SlideShare ist ein Scribd-Unternehmen logo
1 von 23
Downloaden Sie, um offline zu lesen
1
With reference to academic opinion and relevant case law of the European Court of Human
Rights, critically assess the position of the European Court of Human Rights relating to
euthanasia and assisted suicide.
Student Number: 650042321
Module: The European Convention on Human Rights
Word Count: 3824 (Within the 5% Limit)
2
With reference to academic opinion and relevant case law of the European Court of Human Rights,
critically assess the position of the European Court of Human Rights relating to euthanasia and
assisted suicide.
Dr Puppinck and Dr Houge observe that: “[T]he case law of the European Court of Human Rights
[ECtHR, the Court] clearly leads to the acceptance of a right to assisted suicide [A.S].”1
However,
Western States have traditionally disapproved of the practice2
and implemented legislation whereby
the acts are criminal offences;3
legally condoned A.S is a recent innovation of Western society.4
Dupre notes: “The time and timing of death have been profoundly transformed […] prompting
discussion on euthanasia and assisted suicide.”5
Regarding the Court’s position on A.S and
euthanasia, three observations have been deduced. Firstly, Article.2 of the European Convention on
Human Rights (ECHR, the Convention),6
the ‘Right to Life,’ does not encompass a ‘Right to Die’.7
Secondly, within Article.8, the ‘Right to Respect for Private Life’, the Court has established a ‘right to
A.S’.8
Thirdly, the Court affords member States a wide margin of appreciation (MofA) when
restricting the ‘right to A.S’ within their jurisdiction.9
In considering these aspects, the Court’s
position regarding a ‘right to A.S’ is held to be unsound. However, it is first appropriate to distinguish
between A.S and euthanasia.
1
Gregor Puppinck and Claire de La Houge, “The ‘Right’ to Assisted Suicide in the case law of the European
Court of Human Rights’ (2014) Vol.18(7-8) The International Journal of Human Rights, 735, 741
2
Washington v Glucksberg, 521 U.S. 702, 710-12 (1997); Emily Wada, “A Pretty Picture: The Margin of
Appreciation and the Right to Assisted Suicide” (2005) Vol.27 Loyola of Los Angeles International and
Comparative Law Review 275
3
Rustin-Petru CIASC, “Euthanasia, National and International Perspectives” (2013) Vol.9(2) Acta Universitatis
Danubius Juridica, 41
4
Wada (n-2) 283
5
Catherine Dupre, The Age of Dignity, (Hart Publishing, 2015) 146
6
Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms 1950
7
Wada (n-2) 275; JMT Labuschagne, “The European Court of Human Rights and the right to assisted suicide in
international human rights law.” (2004) Vol.17(1) South African Journal of Criminal Justice, 87; Puppinck (n-1)
735
8
Puppinck (n-1) 741
9
Wada (n-3) 275; Carmen Draghici, “The blanket ban on assisted suicide: between moral paternalism and
utilitarian justice” (2015) European Human Right Law Review 286
3
Defining Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia
A.S involves providing the applicant with the means of committing suicide however, the applicant
performs the final, death inducing, act.10
Conversely, in voluntary euthanasia11
the assisting person
commits the final act at the victim’s request.12
Despite this distinction, the ECtHR exclusively
mentions A.S even in situations where the candidate to suicide is unable to execute the lethal act
themselves13
possibly because the two acts are not always easily distinguishable.14
Notably, in Pretty
v United Kingdom,15
despite the applicant being completely paralysed and unable to perform the
lethal act herself, the Court exclusively referred to A.S. Concurrently, at a domestic level, irrespective
of whether States permit16
or ban17
euthanasia, the action also includes A.S.18
Indeed, only
Switzerland applies a distinction in law.19
Accordingly, the two practised are referred to
interchangeably.
10
For instance, self-administering a lethal substance.
Puppinck (n-1) 739; Amelia Mihaela Diaconescu, “Euthanasia” (2012) Vol4(2) Contemporary Readings in Law
and Social Justice, 474
11
Compared to non-voluntary and involuntary euthanasia. Non-voluntary euthanasia involves an individual
ending the life of a person who cannot choose by himself between living and dying. Involuntary euthanasia is
performed on a person who is able to provide informed consent, but does not, because he was not asked. For
instance, causing death by administering an ever increasing dose by the doctor who does not intend to cause
death, but to alleviate pain, but which could produce (involuntarily) the patient’s death. Diaconescu (n-10) 474
J. Lucy Pridgeon, “Euthanasia Legislation in the European Union: is a Universal Law Possible?” (2006) Vol.2(1)
Hans Law Review, 45,46
Gordijn, Bert, Ben Crul and Zbigniew Zylicz ‘Euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide’, in Ten Have, H. and
Clark, D (eds.), The Ethics of Palliative Care: European perspectives (Buckingham, Open University Press,
2002), 182.
