb 1963, 267). Marx’s lesson was 
lost on most later economists. They were content to treat the Industrial 
Revolution as if it were merely the introduction of superior methods of 
production. In contrast, the classical political economists saw primitive 
accumulation as a means of radically reordering the social division of 
labor, which they recognized as a precondition of the creation of a pro-letariat. 
Along this line, Marx (1977, 764), in writing about primitive 
accumulation, proposed the formula: ‘‘Accumulation of capital is . . . 
multiplication of the proletariat.’’ 
We shall see that we can express the classical theory of primitive accu-mulation 
as a model that resembles a crude proto-Marxian model stripped 
of the dialectic. In analyzing this model, keep in mind that Marx began by 
taking the categories of classical political economy as he found them (see 
Perelman 1987, chap. 4). By investigating them more fully, he was able to 
invest the typically static, undialectical categories of classical political 
economy with a dynamic, dialectical quality. 
We will try to follow the same tradition in our study of the classical the-ory 
of primitive accumulation. The classical political economists make 
this task considerably easier. Compared to their analysis of the categories 
of profits or wages, they adopted a far more dynamic, almost dialectical 
approach to their analysis of primitive accumulation. Carrying out such 
an analysis of the classical theory of primitive accumulation has a twofold 
importance: it reveals a side of classical political economy that previously 
has gone unnoticed; and it reminds us that primitive accumulation is an 
ongoing process. 
Even modern commentaries on primitive accumulation do not do the 
topic full justice. Like Marx, most contemporary references relegate the 
concept to a distant past, except perhaps in the case of the proletarianiza-tion 
that the less-developed countries of Africa, Asia, and Latin America
theory of primitive accumulation 37 
are experiencing. Consequently, the separation of workers from their 
means of production is implicitly assumed to be a static, once-and-for-all 
event. 
Since the classical political economists grounded their discussions of 
primitive accumulation in a dynamic framework, scrutiny of the classics 
has more to offer than more modern commentaries on the subject of 
primitive accumulation. To some extent, the deficiencies of these com-mentaries 
may be understandable. Marx himself often wrote about primi-tive 
accumulation with an air of finality and possibly even with a touch of 
Smithian mythology. For example, the first mention of the concept of 
primitive accumulation in Capital appears in chapter 23, ‘‘Simple Repro-duction’’ 
(Marx 1977, 714). At this point, Marx had to address the ques-tion: 
How does the system come to be structured into capital and labor? 
He responded: ‘‘From our present standpoint it therefore seems likely that 
the capitalist, once upon a time, became possessed of money by some 
form of primitive accumulation’’ (Marx 1977, 714). 
Marx’s uncharacteristic ‘‘once upon a time,’’ which sounded as unreal 
as Smith’s mythical history, was obviously provisional. The words ‘‘from 
our present viewpoint’’ also suggest that a more thorough analysis would 
be forthcoming. For reasons already discussed, Marx never provided that 
thoroughgoing critique. Instead, we find only history. 
Yet primitive accumulation remains a key concept for understanding 
capitalism—and not just the particular phase of capitalism associated 
with the transition from feudalism, but capitalism proper. Primitive ac-cumulation 
is a process that continues to this day. Thus, we must carry 
the history of primitive accumulation through the epoch of classical po-litical 
economy by connecting this concept with Marx’s notion of the 
social division of labor.
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman
The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman

Weitere ähnliche Inhalte

Was ist angesagt?

Science and advances of the knowledge in economics
Science and advances of the knowledge in economicsScience and advances of the knowledge in economics
Science and advances of the knowledge in economicsFernando Alcoforado
 
karl marx historial materialism, alienation, mode of production, class struggles
karl marx historial materialism, alienation, mode of production, class struggleskarl marx historial materialism, alienation, mode of production, class struggles
karl marx historial materialism, alienation, mode of production, class struggleskingsly sam zebulun
 
Lecture 4 Evolution of Global Economies Capitalism, Adam Smith & Marxism
Lecture 4 Evolution of Global Economies Capitalism, Adam Smith & MarxismLecture 4 Evolution of Global Economies Capitalism, Adam Smith & Marxism
Lecture 4 Evolution of Global Economies Capitalism, Adam Smith & MarxismPearson College London
 
Karl Marx and theory
Karl Marx and theoryKarl Marx and theory
Karl Marx and theorykuldeep Deep
 
Classical and Neo Classical Economics
Classical and Neo Classical EconomicsClassical and Neo Classical Economics
Classical and Neo Classical EconomicsAbir Shopnobaj
 
Combating the social inequalities in capitalism according to marx and piketty...
Combating the social inequalities in capitalism according to marx and piketty...Combating the social inequalities in capitalism according to marx and piketty...
Combating the social inequalities in capitalism according to marx and piketty...Fernando Alcoforado
 
11.[1 6]an analysis of karl marx’s theory of value on the contemporary capita...
11.[1 6]an analysis of karl marx’s theory of value on the contemporary capita...11.[1 6]an analysis of karl marx’s theory of value on the contemporary capita...
11.[1 6]an analysis of karl marx’s theory of value on the contemporary capita...Alexander Decker
 
Feminist Economics, Finance, and the Commons
Feminist Economics, Finance, and the CommonsFeminist Economics, Finance, and the Commons
Feminist Economics, Finance, and the CommonsConor McCabe
 
Feminist Economics - Cuts are a Feminist Issue
Feminist Economics - Cuts are a Feminist IssueFeminist Economics - Cuts are a Feminist Issue
Feminist Economics - Cuts are a Feminist IssueConor McCabe
 
Feminist Economics - Social Reproduction
Feminist Economics - Social ReproductionFeminist Economics - Social Reproduction
Feminist Economics - Social ReproductionConor McCabe
 
Capital in the Twenty-First Century — Thomas Piketty
Capital in the Twenty-First Century — Thomas PikettyCapital in the Twenty-First Century — Thomas Piketty
Capital in the Twenty-First Century — Thomas Pikettyitchyinsomnia1512
 
Karl Marx- Labor theory of value
Karl Marx- Labor theory of valueKarl Marx- Labor theory of value
Karl Marx- Labor theory of valueArif Rahman
 
The Crisis of Hyper-Consumerism
The Crisis of Hyper-ConsumerismThe Crisis of Hyper-Consumerism
The Crisis of Hyper-ConsumerismDreaCofield
 
Marxism & capitalism
Marxism & capitalismMarxism & capitalism
Marxism & capitalismemclem
 
Karl Marx vs. Adam Smith - Consumption
Karl Marx vs. Adam Smith - ConsumptionKarl Marx vs. Adam Smith - Consumption
Karl Marx vs. Adam Smith - ConsumptionAshwin Raman
 
Karl Marx: Alienated Labor and Communism
Karl Marx: Alienated Labor and CommunismKarl Marx: Alienated Labor and Communism
Karl Marx: Alienated Labor and CommunismRichard Lopez
 
Indian and western sociologists
Indian and western sociologistsIndian and western sociologists
Indian and western sociologistsTheerthaA1
 
Alienation of labor by karl marx review and critique
Alienation of labor by karl marx review and critiqueAlienation of labor by karl marx review and critique
Alienation of labor by karl marx review and critiqueCustom Essaywriters
 

Was ist angesagt? (20)

Science and advances of the knowledge in economics
Science and advances of the knowledge in economicsScience and advances of the knowledge in economics
Science and advances of the knowledge in economics
 
karl marx historial materialism, alienation, mode of production, class struggles
karl marx historial materialism, alienation, mode of production, class struggleskarl marx historial materialism, alienation, mode of production, class struggles
karl marx historial materialism, alienation, mode of production, class struggles
 
Lecture 4 Evolution of Global Economies Capitalism, Adam Smith & Marxism
Lecture 4 Evolution of Global Economies Capitalism, Adam Smith & MarxismLecture 4 Evolution of Global Economies Capitalism, Adam Smith & Marxism
Lecture 4 Evolution of Global Economies Capitalism, Adam Smith & Marxism
 
Karl Marx and theory
Karl Marx and theoryKarl Marx and theory
Karl Marx and theory
 
Classical and Neo Classical Economics
Classical and Neo Classical EconomicsClassical and Neo Classical Economics
Classical and Neo Classical Economics
 
Combating the social inequalities in capitalism according to marx and piketty...
Combating the social inequalities in capitalism according to marx and piketty...Combating the social inequalities in capitalism according to marx and piketty...
Combating the social inequalities in capitalism according to marx and piketty...
 
11.[1 6]an analysis of karl marx’s theory of value on the contemporary capita...
11.[1 6]an analysis of karl marx’s theory of value on the contemporary capita...11.[1 6]an analysis of karl marx’s theory of value on the contemporary capita...
11.[1 6]an analysis of karl marx’s theory of value on the contemporary capita...
 
Feminist Economics, Finance, and the Commons
Feminist Economics, Finance, and the CommonsFeminist Economics, Finance, and the Commons
Feminist Economics, Finance, and the Commons
 
Feminist Economics - Cuts are a Feminist Issue
Feminist Economics - Cuts are a Feminist IssueFeminist Economics - Cuts are a Feminist Issue
Feminist Economics - Cuts are a Feminist Issue
 
Feminist Economics - Social Reproduction
Feminist Economics - Social ReproductionFeminist Economics - Social Reproduction
Feminist Economics - Social Reproduction
 
Capital in the Twenty-First Century — Thomas Piketty
Capital in the Twenty-First Century — Thomas PikettyCapital in the Twenty-First Century — Thomas Piketty
Capital in the Twenty-First Century — Thomas Piketty
 
Karl Marx- Labor theory of value
Karl Marx- Labor theory of valueKarl Marx- Labor theory of value
Karl Marx- Labor theory of value
 
Why ae
Why aeWhy ae
Why ae
 
The Crisis of Hyper-Consumerism
The Crisis of Hyper-ConsumerismThe Crisis of Hyper-Consumerism
The Crisis of Hyper-Consumerism
 
Dependency Theory
Dependency TheoryDependency Theory
Dependency Theory
 
Marxism & capitalism
Marxism & capitalismMarxism & capitalism
Marxism & capitalism
 
Karl Marx vs. Adam Smith - Consumption
Karl Marx vs. Adam Smith - ConsumptionKarl Marx vs. Adam Smith - Consumption
Karl Marx vs. Adam Smith - Consumption
 
Karl Marx: Alienated Labor and Communism
Karl Marx: Alienated Labor and CommunismKarl Marx: Alienated Labor and Communism
Karl Marx: Alienated Labor and Communism
 
Indian and western sociologists
Indian and western sociologistsIndian and western sociologists
Indian and western sociologists
 
Alienation of labor by karl marx review and critique
Alienation of labor by karl marx review and critiqueAlienation of labor by karl marx review and critique
Alienation of labor by karl marx review and critique
 

Andere mochten auch

Show me your hands
Show me your handsShow me your hands
Show me your handsTerry Penney
 
Monomictic lakes francisco muñoz maestre
Monomictic lakes francisco muñoz maestreMonomictic lakes francisco muñoz maestre
Monomictic lakes francisco muñoz maestreFrancisco Maestre
 
Andersen a rozprávka sjl v-2
Andersen a rozprávka sjl   v-2Andersen a rozprávka sjl   v-2
Andersen a rozprávka sjl v-2Skola lamac
 
Chongqing municipal people's government work report
Chongqing municipal people's government work reportChongqing municipal people's government work report
Chongqing municipal people's government work reporttianjin19881
 
Project 2016 progress template 25% completed
Project 2016 progress template  25% completedProject 2016 progress template  25% completed
Project 2016 progress template 25% completedThomas Wheeler
 
Email & Social Media Training
Email & Social Media TrainingEmail & Social Media Training
Email & Social Media TrainingWilliam Mann
 
MCDV Briefing - December 2014
MCDV Briefing - December 2014MCDV Briefing - December 2014
MCDV Briefing - December 2014Esquimalt MFRC
 
Nevi cpd missie visie en strategie v1.0
Nevi cpd missie visie en strategie v1.0Nevi cpd missie visie en strategie v1.0
Nevi cpd missie visie en strategie v1.0John van Veen
 
PLAZA 3.0 - an access point for plant comparative genomics
PLAZA 3.0 - an access point for plant comparative genomicsPLAZA 3.0 - an access point for plant comparative genomics
PLAZA 3.0 - an access point for plant comparative genomicsKlaas Vandepoele
 
Aula 1 a obra de kant como síntese do nascente pensamento burguês
Aula 1   a obra de kant como síntese do nascente pensamento burguêsAula 1   a obra de kant como síntese do nascente pensamento burguês
Aula 1 a obra de kant como síntese do nascente pensamento burguêsLeandro Alano
 
مفهوم الضرر بين الشرع والطب
مفهوم الضرر بين الشرع والطبمفهوم الضرر بين الشرع والطب
مفهوم الضرر بين الشرع والطبDr Ghaiath Hussein
 
Paul Biya - Cameroun - Décret N° 2016355 du 28 juillet 2016 portant inscripti...
Paul Biya - Cameroun - Décret N° 2016355 du 28 juillet 2016 portant inscripti...Paul Biya - Cameroun - Décret N° 2016355 du 28 juillet 2016 portant inscripti...
Paul Biya - Cameroun - Décret N° 2016355 du 28 juillet 2016 portant inscripti...Paul Biya
 
Samen Sterker - Interactie Team door Steven Goetstouwers, CEO Admesy
Samen Sterker - Interactie Team door Steven Goetstouwers, CEO Admesy Samen Sterker - Interactie Team door Steven Goetstouwers, CEO Admesy
Samen Sterker - Interactie Team door Steven Goetstouwers, CEO Admesy TeamVenture
 

Andere mochten auch (20)

Show me your hands
Show me your handsShow me your hands
Show me your hands
 
TJOLI
TJOLITJOLI
TJOLI
 
Monomictic lakes francisco muñoz maestre
Monomictic lakes francisco muñoz maestreMonomictic lakes francisco muñoz maestre
Monomictic lakes francisco muñoz maestre
 
Andersen a rozprávka sjl v-2
Andersen a rozprávka sjl   v-2Andersen a rozprávka sjl   v-2
Andersen a rozprávka sjl v-2
 
lwen
lwenlwen
lwen
 
Chongqing municipal people's government work report
Chongqing municipal people's government work reportChongqing municipal people's government work report
Chongqing municipal people's government work report
 
Project 2016 progress template 25% completed
Project 2016 progress template  25% completedProject 2016 progress template  25% completed
Project 2016 progress template 25% completed
 
Email & Social Media Training
Email & Social Media TrainingEmail & Social Media Training
Email & Social Media Training
 
MCDV Briefing - December 2014
MCDV Briefing - December 2014MCDV Briefing - December 2014
MCDV Briefing - December 2014
 
Nevi cpd missie visie en strategie v1.0
Nevi cpd missie visie en strategie v1.0Nevi cpd missie visie en strategie v1.0
Nevi cpd missie visie en strategie v1.0
 
PLAZA 3.0 - an access point for plant comparative genomics
PLAZA 3.0 - an access point for plant comparative genomicsPLAZA 3.0 - an access point for plant comparative genomics
PLAZA 3.0 - an access point for plant comparative genomics
 
Img056
Img056Img056
Img056
 
Aula 1 a obra de kant como síntese do nascente pensamento burguês
Aula 1   a obra de kant como síntese do nascente pensamento burguêsAula 1   a obra de kant como síntese do nascente pensamento burguês
Aula 1 a obra de kant como síntese do nascente pensamento burguês
 
مفهوم الضرر بين الشرع والطب
مفهوم الضرر بين الشرع والطبمفهوم الضرر بين الشرع والطب
مفهوم الضرر بين الشرع والطب
 
Didactalia
DidactaliaDidactalia
Didactalia
 
Standards of perfect human nature
Standards of perfect human natureStandards of perfect human nature
Standards of perfect human nature
 
Chapter 7
Chapter 7Chapter 7
Chapter 7
 
Paul Biya - Cameroun - Décret N° 2016355 du 28 juillet 2016 portant inscripti...
Paul Biya - Cameroun - Décret N° 2016355 du 28 juillet 2016 portant inscripti...Paul Biya - Cameroun - Décret N° 2016355 du 28 juillet 2016 portant inscripti...
Paul Biya - Cameroun - Décret N° 2016355 du 28 juillet 2016 portant inscripti...
 
Seven indicators of business failure
Seven indicators of business failureSeven indicators of business failure
Seven indicators of business failure
 
Samen Sterker - Interactie Team door Steven Goetstouwers, CEO Admesy
Samen Sterker - Interactie Team door Steven Goetstouwers, CEO Admesy Samen Sterker - Interactie Team door Steven Goetstouwers, CEO Admesy
Samen Sterker - Interactie Team door Steven Goetstouwers, CEO Admesy
 

Ähnlich wie The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman

Capitalism and SocialismWeek-14Socialist alternatives to cap
Capitalism and SocialismWeek-14Socialist alternatives to capCapitalism and SocialismWeek-14Socialist alternatives to cap
Capitalism and SocialismWeek-14Socialist alternatives to capTawnaDelatorrejs
 
Famous Economic thinkers
Famous Economic thinkersFamous Economic thinkers
Famous Economic thinkersmattbentley34
 
Transition in post colonial state.zaid
Transition in post colonial state.zaidTransition in post colonial state.zaid
Transition in post colonial state.zaidZaid Uddin
 
Group presentation on The Wealth of Nations by Adam Smith.pptx
Group presentation on The Wealth of Nations by Adam Smith.pptxGroup presentation on The Wealth of Nations by Adam Smith.pptx
Group presentation on The Wealth of Nations by Adam Smith.pptxSumaiaRuhane
 
Froyen_10th Editionn.pdf
Froyen_10th Editionn.pdfFroyen_10th Editionn.pdf
Froyen_10th Editionn.pdfanjalimittal47
 
Economics And The Complexity
Economics And The ComplexityEconomics And The Complexity
Economics And The ComplexityGreg Pratt
 

Ähnlich wie The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman (10)

Capitalism and SocialismWeek-14Socialist alternatives to cap
Capitalism and SocialismWeek-14Socialist alternatives to capCapitalism and SocialismWeek-14Socialist alternatives to cap
Capitalism and SocialismWeek-14Socialist alternatives to cap
 
Famous Economic thinkers
Famous Economic thinkersFamous Economic thinkers
Famous Economic thinkers
 
Transition in post colonial state.zaid
Transition in post colonial state.zaidTransition in post colonial state.zaid
Transition in post colonial state.zaid
 
Group presentation on The Wealth of Nations by Adam Smith.pptx
Group presentation on The Wealth of Nations by Adam Smith.pptxGroup presentation on The Wealth of Nations by Adam Smith.pptx
Group presentation on The Wealth of Nations by Adam Smith.pptx
 
Lecture 2 eco
Lecture 2 ecoLecture 2 eco
Lecture 2 eco
 
Froyen_10th Editionn.pdf
Froyen_10th Editionn.pdfFroyen_10th Editionn.pdf
Froyen_10th Editionn.pdf
 
Capitalism And Capitalism
Capitalism And CapitalismCapitalism And Capitalism
Capitalism And Capitalism
 
M xs
M xsM xs
M xs
 
Economics And The Complexity
Economics And The ComplexityEconomics And The Complexity
Economics And The Complexity
 
Paper meacci
Paper meacciPaper meacci
Paper meacci
 

Mehr von berat celik

How the Culture of Economics Stops Economists from Studying Group Behavior an...
How the Culture of Economics Stops Economists from Studying Group Behavior an...How the Culture of Economics Stops Economists from Studying Group Behavior an...
How the Culture of Economics Stops Economists from Studying Group Behavior an...berat celik
 
A2 k in the age of intellectual property
A2 k in the age of intellectual propertyA2 k in the age of intellectual property
A2 k in the age of intellectual propertyberat celik
 
Sand, rarer than one thinks
Sand, rarer than one thinksSand, rarer than one thinks
Sand, rarer than one thinksberat celik
 
The Theory Of The Leisure Class - Thorstein Veblen
The Theory Of The Leisure Class - Thorstein VeblenThe Theory Of The Leisure Class - Thorstein Veblen
The Theory Of The Leisure Class - Thorstein Veblenberat celik
 
Harvesting Justice - Transforming Food, Land, and Agricultural Systems in the...
Harvesting Justice - Transforming Food, Land, and Agricultural Systems in the...Harvesting Justice - Transforming Food, Land, and Agricultural Systems in the...
Harvesting Justice - Transforming Food, Land, and Agricultural Systems in the...berat celik
 
Rape as torture in the DRC: Sexual violence beyond the conflict zone
Rape as torture in the DRC: Sexual violence beyond the conflict zoneRape as torture in the DRC: Sexual violence beyond the conflict zone
Rape as torture in the DRC: Sexual violence beyond the conflict zoneberat celik
 
Sharpeville- Nach 50 Jahren. Geschichten vom Überleben in Südafrika
Sharpeville- Nach 50 Jahren. Geschichten vom Überleben in SüdafrikaSharpeville- Nach 50 Jahren. Geschichten vom Überleben in Südafrika
Sharpeville- Nach 50 Jahren. Geschichten vom Überleben in Südafrikaberat celik
 
Breaking the silence: The hidden injuries of neo-liberal academia
Breaking the silence: The hidden injuries of neo-liberal academiaBreaking the silence: The hidden injuries of neo-liberal academia
Breaking the silence: The hidden injuries of neo-liberal academiaberat celik
 
Land Grabbing - A Mexican Presidium Under Threat
Land Grabbing - A Mexican Presidium Under ThreatLand Grabbing - A Mexican Presidium Under Threat
Land Grabbing - A Mexican Presidium Under Threatberat celik
 

Mehr von berat celik (9)

How the Culture of Economics Stops Economists from Studying Group Behavior an...
How the Culture of Economics Stops Economists from Studying Group Behavior an...How the Culture of Economics Stops Economists from Studying Group Behavior an...
How the Culture of Economics Stops Economists from Studying Group Behavior an...
 
A2 k in the age of intellectual property
A2 k in the age of intellectual propertyA2 k in the age of intellectual property
A2 k in the age of intellectual property
 
Sand, rarer than one thinks
Sand, rarer than one thinksSand, rarer than one thinks
Sand, rarer than one thinks
 
The Theory Of The Leisure Class - Thorstein Veblen
The Theory Of The Leisure Class - Thorstein VeblenThe Theory Of The Leisure Class - Thorstein Veblen
The Theory Of The Leisure Class - Thorstein Veblen
 
Harvesting Justice - Transforming Food, Land, and Agricultural Systems in the...
Harvesting Justice - Transforming Food, Land, and Agricultural Systems in the...Harvesting Justice - Transforming Food, Land, and Agricultural Systems in the...
Harvesting Justice - Transforming Food, Land, and Agricultural Systems in the...
 
Rape as torture in the DRC: Sexual violence beyond the conflict zone
Rape as torture in the DRC: Sexual violence beyond the conflict zoneRape as torture in the DRC: Sexual violence beyond the conflict zone
Rape as torture in the DRC: Sexual violence beyond the conflict zone
 
Sharpeville- Nach 50 Jahren. Geschichten vom Überleben in Südafrika
Sharpeville- Nach 50 Jahren. Geschichten vom Überleben in SüdafrikaSharpeville- Nach 50 Jahren. Geschichten vom Überleben in Südafrika
Sharpeville- Nach 50 Jahren. Geschichten vom Überleben in Südafrika
 
Breaking the silence: The hidden injuries of neo-liberal academia
Breaking the silence: The hidden injuries of neo-liberal academiaBreaking the silence: The hidden injuries of neo-liberal academia
Breaking the silence: The hidden injuries of neo-liberal academia
 
Land Grabbing - A Mexican Presidium Under Threat
Land Grabbing - A Mexican Presidium Under ThreatLand Grabbing - A Mexican Presidium Under Threat
Land Grabbing - A Mexican Presidium Under Threat
 

Kürzlich hochgeladen

Managing Finances in a Small Business (yes).pdf
Managing Finances  in a Small Business (yes).pdfManaging Finances  in a Small Business (yes).pdf
Managing Finances in a Small Business (yes).pdfmar yame
 
project management information system lecture notes
project management information system lecture notesproject management information system lecture notes
project management information system lecture notesongomchris
 
Economic Risk Factor Update: April 2024 [SlideShare]
Economic Risk Factor Update: April 2024 [SlideShare]Economic Risk Factor Update: April 2024 [SlideShare]
Economic Risk Factor Update: April 2024 [SlideShare]Commonwealth
 
Call Girls Near Me WhatsApp:+91-9833363713
Call Girls Near Me WhatsApp:+91-9833363713Call Girls Near Me WhatsApp:+91-9833363713
Call Girls Near Me WhatsApp:+91-9833363713Sonam Pathan
 
Unveiling Business Expansion Trends in 2024
Unveiling Business Expansion Trends in 2024Unveiling Business Expansion Trends in 2024
Unveiling Business Expansion Trends in 2024Champak Jhagmag
 
Governor Olli Rehn: Dialling back monetary restraint
Governor Olli Rehn: Dialling back monetary restraintGovernor Olli Rehn: Dialling back monetary restraint
Governor Olli Rehn: Dialling back monetary restraintSuomen Pankki
 
(办理原版一样)QUT毕业证昆士兰科技大学毕业证学位证留信学历认证成绩单补办
(办理原版一样)QUT毕业证昆士兰科技大学毕业证学位证留信学历认证成绩单补办(办理原版一样)QUT毕业证昆士兰科技大学毕业证学位证留信学历认证成绩单补办
(办理原版一样)QUT毕业证昆士兰科技大学毕业证学位证留信学历认证成绩单补办fqiuho152
 
Tenets of Physiocracy History of Economic
Tenets of Physiocracy History of EconomicTenets of Physiocracy History of Economic
Tenets of Physiocracy History of Economiccinemoviesu
 
The Inspirational Story of Julio Herrera Velutini - Global Finance Leader
The Inspirational Story of Julio Herrera Velutini - Global Finance LeaderThe Inspirational Story of Julio Herrera Velutini - Global Finance Leader
The Inspirational Story of Julio Herrera Velutini - Global Finance LeaderArianna Varetto
 
212MTAMount Durham University Bachelor's Diploma in Technology
212MTAMount Durham University Bachelor's Diploma in Technology212MTAMount Durham University Bachelor's Diploma in Technology
212MTAMount Durham University Bachelor's Diploma in Technologyz xss
 
Overview of Inkel Unlisted Shares Price.
Overview of Inkel Unlisted Shares Price.Overview of Inkel Unlisted Shares Price.
Overview of Inkel Unlisted Shares Price.Precize Formely Leadoff
 
The Triple Threat | Article on Global Resession | Harsh Kumar
The Triple Threat | Article on Global Resession | Harsh KumarThe Triple Threat | Article on Global Resession | Harsh Kumar
The Triple Threat | Article on Global Resession | Harsh KumarHarsh Kumar
 
原版1:1复刻温哥华岛大学毕业证Vancouver毕业证留信学历认证
原版1:1复刻温哥华岛大学毕业证Vancouver毕业证留信学历认证原版1:1复刻温哥华岛大学毕业证Vancouver毕业证留信学历认证
原版1:1复刻温哥华岛大学毕业证Vancouver毕业证留信学历认证rjrjkk
 