12
Puppinck (n-1) 739
13
ibid 741
14
ibid 750
15
Pretty v United Kingdom (GC), Ap.234/02, 29th
April 2002
16
E.g. Belgium. See: Pridgeon (n-11) 45
17
E.g. Germany. See: ibid
18
Puppinck (n-1) 739
19
ibid
4
The ‘Right to Die’: Considering Article.2 and Article.8
In Pretty20
the Court held that the ‘right to life’ does not encompass a negative aspect; a right to
die.21
However, the ruling fails to consider the ‘quality of life.’22
Justice Sachs perceives that: “The
right to life without a basis quality of life […] is senseless.”23
Accordingly, the Court failed to properly
address the interaction between the ‘right to life’ and the “claim to the basic quality of life.”24
Labuschagne notes:
“The untenable and vicious effect of these decisions, whatever the technical and
interpretational arguments may be, is that a cruel and senseless dying process, which forms
part of the living process since the individual is still alive when dying, is sanctioned by legal
rules.”25
However, Article.2 is:
“[A] provision which not only safeguards the right to life but sets out the circumstances when
the deprivation of life may be justified. Article 2 ranks as one of the most fundamental
provisions of the convention...”26
Therefore, the Court’s position is commendable for upholding the ‘sanctity of life.’27
Furthermore,
Article.2 obliges the State to not only refrain from intentionally and unlawfully depriving its subjects
of life, but to also take appropriate steps to safeguard their lives.28
States have notably accomplished
20
Pretty v United Kingdom (GC), Ap.234/02, 29th
April 2002
21
ibid Para 39
22
Labuschagne (n-7) 93
23
Justice Sachs in S v Makwanyane and Another (CCT3/94) [1995] ZACC 3 Para 353
24
Labuschagne(n-7) 90-91
25
ibid 93
26
McCann v UK (1995) 21 EHRR 97 Para 146-7. Author emphasis added
27
See Puppinck (n-1)
28
LCB v UK [1998] ECHR 108
See also Osman v UK [1998] ECHR 101 and Keenan v UK 2001 Ap.27229/95, 3rd
April 2001 Para 91-92
5
this by “prohibiting murder and [A.S].”29
Critically, Article.2(2) exhaustively lists the exceptions to the
right to life that are tolerated30
and Article.15(2) further states that:
“No derogation from Article 2, except in respect of deaths resulting from lawful acts of war,
[…] shall be made under this provision.”
Significantly, neither Article.2(2) or Article.15(5) provides that the consent of an individual or their
quality of life are justifications for derogation.31
Accordingly, the Court is correct in its assertion that:
“[Article.2] is unconcerned with issues to do with the quality of living [….] Article 2 cannot,
[…], be interpreted as conferring […] a right to die...”32
However, the Court has expanded the scope of Article.8 and obliged States to adopt a liberal
position on A.S.33
Accordingly, attention now turns towards its development and interaction with
Article.2.
As Houge observes:
“The recognition of the right to A.S was obtained [not by] the substantive right to [A.S] but
the procedural right to know if one is able to legally exercise this right.”34
In Hass v Switzerland,35
Switzerland was obliged “to establish a procedure capable of ensuring that a
decision to end one’s life does indeed correspond with the free wish of the individual concerned.”36
Subsequently in Koch v Germany,37
the State was obliged to establish an effective framework to rule
29
Puppinck (n-1) 757
30
Article.2(2) “Deprivation of life shall not be regarded as inflicted in contravention of this article when it
results from the use of force which is no more than absolutely necessary:
(a) in defence of any person from unlawful violence;
(b) in order to effect a lawful arrest or to prevent escape of a person lawfully detained;
(c) in action lawfully taken for the purpose of quelling a riot or insurrection”
31
ibid
32
Pretty v United Kingdom (n-15) Para 39
33
Puppinck (n-1) 750
34
ibid. Author emphasis added.
35
Haas v Switzerland, Ap.31322/07, 20 January 2011
36
ibid Para 58
37
Koch v Germany, Ap.497/09, 19 July 2012
6
on the merits of decisions refusing A.S.38
Finally, in Gross v Switzerland,39
Switzerland was held to be
obligated to establish a legal framework permitting individuals to claim their right to A.S.40
However,
the legal basis of these obligations is unclear.41
A Conventional procedural obligation is an accessory of a principal material right.42
Therefore, the
Court’s assertions imply the existence of a material right. Such an obligation derives either directly
from the Convention, an autonomous Convectional obligation, and/or domestic law (provided it
enters the scope of the Convention).43
As there is no domestic ‘right to A.S’ in the States concerned,
one can conclude that the procedural obligation derives from an autonomous Convention right.
However, the Court fails to affirm the existence of this right in either Haas, Koch or Gross.44
Rather, it
references Schneider v Germany45
stressing that:
“[Article.8] may encompass a right to judicial review even in a case which the substantive
right in question had yet to be established.”46
However, in Schneider a relevant domestic right already existed while in Koch the legislator had
intentionally omitted the right.47
Therefore, the Court’s reference is inappropriate.48
The Court has
failed to dispel the doubt as to the actual existence of an independent Convention right. Therefore,
“the legal basis [of the] right to A.S is dubious.”49
Accordingly, the Court’s reasoning in finding a right
to A.S under Article.8 needs to be addressed.
38
ibid Para 71
39
Gross v Switzerland, Ap. 67810/10, 14 May 2013
40
Puppinck (n-1) 751
41
ibid
42
Tysiac v Poland Ap.5410/03 20 March 2007 para 113; A procedural right is not an independent right but
rather a right requiring a State to guarantee the means of access to enjoyment of a right.
43
Puppinck (n-1) 751
44
ibid
45
Schneider v Germany Ap.17080/07 15 September 2011 Para 100. The Court noted the possibility of
establishing a procedural obligation without first having recognised a principal material right
46
Koch v Germany (n-37) Para 53
47
Puppinck (n-1) 753
48
ibid
49
ibid 758 “the legal basis on which the Court has [built] the right to [A.S] is dubious.”
7
Article.8 and a ‘Right to Assisted Suicide’
Since Pretty the Court has increasingly ignored Article.2.50
In Hass, it was considered only in terms of
its procedural obligation to verify the subjective will of the suicide candidate51
to prevent:
“an individual from taking his or her own life if the decision has not been taken freely and
with the full understanding of what is involved”52
[ensuring the] “decision [..]correspond[s]
with the free wish of the individual concerned.”53
Thus, the obligation to ‘guarantee and respect the right to life’ under Article.2 is not realised by the
‘mere’ respect of life but by respecting the autonomy of the individual. Moreover, in Koch and Gross,
whilst the Court recalled the sacredness of life it was presented in a negative formulation, the
‘quality of life’ taking ‘priority’:
“Without in any way negating the principle of the sanctity of life protected under the
Convention, the Court Considers that it is under Article.8 that notions of the quality of life
take on significance.”54
Hence, the principal consideration regarding A.S is the subjective right to a ‘quality of life’ rather
than the objective ‘right to life’; the autonomy of an individual being both the basis and the
condition of the ‘right to A.S’.55
Critically, the objectivity of Article.2 has been absorbed into the
subjectivity of Article.856
thereby diminishing the assertion that Article.2 “constitutes an inalienable
attribute of the human person and that is form[s] the supreme value in the scale of human rights.” 57
50
ibid 754
51
ibid 750-53
52
Haas v Switzerland (n-35) Para 54
53
ibid Para 58
54
Pretty v United Kingdom (n-15) Para 65; See Koch v Germany (n-37) Para 51 and Gross v Switzerland (n-39)
Para 58
55
See: Puppinck (n-1) 753-759
56
ibid 758
57
Pretty v United Kingdom (n-15) Para 65
8
The ‘supreme value’ is now personal autonomy. The Court has established this notion of ‘quality of
life’ on an individualistic conception of human dignity (H.D):58
“[I]n an era of growing medical sophistication, many people are concerned that they should
not be forced to linger on in old age or in states of advanced physical or mental decrepitude
which conflict with strongly held ideals of self and personal identity.” 59
Therefore, one’s autonomy is constrained if forced to live in a state that conflicts with one’s such
“ideals.”60
Accordingly, these ‘ideals’ are individualistic resulting in a subjective measurement of the
quality of life.61
Consequently, this concept of H.D is not inherent but self-determined.62
Therefore,
in Koch and Gross the invalidity of one applicant and the old age of the other was held to impeded
the quality of their lives. As Houge reasons: “their dignity as human beings could therefore occur
preferentially choosing to wave existence rather than suffer a decline. The value of life is thus bound
to its quality.”63
The shift from life to the ‘quality of life’, leads to the demands for self-determination
and finally to a right to the quality of death as falling within the Scope of Article.8.64
However, the
Court’s application of H.D and in particular a ‘subjective’ H.D is contestable.