NO1 WorldWide Love marriage specialist baba ji Amil Baba Kala ilam powerful v...
NO1 WorldWide Love marriage specialist baba ji Amil Baba Kala ilam powerful v...NO1 WorldWide Love marriage specialist baba ji Amil Baba Kala ilam powerful v...
NO1 WorldWide Love marriage specialist baba ji Amil Baba Kala ilam powerful v...Amil baba
 
Amil Baba In Pakistan amil baba in Lahore amil baba in Islamabad amil baba in...
Amil Baba In Pakistan amil baba in Lahore amil baba in Islamabad amil baba in...Amil Baba In Pakistan amil baba in Lahore amil baba in Islamabad amil baba in...
Amil Baba In Pakistan amil baba in Lahore amil baba in Islamabad amil baba in...amilabibi1
 
PMFBY , Pradhan Mantri Fasal bima yojna
PMFBY , Pradhan Mantri  Fasal bima yojnaPMFBY , Pradhan Mantri  Fasal bima yojna
PMFBY , Pradhan Mantri Fasal bima yojnaDharmendra Kumar
 
Role of Information and technology in banking and finance .pptx
Role of Information and technology in banking and finance .pptxRole of Information and technology in banking and finance .pptx
Role of Information and technology in banking and finance .pptxNarayaniTripathi2
 
letter-from-the-chair-to-the-fca-relating-to-british-steel-pensions-scheme-15...
letter-from-the-chair-to-the-fca-relating-to-british-steel-pensions-scheme-15...letter-from-the-chair-to-the-fca-relating-to-british-steel-pensions-scheme-15...
letter-from-the-chair-to-the-fca-relating-to-british-steel-pensions-scheme-15...Henry Tapper
 

Kürzlich hochgeladen (20)

Managing Finances in a Small Business (yes).pdf
Managing Finances  in a Small Business (yes).pdfManaging Finances  in a Small Business (yes).pdf
Managing Finances in a Small Business (yes).pdf
 
Q1 2024 Newsletter | Financial Synergies Wealth Advisors
Q1 2024 Newsletter | Financial Synergies Wealth AdvisorsQ1 2024 Newsletter | Financial Synergies Wealth Advisors
Q1 2024 Newsletter | Financial Synergies Wealth Advisors
 
project management information system lecture notes
project management information system lecture notesproject management information system lecture notes
project management information system lecture notes
 
Economic Risk Factor Update: April 2024 [SlideShare]
Economic Risk Factor Update: April 2024 [SlideShare]Economic Risk Factor Update: April 2024 [SlideShare]
Economic Risk Factor Update: April 2024 [SlideShare]
 
Call Girls Near Me WhatsApp:+91-9833363713
Call Girls Near Me WhatsApp:+91-9833363713Call Girls Near Me WhatsApp:+91-9833363713
Call Girls Near Me WhatsApp:+91-9833363713
 
Unveiling Business Expansion Trends in 2024
Unveiling Business Expansion Trends in 2024Unveiling Business Expansion Trends in 2024
Unveiling Business Expansion Trends in 2024
 
Governor Olli Rehn: Dialling back monetary restraint
Governor Olli Rehn: Dialling back monetary restraintGovernor Olli Rehn: Dialling back monetary restraint
Governor Olli Rehn: Dialling back monetary restraint
 
(办理原版一样)QUT毕业证昆士兰科技大学毕业证学位证留信学历认证成绩单补办
(办理原版一样)QUT毕业证昆士兰科技大学毕业证学位证留信学历认证成绩单补办(办理原版一样)QUT毕业证昆士兰科技大学毕业证学位证留信学历认证成绩单补办
(办理原版一样)QUT毕业证昆士兰科技大学毕业证学位证留信学历认证成绩单补办
 
Tenets of Physiocracy History of Economic
Tenets of Physiocracy History of EconomicTenets of Physiocracy History of Economic
Tenets of Physiocracy History of Economic
 
The Inspirational Story of Julio Herrera Velutini - Global Finance Leader
The Inspirational Story of Julio Herrera Velutini - Global Finance LeaderThe Inspirational Story of Julio Herrera Velutini - Global Finance Leader
The Inspirational Story of Julio Herrera Velutini - Global Finance Leader
 
212MTAMount Durham University Bachelor's Diploma in Technology
212MTAMount Durham University Bachelor's Diploma in Technology212MTAMount Durham University Bachelor's Diploma in Technology
212MTAMount Durham University Bachelor's Diploma in Technology
 
🔝+919953056974 🔝young Delhi Escort service Pusa Road
🔝+919953056974 🔝young Delhi Escort service Pusa Road🔝+919953056974 🔝young Delhi Escort service Pusa Road
🔝+919953056974 🔝young Delhi Escort service Pusa Road
 
Overview of Inkel Unlisted Shares Price.
Overview of Inkel Unlisted Shares Price.Overview of Inkel Unlisted Shares Price.
Overview of Inkel Unlisted Shares Price.
 
The Triple Threat | Article on Global Resession | Harsh Kumar
The Triple Threat | Article on Global Resession | Harsh KumarThe Triple Threat | Article on Global Resession | Harsh Kumar
The Triple Threat | Article on Global Resession | Harsh Kumar
 
原版1:1复刻温哥华岛大学毕业证Vancouver毕业证留信学历认证
原版1:1复刻温哥华岛大学毕业证Vancouver毕业证留信学历认证原版1:1复刻温哥华岛大学毕业证Vancouver毕业证留信学历认证
原版1:1复刻温哥华岛大学毕业证Vancouver毕业证留信学历认证
 
NO1 WorldWide Love marriage specialist baba ji Amil Baba Kala ilam powerful v...
NO1 WorldWide Love marriage specialist baba ji Amil Baba Kala ilam powerful v...NO1 WorldWide Love marriage specialist baba ji Amil Baba Kala ilam powerful v...
NO1 WorldWide Love marriage specialist baba ji Amil Baba Kala ilam powerful v...
 
Amil Baba In Pakistan amil baba in Lahore amil baba in Islamabad amil baba in...
Amil Baba In Pakistan amil baba in Lahore amil baba in Islamabad amil baba in...Amil Baba In Pakistan amil baba in Lahore amil baba in Islamabad amil baba in...
Amil Baba In Pakistan amil baba in Lahore amil baba in Islamabad amil baba in...
 
PMFBY , Pradhan Mantri Fasal bima yojna
PMFBY , Pradhan Mantri  Fasal bima yojnaPMFBY , Pradhan Mantri  Fasal bima yojna
PMFBY , Pradhan Mantri Fasal bima yojna
 
Role of Information and technology in banking and finance .pptx
Role of Information and technology in banking and finance .pptxRole of Information and technology in banking and finance .pptx
Role of Information and technology in banking and finance .pptx
 
letter-from-the-chair-to-the-fca-relating-to-british-steel-pensions-scheme-15...
letter-from-the-chair-to-the-fca-relating-to-british-steel-pensions-scheme-15...letter-from-the-chair-to-the-fca-relating-to-british-steel-pensions-scheme-15...
letter-from-the-chair-to-the-fca-relating-to-british-steel-pensions-scheme-15...
 

The Invention of Capitalism - Michael Perelman

  • 1. the invention of capitalism Michael Perelman
  • 2. the invention of capitalism
  • 4. THE INVENTION OF CAPITALISM Classical Political Economy and the Secret History of Primitive Accumulation michael perelman Duke University Press • Durham & London 2000
  • 5. ∫ 2000 Duke University Press All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper $ Typeset in Trump Mediaeval by Keystone Typesetting, Inc. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data appear on the last printed page of this book.
  • 6. Contents Introduction: Dark Designs 1 1 The Enduring Importance of Primitive Accumulation 13 2 The Theory of Primitive Accumulation 25 3 Primitive Accumulation and the Game Laws 38 4 The Social Division of Labor and Household Production 59 5 Elaborating the Model of Primitive Accumulation 92 6 The Dawn of Political Economy 124 7 Sir James Steuart’s Secret History of Primitive Accumulation 139 8 Adam Smith’s Charming Obfuscation of Class 171 9 The Revisionist History of Professor Adam Smith 196 10 Adam Smith and the Ideological Role of the Colonies 229 11 Benjamin Franklin and the Smithian Ideology of Slavery and Wage Labor 254 12 The Classics as Cossacks: Classical Political Economy versus the Working Class 280 13 The Counterattack 321 14 Notes on Development 352 Conclusion 369 References 371 Index 407
  • 8. the invention of capitalism
  • 10. Introduction: Dark Designs In order to develop the laws of bourgeois economy . . . it is not necessary to write the real history of the relations of production. But the correct observation and deduction of these laws . . . always leads to primary equations . . . which point toward a past lying behind the system. These indications . . . then offer the key to understanding the past—a work in its own right.—Karl Marx, Grundrisse Preface In the development of a theory, the invisible of a visible field is not generally anything whatever outside and foreign to the visible defined by that field. The invisible is defined by the visible as its invisible, its forbidden vision: the invisible is not therefore simply what is outside the visible (to return to the spatial meta-phor), the outer darkness of exclusion—but the inner darkness of exclusion, inside the visible itself.—Louis Althusser, ‘‘From Capital to Marx’s Philosophy’’ The Laissez-faire Message of Classical Political Economy Classical political economy, the core works of economic literature from the time of William Petty through that of David Ricardo, presents an imposing facade. The towering figures of early political economy forged a new way of thinking systematically about economic affairs in the late seventeenth and early eighteenth centuries with little more than the writ-ings of business people and moral philosophers to guide them. Every one, from Karl Marx, who created the term ‘‘classical political economy,’’ to modern-day conservatives, recognizes the enormous intellectual achieve-ment of these early economists. For more than two centuries, successive generations of economists have been grinding out texts to demonstrate how these early theorists discovered that markets provide the most efficient method for organizing production. An uncompromising advocacy of laissez-faire is, ostensibly, the intended lesson of classical political economy. Most contemporary readers of Adam Smith, David Ricardo, and the other classical political economists accept their work at face value, as-suming these early writers to be uncompromising advocates of laissez-
  • 11. 2 faire. For the most part, even many Marxists accept this interpretation of classical political economy. Alongside their work on pure economic the-ory, the classical political economists engaged in a parallel project: to pro-mote the forcible reconstruction of society into a purely market-oriented system. While economic historians may debate the depth of involvement in market activities at the time, the incontestable fact remains that most people in Britain did not enthusiastically engage in wage labor—at least so long as they had an alternative. To make sure that people accepted wage labor, the classical political economists actively advocated measures to deprive people of their tradi-tional means of support. The brutal acts associated with the process of stripping the majority of the people of the means of producing for them-selves might seem far removed from the laissez-faire reputation of clas-sical political economy. In reality, the dispossession of the majority of small-scale producers and the construction of laissez-faire are closely con-nected, so much so that Marx, or at least his translators, labeled this expropriation of the masses as ‘‘primitive accumulation.’’ The very sound of the expression, primitive accumulation, drips with poignant echoes of human consequences. The word ‘‘primitive,’’ first of all, suggests a brutality lacking in the subtleties of more modern forms of exploitation. It also implies that primitive accumulation was prior to the form of accumulation that people generally associate with capitalism. Finally, it hints at something that we might associate with ‘‘primitive’’ parts of the world, where capital accumulation has not advanced as far as elsewhere. The second term, accumulation, reminds us that the primary focus of the process was the accumulation of capital and wealth by a small sector of society, or as Marx (1977, 739–40) described it, ‘‘the conquest of the world of social wealth. It is the extension of the area of exploited human material and, at the same time, the extension of the indirect and direct sway of the capitalist.’’ Certainly, at least in the early stages of capitalism, primitive accumulation was a central element in the accumulation process. Although many modern scholars acknowledge the pervasive nature of primitive accumulation during the time that the classical political economists wrote, nobody to my knowledge has recognized the com-plicity of the classical political economists. They strongly advocated pol-icies that furthered the process of primitive accumulation, often through subterfuge. While energetically promoting their laissez-faire ideology, they cham-pioned time and time again policies that flew in the face of their laissez-
  • 12. introduction 3 faire principles, especially their analysis of the role of small-scale, rural producers. As we will see, the underlying development strategy of the classical political economists was consistent with a crude proto-Marxian model of primitive accumulation, which concluded that nonmarket forces might be required to speed up the process of capitalist assimilation in the countryside. This model also explains why most of the classical political economists expressed positions diametrically opposed to the theories usually credited to them. The Secret History of Primitive Accumulation Perhaps because so much of what the classical economists wrote about traditional systems of agricultural production was divorced from their seemingly more timeless remarks about pure theory, later readers have passed over such portions of their works in haste. Although this aspect of classical political economy might have seemed to fall outside the core of the subject, I argue that these interventionist recommendations were a significant element in the overall thrust of their works. Specifically, clas-sical political economy advocated restricting the viability of traditional occupations in the countryside to coerce people to work for wages. Chapter 1, which deals with the history of primitive accumulation, demonstrates the classical political economists’ keen interest in driving rural workers from the countryside and into factories, compelling work-ers to do the bidding of those who would like to employ them, and eradi-cating any sign of sloth. The vitality of these rural producers generally rested on a careful com-bination of industrial and agricultural pursuits. Despite the efficiency of this arrangement, classical political economy was intent on throttling small producers. Classical political economists often justified their posi-tion in terms of the efficiency of the division of labor. They called for measures that would actively promote the separation of agriculture and industry. As we shall see, Marx’s concept of the social division of labor is very important in this respect. In contrast to Smith’s exclusive emphasis on the division of labor—the arrangement of work within the firm—Marx suggested that we also examine the deployment of resources between individual firms and households—the social division of labor. Classical political economists paid virtually no attention to the social division of labor in their theoretical works. For example, although Smith offered a detailed description of the division of labor in his famous pin factory, he did not bother to extend his discussion. What does it mean that
  • 13. 4 society is partitioned in such a way that the pin industry purchases its metals or fuels instead of producing them itself? How does such an ar-rangement originate? Could such changes in the pattern of industries make a difference in an economy, even if technology were unchanging? These questions were so distant from the purview of classical political economy that more than two centuries later, Ronald Coase won a Nobel Prize for bringing them to the attention of mainstream economists. Fol-lowing in the wake of Coase, a group of modern economists developed the new institutionalist school of economics (see Perelman 1991a), which contends that economic forces naturally arrange themselves into some optimal pattern. Like many other economists, the new institutionalist school takes pride in locating anticipations of its work in classical politi-cal economy, especially in the thought of Smith. Even though the new institutionalist school concerns itself with the social division of labor, its theories are of no use in analyzing the coercive nature of primitive ac-cumulation, since this school sees the economy arranging itself through voluntary contracts. Chapter 2 concentrates on the theory of primitive accumulation. Most discussions of primitive accumulation address the subject as a shorthand expression for describing the brutality of the initial burst of capitalism. In contrast, this chapter makes the case for treating primitive accumulation as an essential theoretical concept in analyzing the ongoing process of capitalist accumulation. I suspected that the continuing silence about the social division of labor might have something important to reveal. Following this line of inves-tigation, I looked at what classical political economy had to say about the peasantry and self-sufficient agriculturalists. Here again, the pattern was consistent. The classical political economists were unwilling to trust market forces to determine the social division of labor because they found the tenacity of traditional rural producers to be distasteful. Rather than contending that market forces should determine the fate of these small-scale producers, classical political economy called for state interventions of one sort or another to hobble these people’s ability to produce for their own needs. These policy recommendations amounted to a blatant manipulation of the social division of labor. We cannot justify such policies on the basis of efficiency. If efficiency were of great importance to them, the classical political economists would not have ignored the law permitting the gentry to ride across small farm-ers’ fields in pursuit of foxes while forbidding the farmers from ridding their land of game that might eat the crops. As we shall see in Chapter 3,
  • 14. introduction 5 these Game Laws destroyed an enormous share of the total agricultural produce. Chapter 3 describes the extraordinary history of the Game Laws. Al-though the origin of the Game Laws was feudal, their application and their ferocity peaked during the Industrial Revolution. They were a useful instrument to separate rural people from a major source of sustenance, adding considerable weight to the pressures to accept wage labor. They also incited many poor people in the countryside to rebel. Chapter 4 discusses the relationship between primitive accumulation and the social division of labor from the standpoint of self-provisioning. Chapter 5 analyzes classical political economy’s implicit proto-Marxian theory of primitive accumulation. In addition, it discusses the pattern of practical measures that altered the social division of labor to the detri-ment of independent and small-scale producers. This chapter also dis-cusses how classical political economy applied the calculus of primitive accumulation. It details the relationship between early classical political economy and the rural population with an eye toward efforts to create a capitalistic social division of labor. It demonstrates the continual impor-tance that classical political economy placed on the process of primitive accumulation. The Secret History of Classical Political Economy Why has the social division of labor as an aspect of primitive accumula-tion gone unnoticed for so long by so many students of classical political economy? True, the classical political economists generally maintained their silence regarding primitive accumulation when discussing matters of pure economic theory—although they were not absolutely consistent in this regard. Because of the novelty of their subject, these writers were not entirely in control of their own ideas. Specifically, I found that classical political economy openly expressed its dissatisfaction with the existing social divi-sion of labor quite clearly in diaries, letters, and more practical writings about contemporary affairs. This discovery led me to give a substantially new reading to the history of classical political economy. In their unguarded moments, the intuition of the classical political economists led them to openly express important insights of which they may have been only vaguely, if at all, aware. As a result, they let the idea of the social division of labor surface from time to time even in their more theoretical works. The subject typically cropped up when they were ac-knowledging that the market seemed incapable of engaging the rural pop-
  • 15. 6 ulation fast enough to suit them—or more to the point, that people were resisting wage labor. Much of this discussion touched on what we now call primitive accumulation. Although these slips flew in the face of the laissez-faire theory of classi-cal political economy, they add much to the value of that literature. In-deed, if classical political economy were nothing more than a conscious attempt to come to grips with and justify the emerging forces of capital-ism, it would have far less contemporary interest. Just as a psychologist might detect a crucial revelation in a seemingly offhand remark of a patient, from time to time classical political economy discloses to us insights into its program that the classical political econo-mists would not consciously welcome. These insights will reinforce the conclusions that we draw from their diaries, letters, and more practical writings. The Invention of Capitalism is novel in four major respects. First, it addresses the question of what determines the social division of labor, the division of society into independent firms and industries from the per-spective of classical political economy. It also develops the theoretical implications of primitive accumulation. Third, this book offers a signifi-cantly different interpretation of classical political economy, demonstrat-ing that this school of thought supported the process of primitive ac-cumulation. Finally, it analyzes the role of primitive accumulation in the work of Marx. All of these threads come together in helping us to under-stand how modern capitalism developed and the role of classical political economy in furthering this process. On Reading Classical Political Economy Modern economists sometimes present classical political economy as a polestar by which we can fix our bearings and, in rare cases, guide our-selves toward the future. This approach is disingenuous. Despite the in-valuable lessons that we can learn from studying classical political econ-omy, economists rarely read this literature with an eye to the future or even the past. All too often, seemingly open-minded reviews of the past are merely a means to justify preexisting views of the present. Some readers delight in discovering in classical political economy anticipations of recent techni-cal refinements, such as the theory of utility maximization. Others use the classics to cast their contemporaries in an unfavorable light. John Maynard Keynes, for example, contrasted the common sense of the mer-
  • 16. introduction 7 cantilists with the irrelevant elegance of Professor Pigou. Still other read-ers find the emphasis of the classics on dynamics, growth, or capital ac-cumulation attractive. In using classical political economy as a polestar, many economists represent it as if it were a uniform theory accepted by all. Of course, classical political economy was never a fixed body in space, but a hetero-geneous collection of literature written over a period of about 100 years. If fixity does appear, it is only in the eye of the beholder. Even if many readers do acknowledge the diversity of the literature, they single out a select group of classical political economists as its stars. In general, they portray classical political economy as orbiting around a point somewhere between Smith and Ricardo. Some hold it to be closer to one or the other, but whatever its center, there is a general consensus as to what con-stitutes the canonical literature. In reality, we lack objective standards for selecting the stars of classi-cal political economy. Writing about the entertainment industry, Moshe Adler (1985, 208) has described a process whereby stars can emerge, even when they do not significantly differ in talent from lesser lights: The phenomenon of stars exists where consumption requires knowl-edge. . . . As an example, consider listening to music. Appreciation increases with knowledge. But how does one know about music? By listening to it, and by discussing it with other persons who know about it. [We are] better off patronizing the same artist as others do. . . . Stardom is a market device to economize on learning. Economists studying the selection of technologies have found a simi-lar phenomenon. In the early stages of the development of a technology, seemingly trivial accidents can determine which of several technological paths is chosen. Once industry becomes locked into a particular tech-nological standard, it may continue to follow that line of development even though hindsight shows that the neglected paths might have been superior (see Arthur 1989). A similar process is at work in the study of classical political economy, notwithstanding the significant variations that exist in the talents of early political economists. Once the status of a book is initially elevated, stu-dents are drawn into giving it a deeper consideration. A tradition gradu-ally builds up around what becomes treated as almost sacred texts. Readers of these canonical works are brought into a multidimensional dialogue that includes the authors under study, their times, and the col-lective experience of earlier generations of readers of these texts. In this