Despite its notable presence “in terms of quantity and quality”65
and as a “foundation [in] the legal
reasoning of the Strasbourg Court in its rulings”66
the ECHR makes no reference to H.D.67
Accordingly, its use as an interpretive tool is questionable.68
58
Puppinck (n-1) 755
59
Gross v Switzerland (n-39) Para 58
60
Puppinck (n-1) 755
61
ibid
62
ibid
63
ibid
64
ibid
65
Dupre (n-5) 85
66
Jean Paul Costa, “Human Dignity in the Jurisprudence of the European Court of Human Rights” in
Christopher McCrudden (eds) Understanding Human Dignity (Oxford University Press) 393
67
Diaconescu, (n-10) 481; Costa (ibid) 393
68
Costa (n-66) 393
9
Given that the Convention is inspired by, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR),69
which
is founded on the “recognition of the inherent dignity of all members of the human family” and
speaks of the “inherent dignity of the person,”70
its absence is arguably the deliberate act of its
drafters to exclude it as an interpretative tool.71
Furthermore, Michael Rosen72
and John Harris73
have attacked the concept as “comprehensively vague”, with modern conceptions inheriting several
distinct strands of meaning74
thereby obscuring the Convention’s interpretation. McCrudden further
notes: “[F]or some, it is only a ‘smoke screen’ to hide the emptiness or disagreement on which human
rights are funded.”75
Accordingly, H.D should be excluded from the interpretation of the
Convention.76
However, in SW v U.K.77
the Court formulated its commitment to protecting H.D as being the
“essence” of the ECHR78
and has subsequently referred to its “inviolability” to give greater normative
strength to H.D over even Article.2.79
Furthermore, Daly considers the inherency of H.D within all
human rights,80
Costa submits that notions of H.D were in the drafters’ minds81
and Dupree applauds
how:
69
The Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR) is a declaration adopted by the United Nations General
Assembly on 10 December 1948; Puppinck (n-1) 755
70
Costa (n-66) 394
71
ibid 393
72
Michael Rosen, Dignity: Its History and Meaning (Harvard University Press 2012)
73
J.Harris, Is Cloning an Attack on Human Dignity? (Nature 1997); Harris, Clones, Genes and Immorality (Oxford
University Press 1998)
74
J.Harris, Clones, Genes and Immorality (Oxford University Press 1998) 31; David Albert Jones, “Is Dignity
Language Useful in Bioethical Discussion of Assisted Suicide and Abortion?” in Christopher McCrudden (eds)
Understanding Human Dignity (Oxford University Press) 525
75
Christopher McCrudden, “Human Dignity and Judicial Interpretation of Human Rights.” (2008) Vol.19(4) The
European Journal of International Law, 22
76
Costa, (n-66); Puppinck (n-1) 756-7
77
SW v The United Kingdom 1995 ECHR 52
78
SW v The United Kingdom (ibid) Para 101; See Dupre (n-5) 174
79
See Dupre (n-5) 174
80
Erin Daly, Dignity Rights: Courts, Constitutions and the Worth of the Human Person (University of
Pennsylvania Press, 2013); Dupre (n-5) 85: “[A]lmost every aspect of human interaction and identity [can] be, in
one way or another, translated and adjudicated in terms of human dignity.”
81
Costa (n-66) 394:“[E]specially because the very establishment of the Council of Europe in 1949 and the
elaboration of the Convention […] The founding fathers of the European system of protection of right and
freedoms shared the same philosophy as the authors of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights.”
10
“[R]eliance on human dignity makes discursive space to consider alternative and new ways of
interpreting the law, and […] therefore, provided judges with the key to unlock a difficult
situation and open un a new path in human rights protection.”82
Furthermore, Meyer asserts that the potential variations in meaning do not result in equivocation
but are “a family of concepts clustered around the practice of moral evaluation.”83
Moreover, Dupre
praises the concept’s flexibility and its use when resolving complex, present day situations:
“In practice, [H.D’s] transformative function arguably explains why it has been a key judicial
instrument for departing from established case law and precedent, opening up a new path in
an unchartered territory.” 84
Overall, reference to H.D has played an instrumental role in expanding the Convention’s scope of
protection.85
As Costa concludes, “the concept of human dignity in the Court’s jurisprudence
expresses a deliberate intention of building a bridge between the universal instruments and the silent
European text, filling the vacuum created by the authors of the Convention.”86
Therefore, H.D should
not be excluded from the Court’s interpretation of the Convention. The issue now lies in its
appropriate application.
According to Dwarkin: “[H.D] supposes that there are ways of treating a man that are inconsistent
with recognising him as a full member of the human community, and holds that such treatment is
profoundly unjust.”87
Regarding A.S:
82
Dupre (n-5) 159
83
M. Meyer, “The Simple Dignity of Sentient Life: Speciesism and Human Dignity” (2009) Vol.32(2) Journal of
Social Philosophy 223, 240.
84
Dupre (n-5) 271-2
85
See for example: SW v The United Kingdom (n-77); Keenen v UK [2001] ECHR 239; Rasnstev v Cyprus and the
Russian Federation App.25965/04 07 January 2010; Dordevic v Coratia [2012] ECHR 1640, Goodwin and I v UK
Ap. 28957/95 11 July 2002.
86
Costa (n-66) 401
87
Ronald Dwarkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Harvard University Press, 1978) 198
11
“[H.D] has been in these debates, prompting those who want to maintain a ‘natural timing’
of death and dying, and those who want to make use of their last opportunity to be free and
control their life by controlling their death too.”88
According to Diaconescu: “[H.D] is based on the human being’s right to dignity and the right and
respect for his or her autonomy, self-determination of the subject with regard to his or her own
body.”89
Therefore, in adopting a ‘subjective’ perception of H.D, the Court’s position can be praised
as liberating those who no longer wish to endure life:
“If a person [suffering from a terminal illness or extreme disability] does not have access to
assisted suicide, then he or she is forced to endure the indignity of what is considered a
subhuman condition of life”90
However, proponents of A.S have generally restricted their efforts to “those suffering from terminal
and/or disabling conditions.”91
Yet, in Gross the applicant’s old age, as opposed to invalidity in Koch,
was viewed as interfering with her ‘quality of life.’92
Accordingly, the Court’s use of an individualistic
perception of H.D is perhaps a step too far.93
Furthermore, the Court’s adoption of a subjective,
rather than inherent, notion of H.D is contestable. As noted by Gatterer, an ‘inherent’ dignity is not
subjective94
and therefore, the Court is not adhering to same dignity as envisioned in the UDHR and
which inspired the ECHR.95
Arguably:
88
Dupre (n-5) 146
89
Diaconescu (n-10) 477
90
David Albert Jones. “Is Dignity Language Useful in Bioethical Discussion of Assisted Suicide and Abortion?” in
Christopher McCrudden (eds) Understanding Human Dignity (Oxford University Press) 525, 530-31
91
ibid
92
See Puppinck (n-1)
93
However, see Ketreb v France Ap.38447/09 19th
July 2012 where the Court considered that being young and
healthy prevented Mr Ketreb’s desire to die from being accepted and instead reiterated the State’s obligation
to “take necessary measures to protect the lives of those within its jurisdiction.”
94
Edeltraud Gatterer, Doc. 8421, Protection of the human rights and dignity in the terminally ill and dying,
Report from Social, Health and Family Affairs Committee, 21/05/1999. This report led to the Parliamentary
Assembly of the Council of Europe Recommendation 1418 (1999) which affirmed that the right to life of the
sick and dying must be guaranteed even when they express the desire to die.
95
Puppinck (n-1)755
12
“in substituting the ‘inherent dignity’ for a relative dignity […] the Court radically modified
the ontological foundations of the Convention, that of universal to particular. The Court
removes from rights their objectivity by rendering them subjective, and therefore relevant to
their subject. [Therefore], the measure of human rights is no longer the human, but each
individual.”96
Furthermore, the Court’s position arguably fails to respect the dignity of each human life.97
This
‘Dignity as Life’ concept holds that killing contradicts the intrinsic dignity of human existence both in
respect of life itself and what life makes possible all individuals.98
Kant, for example, considers
suicide as the failure to respect the worth or dignity of human life in one’s own case.99
Accordingly,
the Court’s position directly contradicts these views. Additionally, disability rights movements
caution that:
“The desire for euthanasia is inseparable from the fear of dependence and loss of control, of
incontinence and dementia, in short, from the fear of disability. While this desire is expressed
as a wish ‘to die with dignity’, it implies that living in certain conditions is, per se,
indignity.”100
Therefore, the very act of judging a life with an impairment as being ‘undignified’ and therefore, “a
life unworthy to be lived”101
is not only discriminatory but humiliating towards those who live with
an impairment.102
Arguably, the Court’s position actually debases the very individuals it seeks to
liberate.
96
ibid 756
97
Jones (n-90) 529
98
ibid
99
Immanuel Kant, Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals (2ND
Revised Edition 1785, Translated by Mary J.
Gregor and Jens Timmermann, Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy, 2012) 54, 67; Jones. (n-90) 530
100
Jones. (n-90) 531; See organisations “Not Dead Yet” and “Not Dead Yet UK”, a national, grassroots disability
rights movement that opposes legalization of assisted suicide and euthanasia as deadly forms of
discrimination. <http://notdeadyet.org/about> accessed 17/04/2016
<http://notdeadyetuk.org/> accessed 17/04/2016
101
Jones (n-90) 538
102
ibid
13
Overall, whilst opinions on the Court’s position are divided, “[H.D’s] role is […] to guide judges as
they venture into new territories.”103
Society’s understanding of death and dignity is evolving. As
such, the application of H.D within the Convention must evolve too, even if contentious.104
Nevertheless, the Court’s assertion of a ‘right to A.S’ is confronted with a further hurdle.
Article.2 does not contain a negative right to die and its exceptions interpreted restrictively.
Furthermore, Article.17 states that:
“Nothing in this Convention may be interpreted as implying […] any right to engage in any
activity or perform any act aimed at the destruction on any of the rights and freedoms set
forth herein or at their limitation to a greater extent than is provided for in the Convention.”