  • 17. 8 sense, ‘‘the real life of an author emanates from his readers, disciples, commentators, opponents, critics. An author has no other existence’’ (Prezzolini 1967, 190; see also Latour 1987, 40). By working and reworking these texts, each successive generation finds new levels of meaning, some of which probably eluded even the political economists who created them. As a result, these works acquire a cumula-tive force—albeit highly symbolic—that calls new generations to confront them once again. This process reinforces the stature of the ‘‘founders’’ of political economy, thereby confirming their status as ‘‘stars.’’ Moreover, the erection of this solid structure of scholarship facilitates analysis by providing a cognitive map of the territory, allowing future researchers to navigate with more confidence. Smith’s Wealth of Nations, as we shall see, was not a particularly influ-ential book until a generation after its publication. Once opinion leaders found the book useful in promoting their desired political outcomes, its popularity soared. Only then did Smith become a polestar of classical political economy, and his work a reference point by which all others are judged. Because of this flawed selection process, most histories of the period studiously analyze Smith and Ricardo, along with a handful of supposedly secondary figures. Other equally deserving economists gener-ally escape notice altogether. This book proposes a new reading—a new cosmology so to speak—that remaps classical political economy. Here, the center is nearer to Sir James Steuart and Edward Gibbon Wakefield than to Smith and Ricardo. From this perspective, Adam Smith appears less like the sun than a moon, a lesser body whose light is largely reflected from other sources. This alternative cosmology is not an arbitrary rearrangement of the stars. It highlights important lessons from classical political economy. Within this context, Adam Smith becomes less original. His importance appears to emanate from the vigor of his ideological project of advocating laissez-faire and obfuscating all information that might cast doubt on his ideology. Others, such as Edward Gibbon Wakefield and John Rae, took a more realistic view about the nature of accumulation, but later econo-mists set their analyses aside to create the impression of a humanitarian heritage of political economy. Judging from the literature of the history of economic thought, it is clear this view of history has succeeded mightily. The Invention of Capitalism represents a plea to correct this legacy of error and omission. From this perspective we can see that, for all its heterogeneity, classical political economy did manage to compress much of the varied experience of its day into a compact body of literature that reflects the history of relations of
  • 18. introduction 9 production. Hence, the study of classical political economy provides an ef-fective vantage point for the study of the history of relations of production. Chapter 6 analyzes the role of primitive accumulation in the works of such early economists as Sir William Petty, Richard Cantillon, and the Physiocrats. Chapter 7 concentrates on the important work of Steuart, by far the most interesting and the most incisive theorist of primitive accumulation and the social division of labor prior to Marx. Besides seeing the implica-tions of primitive accumulation more clearly than the other classical po-litical economists, Steuart stood alone in his willingness to write openly and honestly about the subject. This characteristic explains the compara-tive obscurity of his reputation. Next, chapters 8 through 10 are devoted exclusively to Smith, who attempted to develop an alternative to Steuart. According to Smithian theory, the social division of labor would evolve in a satisfactory manner without recourse to outside intervention. This chapter demonstrates that even Smith’s celebrated discussion of the invisible hand was developed as a means of avoiding the challenge that primitive accumulation posed for his system. By showing that the social division of labor would evolve without recourse to outside intervention, Smith had hoped to put the question of primitive accumulation to rest. Although Smith’s theory was accepted as such, practice continued in a different manner. In fact, Smith himself advocated practices that were not in accordance with his theory. This chapter also indicates that Smith was far more interested in chang-ing human behavior than he was with matters of economic development. Chapter 9 examines how Smith attempted to distort history, sociology, and psychology to provide confirmation of this theory of the naturally evolving social division of labor. Chapter 10 continues with the work of Adam Smith, who based much of his theory on the experience of the colonies. Although Smith made great use of the colonial experience, the colonials did not take him nearly as seriously as the English did. The reason is not hard to fathom. In har-nessing the story of the colonies to his ideological cart, Smith did not do justice to the actual situation in the colonies. By tracing his analysis of the colonies, this chapter delves deeper into the manner in which Smith pur-posely obscured the nature of the social division of labor. Chapter 11 continues the study of Smithian theory and practice by comparing Smith with his friend Benjamin Franklin. This genial Ameri-can was a man of practice rather than theory, yet his practical analysis greatly influenced the theory of his day. Franklin’s role is especially key to Smith’s theory of colonial development.
  • 19. 10 Chapter 12 continues the analysis of the relationship of classical politi-cal economy and primitive accumulation into the age of David Ricardo and Thomas Robert Malthus. By reading their works and those of their contem-poraries in terms of their relationship to political economy, we provide a new twist to the different interpretation of classical political economy. This chapter reveals that despite the adherence to the doctrine of laissez-faire in theory, classical political economists maintained a strong interest in promoting policies that furthered primitive accumulation. Chapter 13 investigates the reaction against Smith, beginning with the relatively unknown work of Robert Gourlay and the development of his ideas in the practical school of Wakefield, the systemic colonizer who stressed that the social division of labor should be organized for the pur-pose of capitalist development. The chapter concludes with an analysis of John Rae. Chapter 14 discusses the commonality between Smith and such later revolutionary leaders as Vladimir Ilyich Lenin and Mao Tse-Tung. Dark Designs Classical political economy is the product of a stormy period, distin-guished by the emergence of capitalist social relations. These truly mo-mentous changes of the time do not seem to appear in the great theoretical works of the time. Indeed, the classical political economists displayed little interest in conveying information about the great conflicts between capital and labor, or between capital and early precapitalist relations in the countryside. Nonetheless, these matters were of great importance to classical political economy. While we catch an occasional glimpse of primitive accumulation in the canonical works of classical political economy, for the most part, we must read of the glaring conflicts indirectly. Our tactic is to approach classical political economy in the way that children learn to view a solar eclipse: by punching a small hole in a piece of paper held above another piece. The dark design that appears on the lower paper is the shadow of an eclipse, albeit with some refraction. The classical political economists made this indirect approach necessary because they were generally successful in obscuring the role of primitive accumulation in their theoretical texts. Yet, as mentioned earlier, when we turn to their letters, diaries, and more policy-oriented works, the importance of primitive accumulation be-comes far clearer. We can push our analogy of classical political economy and solar eclipses a bit further. Both represent rare and fascinating events. Past
  • 20. introduction 11 peoples have superstitiously interpreted solar eclipses as signs of im-pending epochal change. Similarly, the titans of political economy were thought to have been able to see over the heads of their contemporaries into the future. In this sense, their theories foreshadowed coming changes in the structure of society. Both phenomena, planetary configurations found millions of miles away and the social changes of a century or more ago, reflect important forces that still shape our lives. Specifically, the struggle against self-provisioning is not confined to the distant past. It continues to this day (see Perelman 1991b). In effect, we can look at the eclipse of precapitalist production relations in much the same fashion, with one major exception: in the case of a solar eclipse, the brilliance of the source can destroy our vision. In the case of classical political economy, the source has attempted to obscure our vision. Revising Classical Political Economy Our classical forbearers may have been bright, but they were also fallible human beings. They were certainly not wholly disinterested observers. Their theories were intended to advance their own interests or those of the groups with whom they identified. These interests colored their works, whether or not they realized this influence themselves. In regard to the struggle over primitive accumulation, these writers seem to have been intentionally obscure insofar as they could, lest they undermine their claim to generality for their theory. The struggle against the self-provisioning of rural people cast only a light shadow across the pages of classical political economy, a glimpse of an all-but-forgotten way of life obliterated by the process of primitive accumulation. Conse-quently, this process has largely gone unnoticed by modern readers of classical political economy. Although we find ourselves reduced to studying the shadows of this struggle, the attempt is still worth the effort. Indeed, we will see that classical political economy conforms to a consistent pattern of almost always supporting positions that would work to harness small-scale agri-cultural producers to the interests of capital. This book may be controversial in that it contradicts the commonly accepted theory that classical political economy offered its unconditional support for the doctrine of laissez-faire. It questions the relative impor-tance of the almost universally admired Smith and makes the case that Smith and other classical authors sought to promote the process of primi-tive accumulation. This rereading suggests that classical political econ-
  • 21. 12 omy followed a different project, one that contradicts the standard inter-pretation of classical political economy. Before turning to the main body of this work, I wish to append a caveat about my imagery of the eclipse. By studying the shadows cast by the classics, we must keep in mind that such images have fewer dimensions than the object under study. One dimension that disappears from the perspective of classical political economy concerns the social relations between labor and capital. Writing from the comfortable heights of their elevated social position, the classical political economists interpreted working-class organization as mere disorder. Because of this insensitivity, a work such as this one is necessarily imbalanced. Much attention is given to the efforts of capital to control labor, but little is devoted to the reverse. I leave the reader with the responsibility of estimating the actual balance of forces. I hope that this book succeeds in making three points. First, primitive accumulation was an important force in capitalist development. Second, primitive accumulation cannot be relegated to a precapitalist past or even some imagined moment when feudal society suddenly became capitalist. Primitive accumulation played a continuing role in capitalist develop-ment. Third, classical political economy was concerned with promoting primitive accumulation in order to foster capitalist development, even though the logic of primitive accumulation was in direct conflict with the classical political economists’ purported adherence to the values of laissez-faire. I recognize that the seeds of capitalism had been planted long before the age of classical political economy, but never before and nowhere else had the process of capital accumulation become so intense. Hopefully, The Invention of Capitalism will throw light on the origins of that intensity.
  • 22. chapter 1 The Enduring Importance of Primitive Accumulation Common fields and pastures kept alive a vigorous co-operative spirit in the com-munity; enclosures starved it. In champion [sic] country people had to work to-gether amicably, to agree upon crop rotations, stints of common pasture, the up-keep and improvement of their grazings and meadows, the clearing of the ditches, the fencing of the fields. They toiled side by side in the fields, and they walked together from field to village, from farm to heath, morning, afternoon and evening. They all depended on common resources for their fuel, for bedding, and fodder for their stock, and by pooling so many of the necessities of livelihood they were disciplined from early youth to submit to the rules and customs of the community. After enclosure, when every man could fence his own piece of territory and warn his neighbours off, the discipline of sharing things fairly with one’s neighbours was relaxed, and every household became an island unto itself. This was the great revolution in men’s lives, greater than all the economic changes following en-closure. Yet few people living in this world bequeathed to us by the enclosing and improving farmer are capable of gauging the full significance of a way of life that is now lost.—Joan Thirsk, ‘‘Enclosing and Engrossing’’ Compulsion and the Creation of a Working Class The brutal process of separating people from their means of providing for themselves, known as primitive accumulation, caused enormous hard-ships for the common people. This same primitive accumulation pro-vided a basis for capitalist development. Joan Thirsk, one of the most knowledgeable historians of early British agriculture, describes above the nature of some of the harshest social and personal transformations associ-ated with the enclosures. Some people denounced this expropriation. Marx (1977, 928) echoed their sentiment, charging: ‘‘The expropriation of the direct producers was accomplished by means of the most merciless barbarianism, and under the stimulus of the most infamous, the most sordid, the most petty and the most odious of passions.’’ Formally, this dispossession was perfectly legal. After all, the peasants did not have property rights in the narrow sense. They only had tradi-
  • 23. 14 tional rights. As markets evolved, first land-hungry gentry and later the bourgeoisie used the state to create a legal structure to abrogate these traditional rights (Tigar and Levy 1977). Simple dispossession from the commons was a necessary, but not al-ways sufficient condition to harness rural people to the labor market. Even after the enclosures, laborers retained privileges in ‘‘the shrubs, woods, undergrowth, stone quarries and gravel pits, thereby obtaining fuel for cooking and wood for animal life, crab apples and cob nuts from the hedgerows, brambles, tansy and other wild herbs from any other little patch of waste. . . . Almost every living thing in the parish however insig-nificant could be turned to some good use by the frugal peasant-labourer or his wife’’ (Everitt 1967, 405). To the extent that the traditional economy might be able to remain intact despite the loss of the commons, a supply of labor satisfactory to capital might not be forthcoming. As a result, the level of real wages would be higher, thereby impeding the process of accumulation. Not sur-prisingly, one by one, these traditional rights also disappeared. In the eyes of the bourgeoisie, ‘‘property became absolute property: all the tolerated ‘rights’ that the peasantry had acquired or preserved . . . were now re-jected’’ (Foucault 1979, 85). Primitive accumulation cut through traditional lifeways like scissors. The first blade served to undermine the ability of people to provide for themselves. The other blade was a system of stern measures required to keep people from finding alternative survival strategies outside the sys-tem of wage labor. A host of oftentimes brutal laws designed to under-mine whatever resistance people maintained against the demands of wage labor accompanied the dispossession of the peasants’ rights, even before capitalism had become a significant economic force. For example, beginning with the Tudors, England enacted a series of stern measures to prevent peasants from drifting into vagrancy or falling back onto welfare systems. According to a 1572 statute, beggars over the age of fourteen were to be severely flogged and branded with a red-hot iron on the left ear unless someone was willing to take them into service for two years. Repeat offenders over eighteen were to be executed unless someone would take them into service. Third offenses automatically re-sulted in execution (Marx 1977, 896ff.; Marx 1974, 736; Mantoux 1961, 432). Similar statutes appeared almost simultaneously during the early sixteenth century in England, the Low Countries, and Zurich (LeRoy Ladurie 1974, 137). Eventually, the majority of workers, lacking any alter-native, had little choice but to work for wages at something close to subsistence level.