Therefore, Aritcle.8 cannot be interpreted as implying a new right that aims at the destruction of
Article.2.105
Ultimately, even when jurisprudentially absorbed in Article.8 the wording of Article.2
remains “no one shall be deprived on their life intentionally” and therefore, cannot be tolerated.
Despite adopting a ‘subjective’ H.D to broaden the scope of Article.8 and asserting that a ‘right to
A.S’ does not “[negate] the principle of the sanctity of life”106
one cannot accept the position of the
Court. However, “What if Article.2 […] also meant the right to live with dignity until, and including
the very end of one’s life, and not just the sanctity of life.”107
Overall, the issue is unresolved and the
Court’s position is contestable.
Nevertheless, States must guarantee “access to the effective enjoyment of the right”108
or justify its
restriction.109
This is the final aspect of the Court’s positon to be discussed.
103
Dupre (n-5) 159
104
ibid
105
Puppinck (n-1) 753-759
106
Pretty v United Kingdom (n-15) Para 65; See Koch v Germany (n-37) Para 51 and Gross v Switzerland (n-39)
Para 58; Puppinck (n-1) 735
107
Dupre (n-5) 159
108
Puppinck (n-1) 751
109
Airey v Ireland Apl. 6289/73 9 October 1979 para 24
14
Controlling the ‘Right to Assisted Suicide’: A State’s Margin of Appreciation
The MofA is a “core principle controlling the ECtHR”.110
It is the “degree of discretion” afforded to
States that is invoked when there is “difficulty in identifying uniform European conceptions to the
extent of rights restrictions”111
; the wider the MofA the greater the level of discretion afforded.112
A
lack of consensus suggests to the Court that the matter is likely best left to individual states:113
“[T]he absence of a consensus is probably a decisive factor in finding that there is a wide
margin of appreciation.” 114
Regarding A.S the Court considers that:
“State Parties to the Convention are far from reaching a consensus […], which points towards
a considerable margin of appreciation.” 115
On the one hand, a wide MofA is warranted. While “Switzerland, Belgium and the Netherlands each
have some form of permitted A.S”116
they nevertheless, approach its regulation and accessibility
differently.117
Likewise, “although there is a strong and deeply rooted consensus against the legality
of assisted suicide, each country […] deals with the issue differently, or chooses not to address it at
all.”118
Furthermore, as Pridgeon notes, “[M]any states are divided internally on whether or not such
110
Howard Charles Yourow, The Margin of Appreciation Doctrine in the Dynamics of European Human Rights
Jurisprudence (Springer Publishers 1996) 13
111
Wada (n-2) 275
112
Karen Reid, A Practitioner’s Guide to the European Convention on Human Rights (Sweet and Maxwell 1998)
33
113
Ian Cameron and Maja Kirilova Eriksson, An Introduction to the European Convention on Human Rights
(Lustus Förlag 1993) 45 and 74; Wada (n-2) 275
114
Cameron (n-113) 72-73
115
Koch v Germany (n-37) Para 70
116
Derek Huphrey, Assisted Suicide Laws Around the World Last updated October 2015 available at:
http://www.assistedsuicide.org/suicide_laws.html
117
ibid
118
Wada (n-2) 287
15
procedures should be legalised.”119
Therefore, owing to the lack of consensus the Court correctly
affords a wide MofA on the issue.120
On the other hand, the Court’s position can be criticised. As acknowledged by the Parliamentary
Assembly of the Council of Europe in 1999121
and again in 2012,122
a broad consensus exists in the
prohibition of A.S.123
Questionably, the Court, omitting both documents, instead finds a lack of
consensus as to its legalisation.124
Therefore, States must now justify restriction of the ‘right to A.S’
under Article.8(2) as being:
“[i]n accordance with the law and is necessary in a democratic society in the interests of
national security, public safety or the economic well-being of the country, for the prevention
of disorder or crime, for the protection of health or morals, or for the protection of the rights
and freedoms of others.”125
Article.8(2) is considered “in accordance with the nature of the issues and the importance of the
interests at stake.”126
One such interest is “the risk of abuse inherent in a system that facilitates
access to assisted suicide.”127
Regarding the U.K.’s absolute prohibition of A.S the Court observes
that:
“The more serious the harm involved the more heavily will weigh in the balance
considerations of public health and safety against the countervailing principle of public
autonomy. The law […] was designed to safeguard life by protecting the weak and vulnerable
[…] it is the vulnerability of the class which provides the rational for the law in question. It is
119
Pridgeon (n-11) 45
120
Cameron (n-113) 72-73
121
See Recommendation 1418 (1999) of the Parliamentary Assembly of the Council of Europe.
122
See Resolution 1859 (2012) of the Parliamentary Assembly of the Council of Europe.
123
See Resolution 1859 (2012) of the Parliamentary Assembly of the Council of Europe.
124
Puppinck (n-1) 760
125
European Convention on Human Rights 1950 Article.8(2)
126
Labuschagne (n-7) 96
127
Haas v Switzerland (n-35) Para 58
16
primarily for States to assess the risk and the likely incidence of abuse [if] exceptions were
created.”128
Therefore, the U.K.’s legislative interference with Article.8 is considered proportionate to the aim
pursued129
and within its MofA.130
Indeed, instances of abuse have been reported in Belgium,
Switzerland and the Netherlands.131
Accordingly: “One individual’s ‘fundamental right to a dignified
life and a dignified death should not outweigh the risk of many lives”132
and the Court’s position is
warranted.
However, the weight afforded to this ‘fear of abuse’ is contestable. In the U.K. domestic case
Nicklinson v Ministry of Justice,133
Lady Hale’s dissenting opinion criticised the UK’s ‘blanket ban’134
on A.S:
“It would not be beyond the wit of the legal [and medical] system to devise a process for
identifying these people […] It fails to strike a fair balance between the rights of those who
have freely chosen to commit suicide but are unable to do so without some assistance and
the interests of the community as a whole.”135
From this perspective, the Court has afforded the State too much discretion. However, Lord
Neuberger, considers it: “impossible, at least on present material, to say with confidence in advance
that any such scheme could satisfactorily and appropriately be fashioned.”136
Therefore, the
potential for abuse should remain a critical factor when considering Article.8(2).
128
Pretty v United Kingdom (n-15) Para 74. Author emphasis added
129
The protection of individuals who would be vulnerable to abuse should A.S be permitted.
130
Pretty v United Kingdom (n-15) Para 74-78; See Draghici (n-9) 289
131
Final observations of the UN Human Rights Committee on the reports presented by the Netherlands, 25
August 2009, CCPR/C/NLD/CO/4 para 7; See also Puppinck (n-1) 739
132
Wada (n-2) 283
133
Nicklinson v Ministry of Justice [2014] UKSC 38
134
See: Draghici (n-9) 286
135
Nicklinson v Ministry of Justice (n-133) Para 314 and 317
136
ibid Para 186 and 188
17
Nevertheless, the Court’s acceptance of ‘blanket bans’ is further disputed. Dr Draghici has observed
how many other ‘blanket bans’ have been found incompatible with human-right guarantees
including:137
irreducible life sentences;138
the prohibition of prisoners’ right to vote;139
and
prisoners’ lack of access to assisted reproductive facilities.140
Criticised as inflexible, they fail to take
into account the individual circumstances of an applicant and therefore, cannot be considered
proportionate to the legitimate aim pursued.141
Overall:
“The underlying tenant is transferable to [A.S.]; the law must be capable of responding fairly
to different individual circumstances, and public interest consideration cannot remove the
need to assess each case on its own merits.”142
Accordingly, A.S ‘blanket bans’ should be prohibited. However, a greater European consensus
existed regarding other bans thus enabling the Court to reduce the States’ MofA. Consequently,
‘blanket bans’ are permissible when there is a lack of consensus. Under this reasoning, the Court’s
acceptance of the UK’s A.S. ‘blanket ban’ is justified.
Finally, Lady Hale holds the U.K.’s failure to make allowances for exceptional cases, not its ‘blanket
ban’, as breaching Article.8: “It seems to me that […], the prohibition is justified. It is the lack of any
exception to meet the particular circumstances of the sorts of cases before us that is
incompatible.”143
Moreover, whilst “interference is necessary to prevent abuse to the detriment of
vulnerable people […] the assumption that a mentally competent, but bodily disabled, individual is to
be treated as a vulnerable person, whose personal autonomy must be restricted in the name of
137
Draghici (n-9) 286
138
Vinter v United Kingdom [2012] ECHR 61
139
See: http://www.echr.coe.int/Documents/FS_Prisoners_vote_ENG.pdf
Firth and Others v United Kingdom [2014] ECHR 874; McHugh and Others v United Kingdom Ap.51987/08 10
February 2015
140
Draghici (n-9) 293
141
ibid
142
ibid 292-293
143
Nicklinson v Ministry of Justice (n-133) Para 186
18
protecting them, arguably amounts to moral paternalism.”144
In the U.K. suicide is legal yet,145
individuals who are physically unable to take charge of their bodies and perform the necessary
actions are prevented from its realisation. Thus the law discriminates against them. In Thlimmenos v
Greece146
the Court accepted Article.14147
as also covering reverse discrimination; treating
individuals whose situations are significantly different in the same way.148
However, having regard to
the State’s MofA “in assessing whether and to what extent differences in otherwise similar situations
justify a different treatment,”149
the Court considers that:
“[C]ogent reasons exist […] for not […] distinguish[ing] between those who are able and
those who are unable to commit suicide unaided. The borderline between the two categories
will often be very a very fine one and to seek to build into new law an exception […] would
seriously undermine protection of life.”150
Alternatively, as per Dickson v U.K.:151
“the possibility of justifying the restriction on applicants’
Convention rights by the minimal number of persons adversely affected is unacceptable.”152
Nevertheless, reiterating Lord Neuberger’s position,: “The most persuasive case [is that] those
capable of forming a free and informed decision to commit suicide and distinguish them from those
who might be vulnerable; [However] it is impossible […] to say […] that any such scheme could
satisfactorily and appropriately be fashioned.”153
The fear of abuse remains paramount.