  • 24. importance of primitive accumulation 15 In the wake of primitive accumulation, the wage relationship became a seemingly voluntary affair. Workers needed employment and employers wanted workers. In reality, of course, the underlying process was far from voluntary. As Foucault (1979, 222) argues: Historically, the process by which the bourgeoisie became the politi-cally dominant class in the course of the 18th Century was masked by the establishment of an explicitly coded and formally egalitarian juridical framework, made possible by the organization of a parlia-mentary, representative regime. But the development and generaliza-tion of disciplinary mechanisms constituted the other, dark side of these processes . . . supported by these tiny, everyday, physical mech-anisms, by all those systems of micro-power that are essentially non-egalitarian. Indeed, the history of the recruitment of labor is an uninterrupted story of coercion either through the brute force of poverty or more direct regula-tion, which made a continuation of the old ways impossible (Moore 1951). Of course, the extractions common to traditional relatively self-sufficient household economy kept many people at or just above the subsistence level, but for many the market was a step backward. The disorienting introduction of the individualistic ways of the market cut people off from their traditional networks and created a sense of dehumanization (see Kuczynski 1967, 70). A purported need for discipline justified the harsh measures that the poor endured. Indeed, writers of every persuasion shared an obsessional concern with the creation of a disciplined labor force (Furniss 1965; Appleby 1978). Supporters of such measures typically defended their position by invoking the need to civilize workers or stamp out sloth and indolence. Yet capital required these measures to conquer the household economy in order to be able to extract a greater mass of surplus value. In fact, almost everyone close to the process of primitive accumulation, whether a friend or foe of labor, agreed with Charles Hall’s (1805, 144) verdict that ‘‘if they were not poor, they would not submit to employments’’—at least so long as their remuneration were held low enough to create substantial profits. Employers were quick to perceive the relationship between poverty and the chance to earn handsome profits. Ambrose Crowley, for example, set up his factory in the north rather than the midlands, for there ‘‘the cuntry is verry poore and populous soe workmen must of necessity increase’’ (cited in Pollard 1965, 197). This process was cumulative. An increase in poverty begat more population, which in turn created further poverty, and so on. In this regard, Marx (1865, 72) noted that the level of wages in the
  • 25. 16 agricultural districts of England varied according to the particular condi-tions under which the peasantry had emerged from serfdom. The more impoverished the serfs, the lower their descendants’ wages would be. Classical Political Economy and the War on Sloth The classical political economists joined in the chorus of those condemn-ing the sloth and indolence of the poor. Although they applauded the leisure activities of the rich, they denounced all behavior on the part of the less fortunate that did not yield a maximum of work effort. Consider the case of Francis Hutcheson—‘‘the never to be forgotten Dr. Hutcheson,’’ as his student, Adam Smith, later described him in a letter to Dr. Archibald Davidson (reprinted in Mossner and Ross 1977, 309)—the same Francis Hutcheson whose Short Introduction to Moral Philosophy in Three Books (1742) seems to have served as a model for the economic sections of Smith’s Glasgow lectures (see Scott 1965, 235, 240). A later work, his System of Moral Philosophy, exemplifies Dr. Hutcheson’s contributions to that noble field of moral philosophy. After a few brief notes on the need to raise prices, Hutcheson (1755, 2:318–19) mused: ‘‘If a people have not acquired an habit of industry, the cheapness of all the necessaries of life encourages sloth. The best remedy is to raise the demand for all necessaries. . . . Sloth should be punished by tempo-rary servitude at least.’’ The menacing ‘‘at least’’ in this citation suggests that the never-to-be-forgotten professor might have had even sterner med-icine in mind than mere temporary servitude. What else might the good doctor recommend to earnest students of moral philosophy in the event that temporary servitude proved inadequate in shunting people off to the workplace? This attitude, of course, is not unique to classical political economy. We might ask, was there ever a nation in which the rich found the poor to be sufficiently industrious? The universal howl of ‘‘sloth and indolence’’ can be heard as far away as nineteenth-century Japan, to cite one example (see T. Smith 1966, 120). However, no country seems to have gone as far as England in its war on sloth. Indeed, writers of the time charged that a want of discipline was responsible for criminality as well as disease. By the late eighteenth century, even hospitals came to be regarded as a proper me-dium to instill discipline (see Ignatieff 1978, 61ff.). Almost poetically, Thomas Mun (1664, 193) railed against ‘‘the general leprosy of our piping, potting, feasting, fashions, and misspending of our time in idleness and pleasure.’’ Josiah Tucker (1776a, 44–45) employed a military metaphor to make a similar point:
  • 26. importance of primitive accumulation 17 In a word, the only possible Means of preventing a Rival Nation from running away with your Trade, is to prevent your own People from being more idle and vicious than they are. . . . So the only War, which can be attended with Success in that Respect, is a War against Vice and Idleness; a War, whose Forces must consist of—not Fleets and Armies—but such judicious Taxes and Wise regulations, as will turn the Passion of private Self-Love into the Channel of Public Good. Primitive Accumulation and the Eradication of Holidays Although their standard of living may not have been particularly lavish, the people of precapitalistic northern Europe, like most traditional peo-ple, enjoyed a great deal of free time (see Ashton 1972, 204; see also V. Smith 1992; Wisman 1989). The common people maintained innumer-able religious holidays that punctuated the tempo of work. Joan Thirsk estimated that in the sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries, about one-third of the working days, including Sundays, were spent in leisure (cited in K. Thomas 1964, 63; see also Wilensky 1961). Karl Kautsky (1899, 107) offered a much more extravagant estimate that 204 annual holidays were celebrated in medieval Lower Bavaria. Despite these frequent holidays, the peasants still managed to produce a significant surplus. In English feudal society, for example, the peasants survived even though the gentry was powerful enough to extract some-thing on the order of 50 percent of the produce (see Postan 1966, 603). As markets evolved, the claims on the peasants’ labors multiplied. For in-stance, in southern France, rents appear to have grown from about one-fourth of the yield in 1540 to one-half by 1665 (LeRoy Ladurie 1974, 117). Although people increasingly had to curtail their leisure in order to meet the growing demands of nonproducers, many observers still railed against the excessive celebration of holidays. Protestant clergy were especially vocal in this regard (Hill 1967, 145–218; see also Marx 1977, 387; Freuden-berger and Cummins 1976). Even as late as the 1830s, we hear the com-plaint that the Irish working year contained only 200 days after all holidays had been subtracted (Great Britain 1840, 570; cited in Mokyr 1983, 222). Time, in a market society, is money. As Sir Henry Pollexfen (1700, 45; cited in Furniss 1965, 44) calculated: ‘‘For if but 2 million of working people at 6d. a day comes to 500,000£ which upon due inquiry whence our riches must arise, will appear to be so much lost to the nation by every holiday that is kept.’’ Zeal in the suppression of religious festivals was not an indication that representatives of capital took working-class devotion lightly. In some
  • 27. 18 rural districts of nineteenth-century England, tending to one’s garden on the Sabbath was a punishable offense. Some workers were even impris-oned for this crime (Marx 1977, 375–76n). Piety, however, also had its limits. The same worker might be charged with breach of contract should he prefer to attend church on the Sabbath rather than report for work when called to do so (ibid.). In France, where capital was slower to take charge, the eradication of holidays was likewise slower. Tobias Smollett (1766, 38) complained of the French: ‘‘Very nearly half of their time, which might be profitably employed in the exercise of industry, is lost to themselves and the com-munity, in attendance upon the different exhibitions of religious mum-mery.’’ Voltaire called for the shifting of holidays to the following Sunday. Since Sunday was a day of rest in any case, employers could enjoy approxi-mately forty additional working days per year. This proposal caused the naive Abbe Baudeau to wonder about the wisdom of intensifying work when the countryside was already burdened with an excess population (cited in Weulersse 1959, 28). How could the dispossessed be employed? Of course, changes in the religious practices of Europe were not induced by a shortage of people but by people’s willingness to conform to the needs of capital. For example, the leaders of the French Revolution, who prided themselves on their rationality, decreed a ten-day week with only a single day off. Classical political economists enthusiastically joined in the con-demnation of the celebration of an excessive number of holidays (see Cantillon 1755, 95; Senior 1831, 9). The suppression of religious holidays was but a small part of the larger process of primitive accumulation. Classical Political Economy and the Ideal Working Day Once capital began to dislodge the traditional moorings of society, the bourgeoisie sought every possible opportunity to engage people in produc-tive work that would turn a profit for employers. Accordingly, classical political economists advocated actions to shape society around the logic of accumulation in order to strengthen the dependency on wage labor. In the utopia of early classical political economy, the poor would work every waking hour. One writer suggested that the footmen of the gentry could rise early to employ their idle hours making fishing nets along with ‘‘disbanded soldiers, poor prisoners, widows and orphans, all poor trades-men, artificers, and labourers, their wives, children, and servants’’ (Puckle 1700, 2:380; cited in Appleby 1976, 501). Joseph Townsend (1786, 442) proposed that when farm workers re-turned in the evenings from threshing or ploughing, ‘‘they might card,
  • 28. importance of primitive accumulation 19 they might spin, or they might knit.’’ Many were concerned that chil-dren’s time might go to waste. William Temple called for the addition of four-year-old children to the labor force. Anticipating modern Skinnerian psychology, Temple (1770, 266; see also Furniss 1965, 114–15) speculated, ‘‘for by these means, we hope that the rising generation will be so habitu-ated to constant employment that it would at length prove agreeable and entertaining to them.’’ Not to be outdone, John Locke, often seen as a philosopher of liberty, called for the commencement of work at the ripe age of three (Cranston 1957, 425). Others called for new institutional arrangements to ensure a steadily increasing flow of wage labor. Fletcher of Saltoun recommended perpetual slavery as the appropriate fate of all who would fail to respond to less harsh measures to integrate them into the labor force (see Marx 1977, 882). Hutcheson, as we have seen, followed suit. Always the idealist, Bishop George Berkeley (1740, 456) preferred that such slavery be limited to ‘‘a certain term of years.’’ No source of labor was to be overlooked. For example, in a movement that Foucault has termed ‘‘the great confinement,’’ institutions were founded to take charge indiscriminately of the sick, criminal, and poor (Foucault 1965, 38–65). The purpose was not to better the conditions of the inmates but rather to force them to contribute more to the national wealth (for a selection of citations that reflect more charitably on the early political economists, see Wiles 1968). Occasionally, writers of the time found signs of progress. By 1723, Daniel Defoe (1724–26, 86; see also 493) was delighted to discover that so much progress had taken place in Norwich that ‘‘the very children after four or five years of age, could every one earn their own bread.’’ For classical political economy such edifying scenes of hard labor were not common enough. To his credit, Jean-Baptiste Say (1821, 50–51; see also Ricardo 1951–73, 8:184), generally a strong proponent of capitalist development, penned one of the few protests of the state of affairs in Britain in a letter to Robert Malthus: I shall not attempt to point out the parts of this picture which apply to your country, Sir. . . . But if social life [a term that Say used almost like the social division of labor] were a galley, in which after rowing with all their strength for sixteen hours out of the twenty-four, they might indeed be excused for disliking social life. . . . I maintain no other doctrine when I say that the utility of productions is no longer worth the productive services, at the rate at which we are compelled to pay for them.
  • 29. 20 Sadly, no other classical political economist was willing to side with Say in this regard. Bentham and Laissez-faire Authoritarianism Classical political economy frequently couched its recommendations in a rhetoric of individual liberty, but its conception of liberty was far from all-encompassing. Liberty, for capital, depended on the hard work of common people. Lionel Robbins (1981, 8), a strong proponent of market society, also alluded to this authoritarian side of laissez-faire, noting, ‘‘the necessity of a framework of law and an apparatus of enforcement is an essential part of the concept of a free society.’’ Earlier, he wrote, ‘‘If there be any ‘invisible hand’ in a non-collectivist order, it operates only in a framework of delib-erately contrived law and order’’ (Robbins 1939, 6; see also Samuels 1966). Within this contrived law and order, workers found their rights to orga-nize unions and even to act politically severely restricted. The entire judicial edifice was erected with an eye toward making ownership of capi-tal more profitable (Tigar and Levy 1977). Max Weber (1921, 108; see also Perelman 1991a, chap. 3) once observed that rational accounting methods are ‘‘associated with the social phe-nomena of ‘shop discipline’ and appropriation of the means of production, and that means: with the existence of a ‘system of domination’ [Herr-schaftsverhältniss].’’ Similarly, the rational accounting system of politi-cal economy required a ‘‘system of domination,’’ albeit on a grander scale. Weber concluded, ‘‘No special proof is necessary to show that military discipline is the ideal model for the modern capitalist factory’’ (1156). In this sense, we may see Jeremy Bentham, rather than Smith, as the archetypal representative of classical political economy. Indeed, Ben-tham’s dogmatic advocacy of laissez-faire far exceeded that of Smith. For example, after Smith made the case for a government role in controlling interest rates, Bentham (1787b, 133) caustically rebuked him with the words, ‘‘To prevent our doing mischief to one another, it is but too neces-sary to put bridles into our mouths.’’ Although Bentham theoretically championed laissez-faire in the name of freedom, he was intent on subordinating all aspects of life to the in-terests of accumulation. Bentham limited his passionate concern with laissez-faire to those who conformed to the norms of a capitalist society; a jarring confrontation with state power was to be the lot of the rest. Accord-ing to Bentham, ‘‘Property—not the institution of property, but the consti-tution of property—has become an end in itself’’ (Bentham 1952, 1:117).
  • 30. importance of primitive accumulation 21 Bentham was absolutely clear about the need for this ‘‘constitution of property.’’ He realized that even though control over labor is a major source of wealth, labor stubbornly resists the will of the capitalist. In Bentham’s (1822, 430) inimitable language: Human beings are the most powerful instruments of production, and therefore everyone becomes anxious to employ the services of his fellows in multiplying his own comforts. Hence the intense and uni-versal thirst for power; the equally prevalent hatred of subjection. Each man therefore meets with an obstinate resistance to his own will, and this naturally engenders antipathy toward beings who thus baffle and contravene his wishes. Bentham never acknowledged any contradiction between his advocacy of laissez-faire and his proposals for managing labor. For him: ‘‘Between wealth and power, the connexion is most close and intimate: so intimate, indeed, that the disentanglement of them, even in the imagination, is a matter of no small difficulty. They are each of them respectively an in-strument of the production of the other’’ (Bentham 1962, 48; cited in Macpherson 1987, 88–89). Bentham understood that the struggles to subdue the poor would spill over into every aspect of life. He hoped to turn these struggles into profit for himself and, to a lesser extent, others of his class. Given labor’s natural resistance to creating wealth for those who exploited them, unfree labor held an obvious attraction for Bentham. He designed detailed plans for his fabled Panopticon, a prison engineered for maximum control of inmates in order to profit from their labor. In a 1798 companion piece to his design for the Panopticon, Pauper Management Improved, Bentham proposed a National Charity Company modeled after the East India Company—a privately owned, joint stock company partially subsidized by the government. It was to have absolute authority over the ‘‘whole body of the burdensome poor,’’ starting with 250 industry houses accommodating a half million people and expanding to 500 houses for one million people (Bentham n.d., 369; cited in Him-melfarb 1985, 78). Bentham planned to profit handsomely from these inmates, especially those born in the houses, since they would then have to work as appren-tices within the company. He rhapsodized, ‘‘So many industry-houses, so many crucibles, in which dross of this kind [the poor] is converted into sterling’’ (cited in Himmelfarb 1985, 80). A strict regimen, unremitting supervision and discipline, and economies of diet, dress, and lodging would make profits possible. Jeremy Bentham, vigorous advocate of free-
  • 31. 22 dom of commerce that he was, dreamed of the profits that would accrue from the use of inmate labor: What hold can another manufacturer have upon his workmen, equal to what my manufacturer would have upon his? What other master is there that can reduce his workmen, if idle, to a situation next to starving, without suffering them to go elsewhere? What other master is there whose men can never get drunk unless he chooses that they should do so. And who, so far from being able to raise their wages by combination, are obliged to take whatever pittance he thinks it most his interest to allow? (see also Ignatieff 1978, 110; Foucault 1979) According to classical political economy, all social conditions and all social institutions were to be judged merely on the basis of their effect on the production of wealth. In this spirit, Bentham recommended that chil-dren be put to work at four instead of fourteen, bragging that they would thereby be spared the loss of those ‘‘ten precious years in which nothing is done! Nothing for industry! Nothing for improvement, moral or intellec-tual!’’ (cited in Himmelfarb 1985, 81). Bentham went even further, intent on subordinating every facet of hu-man existence to the profit motive. He even wanted to promote the ‘‘gen-tlest of all revolutions,’’ the sexual revolution. In this regard, Bentham was not the least concerned with furthering the bounds of human free-dom, but with ensuring that the inmates would have as many offspring as possible (ibid., 83). Bentham was even planning to call himself the ‘‘Sub- Regulus of the Poor.’’ Unfortunately, because of lack of government sup-port, his plans came to naught. As he complained in his memoirs, ‘‘But for George the Third, all the prisoners in England would, years ago, have been made under my management’’ (Bentham 1830–31, 96). Alas, Bentham never succeeded in his personal goals. Perhaps he was too greedy. Perhaps his methods were too crude. Instead, as we shall see, capitalism found more subtle methods for harnessing labor. As a result, today we remember Bentham as a valiant defender of the ideals of laissez-faire rather than as the Sub-Regulus of the Poor. Victory Classical political economists were generally more coy about their inten-tions than Bentham. Despite their antipathy to indolence and sloth, they covered themselves with a flurry of rhetoric about natural liberties. On closer examination, we find that the notion of the system of natural liber-ties was considerably more flexible than it appeared. Let us turn once
  • 32. importance of primitive accumulation 23 again to Francis Hutcheson, who taught Smith about the virtue of natural liberty. He contended that ‘‘it is the one great design of civil laws to strengthen by political sanctions the several laws of nature. . . . The pop-ulace needs to be taught, and engaged by laws, into the best methods of managing their own affairs and exercising mechanic art’’ (Hutcheson 1749, 273; emphasis added). In effect, Hutcheson realized that once primi-tive accumulation had taken place, the appeal of formal slavery dimin-ished. Extramarket forces of all sorts would become unnecessary, since the market itself would ensure that the working class remained in a con-tinual state of deprivation. Patrick Colquhoun (1815, 110), a London po-lice magistrate, noted: Poverty is that state and condition in society where the individual has no surplus labour in store, or, in other words, no property or means of subsistence but what is derived from the constant exercise of industry in the various occupations of life. Poverty is therefore a most necessary and indispensable ingredient in society, without which nations and communities could not exist in a state of civiliza-tion. It is the lot of man. It is the source of wealth, since without poverty, there could be no labour; there could be no riches, no re-finement, no comfort, and no benefit to those who may be possessed of wealth. Or, as Marx (1865, 55–56) phrased it: ‘‘We find on the market a set of buyers, possessed of land, machinery, raw materials, and the means of subsistence, all of them, save land, the products of labour, and on the other hand, a set of sellers who have nothing to sell except their labouring power, their working arms and brains.’’ Later political economists disregarded the compulsion required to force labor into the market, blithely assuming that the market alone was suffi-cient to guarantee the advancement of the accumulation process without the aid of extramarket forces. Workers at the time generally understood the strategic importance of measures to foster primitive accumulation. In this spirit, Thomas Spence, a courageous working-class advocate, pro-claimed that ‘‘it is childish . . . to expect . . . to see anything else than the utmost screwing and grinding of the poor, till you quite overturn the present system of landed property’’ (cited in E. P. Thompson 1963, 805). The system, however, was not overturned, but instead grew stronger. Workers were forced to surrender more and more of their traditional peri-ods of leisure (see Hill 1967; Reid 1976, 76–101). The working day was lengthened (Hammond and Hammond 1919, 5–7). The working class, in the person of Spence, cried out: ‘‘Instead of working only six days a week
  • 33. 24 we are obliged to work at the rate of eight or nine and yet can hardly subsist . . . and still the cry is work—work—ye are idle. . . . We, God help us, have fallen under the hardest set of masters that have ever existed’’ (cited in Kemp-Ashraf 1966, 277; see also Tawney 1926, esp. 223). This state-ment was eloquent enough to earn its author a sentence of three years’ imprisonment after its publication in 1803—a result typical of the fate of those who challenged the capitalist order. Whenever the working class and its friends effectively protested against capitalism, the silent compul-sion of capital (Marx 1977, 899) gave way to compulsory silence. Spence’s silencing was not completely effective. Although some merely wrote him off as a ‘‘radical crank’’ (Knox 1977, 73), more recent studies have demonstrated that Spence deserves a more respectful reception (Kemp-Ashraf 1966). Indeed, Spence’s biographer asserts that Owenism and the subsequent heritage of British socialism stands in direct line of descent from Spence’s critique of capitalism (Rudkin 1966, 191ff.). Jour-nalists of the time agreed with this evaluation (see Halevy 1961, 44n). Unfortunately, the Spences of the world were unable to reverse or even impede the process of primitive accumulation. No society went so far as the British in terms of primitive accumula-tion. This aspect of capitalist development is all but forgotten today. In-stead, separated by two centuries, contemporary economists such as Mil-ton Friedman (1962) gloss over the dark side of capitalism, ignoring the requisite subordination, while celebrating the freedom to dispose of one’s property. These modern economists, as we shall see, are very much mis-taken in their interpretation of the evolution of the so-called free market.
  • 34. chapter 2 The Theory of Primitive Accumulation Analytical Preliminaries Although primitive accumulation was a central concern to classical polit-ical economists, the study of this concept began in confusion and later settled into an unfortunate obscurity. The seemingly Marxian expression, ‘‘primitive accumulation,’’ originally began with Adam Smith’s (Smith 1976, 2.3, 277) assertion that ‘‘the accumulation of stock must, in the nature of things, be previous to the division of labour.’’ Smith’s approach to original accumulation is odd, to say the least. Cer-tainly, the division of labor is to be found throughout history. It even exists in insect societies (see Morely 1954). Yet Smith would have us believe that the division of labor had to wait for ‘‘the accumulation of stock,’’ his code word for capital. Such an idea is patently false. How could we interpret the division of labor in an anthill or a beehive as a conse-quence of the accumulation of stock? Marx translated Smith’s word, ‘‘previous’’ as ‘‘ursprünglich’’ (Marx and Engels 1973, 33:741), which Marx’s English translators, in turn, rendered as ‘‘primitive.’’ In the process, Marx rejected Smith’s otherworldly con-ception of previous accumulation. He chided Smith for attempting to explain the present existence of class by reference to a mythical past that lies beyond our ability to challenge it. Marx insisted, ‘‘Primitive accumu-lation plays approximately the same role in political economy as original sin does in theology’’ (1977, 873). Marx’s analogy is apt. Both original sin and original accumulation divert our attention away from the present to a mythical past, which supposedly explains the misfortunes that people suffer today. In other words, any theory based on either original sin or original ac-cumulation is both excessively and insufficiently historical. It is exces-sively historical because it situates the subject in a remote past, discon-nected from contemporary society. It is insufficiently historical because it relies on a mythical treatment of the past. Etienne Balibar’s (1988, 49) expression, ‘‘ahistorical historicism, or the historicity without history in
  • 35. 26 Marx’s thought,’’ is an appropriate characterization of this part of Marx’s work. To underscore his distance from Smith, Marx prefixed the pejorative ‘‘so-called’’ to the title of the final part of the first volume of Capital, which he devoted to the study of primitive accumulation. Marx, in es-sence, dismissed Smith’s mythical ‘‘previous’’ accumulation, in order to call attention to the actual historical experience. In contrast to the ‘‘so-called’’ primitive accumulation, Marx analyzed in detail the brutality of the actual historical experience of separating people from their means of production in an effort to lay bare the origin of the capitalist system. The Historical Basis of Primitive Accumulation The contrast between Smith’s scanty treatment of previous accumulation and Marx’s extensive documentation of the subject is striking. Marx’s (1977, 915) survey of primitive accumulation carries us through a several-centuries- long process, in which a small group of people brutally expropri-ated the means of production from the people of precapitalist society around the globe: The discovery of gold and silver in America, the extirpation, enslave-ment and entombment in mines of the indigenous population of that continent, the beginnings of the conquest and plunder of India, and the conversion of Africa into a preserve for the commercial hunting of blackskins, are all things which characterize the dawn of the era of capitalist production. These idyllic proceedings are the chief mo-ments of primitive accumulation. Marx did not limit his interpretation of primitive accumulation to iso-lated pockets of the world. The fruits of primitive accumulation are fun-gible. For example, he insisted that ‘‘a great deal of capital, which appears today in the United States without any birth-certificate, was yesterday, in England, the capitalized blood of children’’ (ibid., 920). According to Smith, economic development progressed through the voluntary acts of the participants. Marx (ibid., 926), in contrast, believed that ‘‘capital comes dripping from head to toe, from every pore, with blood and dirt.’’ Workers were ‘‘tortured by grotesquely terroristic laws into accepting the discipline necessary for the system of wage-labour’’ (ibid., 899). Where Smith scrupulously avoided any analysis of social relations, Marx produced an elaborate study of the connection between the develop-ment of capitalistic social relations and so-called primitive accumulation. In later years, Marx displayed an impatience with those who failed to
  • 36. theory of primitive accumulation 27 ground their treatment of primitive accumulation in concrete historical analysis. For example, he chastised Nikolai Mikhailovsky’s suprahis-torical presentation of primitive accumulation, in which the latter me-chanically extrapolated Russia’s future from Marx’s analysis of the Euro-pean experience of primitive accumulation (letter to the editorial board of Otechestvenniye Zapitski, November 1877, in Marx and Engels 1975, 291–94). Granted that primitive accumulation is a historical process rather than a mythical event, a further question arises: Why does this process, or at least most accounts of Marx’s treatment of it, seem to stop so abruptly with the establishment of a capitalist society? Marx himself offered few examples of primitive accumulation that occurred in the nineteenth cen-tury outside of colonial lands. In his letter to Otechestvenniye Zapitski, Marx seemed to take an al-most Smithian position, diminishing the importance of primitive accu-mulation by relegating it to a distant past. Marx even denigrated his chap-ter in Capital on primitive accumulation as ‘‘this historical sketch,’’ insisting that it ‘‘does not claim to do more than trace the path by which in Western Europe, the capitalist economy emerged from the womb of the feudal economic system. It therefore describes the historical process which by divorcing workers from their means of production converts them into wage workers’’ (ibid., 293). We must read this letter in its politi-cal context. Marx was upset that Mikhailovsky was attempting to use the chapter on primitive accumulation to convey the impression that Russia’s future would be mechanically determined by the ‘‘inexorable laws’’ of capitalism (ibid.). Marx was certain that, although the nature of capital might be unchanged, the specifics of Russian and western European devel-opment would be quite different. Consequently, he wanted to point out to Mikhailovsky the mistake of thinking that one could mechanically ‘‘pre-dict’’ the Russian outcome on the basis of western European experiences. At times, Marx did propose a theoretical stance that would seem to confine the importance of primitive accumulation to the historical past. Lucio Colletti (1979, 130) singles out the following extended passage from the Grundrisse: The conditions which form its [capital’s] point of departure in pro-duction— the condition that the capitalist, in order to posit himself as capital, must bring values into circulation which he created with his own labour—or by some other means, excepting only already avail-able, previous wage labour—belongs among the antediluvian condi-tions of capital, belongs to its historic presuppositions, which, pre-
  • 37. 28 cisely as such historic presuppositions, are past and gone, and hence belong to the history of its formation, but in no way to its contempo-rary history, i.e., not to the real system of the mode of production ruled by it. While e.g., the flight of serfs to the cities is one of the historic conditions and presuppositions of urbanism, it is not a condi-tion, not a moment of the reality of developed cities but belongs rather to their past presuppositions, to the presuppositions of their becoming which are suspended in their being. The conditions and presuppositions of the becoming, or the arising, of capital presuppose precisely that it is not yet in being but merely in becoming; they therefore disappear as real capital arises, capital which itself, on the basis of its own reality, posits the conditions for its realization. (Marx 1974, 459–60) In Capital, the same idea appears with a similar wording, except for the elimination of some of the more baroque Hegelesque terminology (Marx 1977, 775). Taken very simply, Marx seems to have been suggesting that the initial separation of workers from the means of production was a nec-essary historical event for the establishment of capitalism. In short, prim-itive accumulation was an essential component of what Engels (1894, 217) called the ‘‘great division of labor between the masses discharging simple manual labour and the few privileged persons directing labour,’’ but it was irrelevant to the ongoing process of capitalism. In Capital, Marx also generally appears to restrict the action of primitive accumula-tion to a short period in which traditional economies converted to capital-ism. As he wrote in Capital: ‘‘The different moments of primitive ac-cumulation can be assigned in particular to Spain, Portugal, Holland, France and England, in more or less chronological order. These different moments are systematically combined together at the end of the seven-teenth century in England’’ (Marx 1977, 915). Was Smith then correct after all in relegating primitive accumulation to the past—at least in the societies of advanced capitalism? We will see that the answer is an emphatic no. The Coexistence of Primitive and Capitalist Accumulation Despite Marx’s words to the contrary, the overall presentation of the first volume of Capital suggests that he rejected Smith’s approach of assigning primitive accumulation to a distant past. Indeed, the material in his part 8, ‘‘The So-Called Primitive Accumulation,’’ does not appear to be quali-
  • 38. theory of primitive accumulation 29 tatively different from what is found in the previous chapter, ‘‘The Gen-eral Theory of Capitalist Accumulation.’’ When Marx’s study of primitive accumulation finally reached the sub-ject of Edward Gibbon Wakefield, Marx did not qualify his appreciation of the father of modern colonial theory by limiting its relevance to an earlier England. Instead, he insisted that Wakefield offered significant insights into the England where Marx lived and worked (Marx 1977, 940; see also Marx 1853, 498). Read in this light, Marx’s letter to Mikhailovsky is also consistent with the idea that the importance of primitive accumulation was not what it taught about backward societies, but about the most advanced ones. In spite of the presumptions of some authors to prove otherwise (see, for example, Foster-Carter 1978, esp. 229), Marx (1976, 400n) himself, refer-ring to the institutions of Mexico, contended that the ‘‘nature of capital remains the same in its developed as in its undeveloped forms.’’ Even so, the presentation in Capital still does suggest a temporal cleav-age between the initial moment of primitive accumulation, when capital-ists accumulated by virtue of direct force, and the era of capitalist ac-cumulation, when capitalists accumulated surplus value in the market. This dichotomy might appeal to our common sense; still, it is itself rather ahistorical. In conclusion, at some times, Marx’s analysis of primitive accumula-tion sometimes seems to be a process that ceased with the establishment of capitalism. At other times, it seems to be more of an ongoing process. What then is the source of this confusion? The Primacy of Capitalist Accumulation in Capital Why was Marx not more explicit about the continuity of primitive ac-cumulation? To answer this question, recall the purpose of Marx’s ex-position of primitive accumulation. On a theoretical level, Marx was at-tempting to debunk Smith’s theology of previous accumulation, which suggested that capitalists’ commanding position was due to their past savings. In the process, he was attempting to lay bare the historical origins of market relations. He intended this historical analysis to refute the con-tention of classical political economy that markets supposedly work fairly because invisible hands somehow intelligently guide the world to-ward inevitable prosperity and even a higher level of culture. Marx’s depiction of primitive accumulation conveyed an overriding
  • 39. 30 sense of the unfairness of that altogether brutal experience. Yet, this por-trayal stood in contradiction to the main thrust of Capital. After all, Marx’s primary message was that the seemingly fair and objective rule of capital necessarily leads to exploitation. Although Marx accepted that markets were progressive in the long run, insofar as they prepared the ground for socialism, he was convinced that allegedly impartial market forces produced more cruelty than the crude and arbitrary methods of primitive accumulation. To emphasize primi-tive accumulation would have undermined Marx’s critique of capitalism. Marx would not have wished his readers to believe that measures to eliminate ‘‘unjust’’ instances of primitive accumulation might suffice to bring about a good society. To have stressed the continuing influence of primitive accumulation would have risked throwing readers off track. Certainly, Marx did not want his readers to conclude that the ills of so-ciety resulted from unjust actions that were unrelated to the essence of a market society. On the contrary, Marx insisted that the law of supply and demand, not primitive accumulation, was responsible for the better part of the horrible conditions that the working class experienced. As a result, he subordi-nated his insights about primitive accumulation to a more telling critique of capitalism; namely, that, once capitalism had taken hold, capitalists learned that purely market pressures were more effective in exploiting labor than the brutal act of primitive accumulation. In this sense, Marx’s relegation of primitive accumulation to the historical past made sense. By calling attention to the consequences of the market’s unique logic, he was reinforcing his basic contention that piecemeal reforms would be inade-quate. In this vein, Marx (1977, 899–900) wrote: It is not enough that the conditions of labour are concentrated at one pole of society in the shape of capital, while at the other pole are grouped masses of men who have nothing to sell but their labour-power. Nor is it enough that they are compelled to sell themselves voluntarily. The advance of capitalist production develops a working class which by education, tradition and habit looks upon the require-ments of that mode of production as self-evident natural laws. The organization of the capitalist process of production, once it is fully developed, breaks down all resistance. The constant generation of a relative surplus population keeps the law of the supply and demand of labour, and therefore wages, within narrow limits which correspond to capital’s valorization requirements. The silent compulsion of eco-nomic relations sets the seal on the domination of the capitalist over
  • 40. theory of primitive accumulation 31 the worker. Direct extra-economic force is still of course used, but only in exceptional cases. In the ordinary run of things, the worker can be left to the ‘‘natural laws of production,’’ i.e., it is possible to rely on his dependence on capital, which springs from the conditions of production themselves, and is guaranteed in perpetuity by them. It is otherwise during the historical genesis of capitalist production. The rising bourgeoisie needs the power of the state, and uses it to ‘‘regulate’’ wages, i.e., to force them into the limits suitable to make a profit, to lengthen the working day, and to keep the worker himself at his normal level of dependence. This is an essential aspect of so-called primitive accumulation. (emphasis added) The force of the ‘‘silent compulsion’’ is more effective than the crude methods of primitive accumulation: the pretensions of capital in its embryonic state, in its state of becom-ing, when it cannot yet use the sheer force of economic relations to secure its right to absorb a sufficient quantity of surplus labour, but must be aided by the power of the state. . . . Centuries are required before the ‘‘free’’ worker, owing to the greater development of the capitalist mode of production, makes a voluntary agreement, i.e. is compelled by social conditions to sell the whole of his active life. (ibid., 382) Again, in describing the centralization of capital, Marx (1981, 3:609) noted how effectively market forces had replaced primitive accumula-tion: ‘‘Profits and losses that result from fluctuations in the price of . . . ownership titles, and also their centralization in the hands of railway magnates . . . now appears in place of labour as the original source of capital ownership, as well as taking the place of brute force.’’ Marx (ibid., 354) also made the connection between market forces and primitive accumulation when he discussed the tendency of the rate of profit to fall: ‘‘This is simply the divorce of the conditions of labour from the producers raised to a higher power. . . . It is in fact this divorce between the conditions of labour on the one hand and the producers on the other that forms the concept of capital, as this arises with primitive accumulation.’’ Here, Marx (ibid., 348) referred to ‘‘expropriating the final residue of direct producers who still have something left to expropriate.’’ This note is important because it indicates that Marx realized the ongoing nature of primitive accumulation, although as I argue he wanted to suppress its importance to highlight the ‘‘silent compulsion’’ of the market.
  • 41. 32 Judging by his words, Marx was also careful to avoid confusing such ‘‘financial primitive accumulation’’ with primitive accumulation proper. Marx (ibid., 570–71) noted: Conceptions that still had a certain meaning at a less developed state of capitalist production now become completely meaningless. Success and failure lead in both cases to the centralization of capitals and hence to expropriation on the most enormous scale. Expropriation now ex-tends here from the immediate producers to the small and medium capitalists themselves. Expropriation is the starting-point of the capi-talist mode of production, whose goal it is to carry it through to com-pletion, and even in the last instance to expropriate all individuals. No matter what his strategic reasons, Marx seems to have downplayed the role of primitive accumulation in order to focus on modern capitalist accumulation. Although he succeeded in that respect, this ahistoricity obscures our understanding of the early process of capitalist development. Specifically, by relegating primitive accumulation to the precapitalistic past, we lose sight of the twofold time dimension of primitive accumula-tion. First, as we shall emphasize later, the separation of people from their traditional means of production occurred over time as capital gradually required additional workers to join the labor force. Second, the process of primitive accumulation was a matter of degree. All-out primitive accu-mulation would not be in the best interests of capital. Instead, capital would manipulate the extent to which workers relied on self-provisioning in order to maximize its advantage. The Theoretical Context of Primitive Accumulation Marx’s presentation of primitive accumulation had the unfortunate con-sequence of divorcing the process from political economy. Peter Cressey and John MacInnes (1980, 18) made a similar point, noting: Marx argues that primitive accumulation was a process irreducible to the categories of political economy and explicable only in terms of struggle and ultimately force. At first sight it appears that historical analysis of primitive accumulation explains the initial ‘‘formal’’ sub-ordination of labour, in that the workplace capitalist simply appropri-ates (formally) a production process bequeathed by pre-capitalist so-ciety. [Ultimately, the] . . . concept of the formal subordination of labour, like Smith’s concept of previous accumulation, is not derived from history but from political economy.
  • 42. theory of primitive accumulation 33 Etienne Balibar’s analysis of Marx’s use of the term proletariat rein-forces our case for looking at the concept of primitive accumulation more closely. Balibar noted that Marx’s Capital rarely mentions the proletariat, but generally refers to the working class. In the first edition of the first volume, the term only appears in the dedication to Wilhelm Wolff and the two final sections on ‘‘The General Law of Capitalist Accumulation,’’ which concerned the law of population and the process of primitive ac-cumulation. On only one occasion do the proletarian and the capitalist confront each other directly in Capital. Balibar (1988, 19–20) concluded, ‘‘These pas-sages have in common their insistence upon the insecurity characteristic of the proletarian condition.’’ On a more general level, Balibar claimed that Marx’s use of the term proletariat seemed to be intended to infer that the condition of the working class was unstable, that it perpetuated the violence associated with the transition to capitalism, and that the situa-tion is historically untenable (ibid.). Following Balibar, we might interpret the notion of the proletariat as an abstract concept to describe the situation of people displaced from their traditional livelihoods by primitive accumulation. The concept of the proletariat abstracts from any of the specific conditions that affected these people, with the exception of their lack of control over the means of production, which sets the stage for the introduction of capitalist forces. Both Balibar’s reading of the use of the word proletariat and my own un-derstanding of Marx’s treatment of primitive accumulation suggest that Marx obscured the phenomena of primitive accumulation in order to fo-cus attention on the working of markets. By relegating the relevance of primitive accumulation to the historical process of proletarianization, we ignore the centrality of the ongoing process of primitive accumulation in shaping the conditions of the working class. I am convinced that we can benefit from a closer look at primitive accumulation, without losing sight of Marx’s invaluable analysis of mar-ket forces. In the process of investigating this subject, I will attempt to reintegrate primitive accumulation into the structure of political econ-omy, especially classical political economy. Acknowledging the Scope of Primitive Accumulation In reality, primitive accumulation did not suddenly occur just before the transition to European capitalism. Nor was it confined to the countryside of western Europe. Primitive accumulation may be seen as occurring even well before the age of capitalism.
  • 43. 34 For example, land was already scarce for the majority of people during the Middle Ages. According to M. M. Postan (1966, 622–23): about one-half of the peasant population had holdings insufficient to maintain their families at the bare minimum of subsistence. This meant that in order to subsist the average smallholder had to supple-ment his income in other ways. . . . [I]ndustrial and trading activities might sustain entire villages of smallholders. . . . Most of the oppor-tunities for employment must, however, have lain in agriculture. . . . [I]n almost all the villages some villagers worked for others. Other factors reinforced the pressure of land scarcity. For example, the twelfth-century Danes levied tribute from the British. This extortion was not primitive accumulation, since it was not intended to coerce workers into the labor market and foster market relations. However, it did impel Britain to monetize its economy in a way that bore some resemblance to primitive accumulation (Sohn-Rethel 1978, 107). Similarly, medieval usury, often simply dismissed as a parasitic intrusion into the economy, prodded the economy to advance (Marx 1967, 3:596–97). The process of primitive accumulation does not merely extend back-ward before the epoch of classical political economy. It lasted well into more modern times. In England, as well as in the other countries of ad-vanced capitalism, the conversion of small-scale farmers into proletarians continued throughout the nineteenth century and into the twentieth. This transformation involved more than the ‘‘silent compulsion’’ of mar-ket forces. In the case of the destruction of small-scale farming in the United States, the federal government was central in developing the trans-portation and research systems that tipped the balance in favor of large-scale agriculture (see Perelman 1977; 1991b). The continuity of primitive accumulation stands in stark contrast to its usual image as the one-time destruction of the peasant economy, the immediate effect of which was to create a society with capitalists on the one side and workers on the other. This perception is understandable, but misleading. Indeed, on the eve of capitalism, the majority of people were peasants or at least had some connection to farming. Moreover, primitive accumulation was not limited to agriculture. It extended across many, if not all, sectors of the economy (Berg 1986, 70). It took place in the city as well as the countryside. After all, urban people still provide for themselves directly in a multitude of ways other than the growing of food. Depriving people of these means of provision forces a greater dependence on the market just as surely as restricting their access to the means of food production.
  • 44. theory of primitive accumulation 35 Take a relatively modern example. Packing people into crowded urban quarters left little space for doing laundry. As a result, people become de-pendent on commercial laundries. After World War II, the ability of the typical U.S. family to produce for its own needs continued to diminish, despite the widespread availability of household appliances, such as wash-ing machines, that should have made many types of self-provisioning easier. Likewise, Paul Sweezy (1980, 13) interprets Japan’s huge enter-tainment sector as a partial result of people being forced to live in such cramped quarters that they are unable to socialize in their homes. The need to purchase such services compels people to sell more labor. We see the impact of this pressure reflected in the recent increase in the number of women in the labor force. Gabriel Kolko (1978, 267) calculates that the share of life years available for wage labor for the average adult has expanded from 39 percent in 1900 to 44.4 percent in 1970, despite rising education levels, better child labor laws, and a shorter workweek. Since that time, work has demanded a rapidly escalating share of the typical family’s time. Juliet Schor (1991, 29) estimates that the average person worked 163 more hours in 1987 than in 1969. This process can feed on itself. Because people have to earn more wages to compensate for the increased difficulty of providing for certain of their own needs, they have less time to do other sorts of work on their own, inducing families to transfer still more labor from the household to the commercial sector. Child care centers are an obvious outcome of this process. In addition, the fast-food industry is predicated on the difficulty of working a job and performing a multitude of other household chores in the same day. The foregoing discussion suggests that wage labor and nonwage labor are, indeed, inextricably linked. The analysis of one category necessitates consideration of the other. As we shall see later, the concept of the social division of labor enhances our understanding of this mutual interplay of wage and nonwage labor. For now, we need only keep in mind our modern-day examples of goods and services that were once produced within the household, which became commodities sold by commercial firms. This new arrangement is related, at least in part, to the pattern of own-ership of the means of creating these goods and services in the household. Formally, the lack of ownership of a workspace for doing laundry is no different from the lack of ownership of the parcel of land on which a household once grew its own food. In either case, the denial of ownership to a particular means of production creates a change in the mix of wage and nonwage labor.
  • 45. 36 Ignoring Balibar’s warning about the careless use of the word prole-tariat, we could interpret this restructuring of the life of a modern house-hold as a contemporary variant of the process of primitive accumula-tion, whereby the mass of people working for wages has increased. In this sense, the concept of primitive accumulation is closely bound up with that of the social division of labor. Classical Political Economy and Primitive Accumulation Even though Marx muted his analysis of the continuing nature of primi-tive accumulation, he was abundantly clear that primitive accumulation resulted in momentous changes in social relations that were central to creation of the capitalist system (see Dobb 1963, 267). Marx’s lesson was lost on most later economists. They were content to treat the Industrial Revolution as if it were merely the introduction of superior methods of production. In contrast, the classical political economists saw primitive accumulation as a means of radically reordering the social division of labor, which they recognized as a precondition of the creation of a pro-letariat. Along this line, Marx (1977, 764), in writing about primitive accumulation, proposed the formula: ‘‘Accumulation of capital is . . . multiplication of the proletariat.’’ We shall see that we can express the classical theory of primitive accu-mulation as a model that resembles a crude proto-Marxian model stripped of the dialectic. In analyzing this model, keep in mind that Marx began by taking the categories of classical political economy as he found them (see Perelman 1987, chap. 4). By investigating them more fully, he was able to invest the typically static, undialectical categories of classical political economy with a dynamic, dialectical quality. We will try to follow the same tradition in our study of the classical the-ory of primitive accumulation. The classical political economists make this task considerably easier. Compared to their analysis of the categories of profits or wages, they adopted a far more dynamic, almost dialectical approach to their analysis of primitive accumulation. Carrying out such an analysis of the classical theory of primitive accumulation has a twofold importance: it reveals a side of classical political economy that previously has gone unnoticed; and it reminds us that primitive accumulation is an ongoing process. Even modern commentaries on primitive accumulation do not do the topic full justice. Like Marx, most contemporary references relegate the concept to a distant past, except perhaps in the case of the proletarianiza-tion that the less-developed countries of Africa, Asia, and Latin America
  • 46. theory of primitive accumulation 37 are experiencing. Consequently, the separation of workers from their means of production is implicitly assumed to be a static, once-and-for-all event. Since the classical political economists grounded their discussions of primitive accumulation in a dynamic framework, scrutiny of the classics has more to offer than more modern commentaries on the subject of primitive accumulation. To some extent, the deficiencies of these com-mentaries may be understandable. Marx himself often wrote about primi-tive accumulation with an air of finality and possibly even with a touch of Smithian mythology. For example, the first mention of the concept of primitive accumulation in Capital appears in chapter 23, ‘‘Simple Repro-duction’’ (Marx 1977, 714). At this point, Marx had to address the ques-tion: How does the system come to be structured into capital and labor? He responded: ‘‘From our present standpoint it therefore seems likely that the capitalist, once upon a time, became possessed of money by some form of primitive accumulation’’ (Marx 1977, 714). Marx’s uncharacteristic ‘‘once upon a time,’’ which sounded as unreal as Smith’s mythical history, was obviously provisional. The words ‘‘from our present viewpoint’’ also suggest that a more thorough analysis would be forthcoming. For reasons already discussed, Marx never provided that thoroughgoing critique. Instead, we find only history. Yet primitive accumulation remains a key concept for understanding capitalism—and not just the particular phase of capitalism associated with the transition from feudalism, but capitalism proper. Primitive ac-cumulation is a process that continues to this day. Thus, we must carry the history of primitive accumulation through the epoch of classical po-litical economy by connecting this concept with Marx’s notion of the social division of labor.