144
Draghici (n-9) 296
145
The Suicide Act 1961 Section.1:
“Suicide to cease to be a crime.
The rule of law whereby it is a crime for a person to commit suicide is hereby abrogated”
146
Thlimmenos v Greece (2001) Ap.34369/97 31 E.H.R.R.
147
Article.14: “The enjoyment of the rights and freedoms set forth in this Convention shall be secured without
discrimination on any ground such as sex, race, colour, language, religion, political or other opinion, national or
social origin, association with a national minority, property, birth or other status.”
148
Thlimmenos v Greece (n-146) Para 411
149
Pretty v United Kingdom (n-15) Para 89
150
Pretty v United Kingdom (n-15) Para 89
151
Dickson v United Kingdom (2007) 44 E.H.R.R 21
152
ibid
153
Nicklinson v Ministry of Justice (n-133)Para 186 and 188
19
Overall, ‘blanket bans’ fail to consider the induvial circumstances of a case and are discriminatory.
However, without expunging fears of abuse or establishing a consensus on the issue, the Court
correctly asserts a wide MofA and permits States to implement “the safer- but certain to generate
injustice- blanket prohibition.”154
However, owing to the questionable foundations upon which the
‘right to A.S’ has been developed, the overall position of the Court is problematic. The only thing
clear about the Court’s ‘right to A.S’ is its legal ambiguity.
154
Draghici (n-9) 297
20
Bibliography
Cases
Airey v Ireland App.6289/73 9 October 1979
Dickson v U.K. App.00044362/04 4 December 2007; [2007] 44 E.H.R.R 21
Dordevic v Croatia App.41526/10 24 July 2012; [2012] ECHR 1640
Firth and Others v U.K. App.47784/09 12 August 2014; [2014] ECHR 874
Goodwin and I v U.K. App.28957/95 11 July 2002.
Gross v Switzerland App.67810/10 14 May 2013
Haas v Switzerland App.31322/07, 20 January 2011
Keenan v U.K. App.27229/95 3 April 2001; [2001] ECHR 239
Ketreb v France App.38447/09 19 July 2012
Koch v Germany App.497/09, 19 July 2012
Laskey, Jaggard, and Brown v. U.K App.21826/93, 21627/93, 21974/93 19 February 1997; 24 Eur.
H.R. Rep. 39 (1997)
LCB v UK App. 23413/94 9 June 1998; [1998] ECHR 108
McCann v UK App.18984/91 6 October 1995; [1995] 21 EHRR 97
McHugh and Others v United Kingdom App.51987/08 10 February 2015
Nicklinson v Ministry of Justice [2014] UKSC 38
Osman v UK App.23452/94 28 October 1998; [1998] ECHR 101
Pretty v United Kingdom (GC) App.234/02 29th
April 2002
Rasnstev v Cypris and the Russian Federation App.25965/04 07 January 2010
Rodriguez v British Columbia (AG) [1993] 3 S.C.R. 519
S v Makwanyane and Another (CCT3/94) [1995] ZACC 3
Schneider v Germany App.17080/07 15 September 2011
SW v The United Kingdom App.20166/92 22 November 1995; [1995] ECHR 52
Thlimmenos v Greece App.34369/97 6 April 2000
Tremblay v France App.37194/02 11 December 2007
Tysiac v Poland App.5410/03 20 March 2007
Vinter v United Kingdom App.66069/09, 130/10 and 3896/10 9 July 2013;
21
Washington v Glucksberg 521 U.S. 702, 710-12 (1997)
Legislation and Declarations
International
Universal Declaration of Human Rights 1948
Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms 1950
Domestic
Germany: German Penal Code Section 216
Switzerland: Swiss Penal Code Article 114 and 115
UK: Suicide Act 1961 (1961 CHAPTER 60 9 and 10 Eliz 2) 3 August 1961
Journals
Diaconescu, A.M, “Euthanasia” (2012) Vo.4(2) Contemporary Readings in Law and Social Justice, 474
Draghici, C. “The blanket ban on assisted suicide: between moral paternalism and utilitarian justice”
(2015) European Human Right Law Review 286
Dupre, C. “Dignity, Democracy, Civilisation” (2012) Vol.33(3) Liverpool Law Review, 263
Jean Paul Costa, “Human Dignity in the Jurisprudence of the European Court of Human Rights” in
Christopher McCrudden (eds) Understanding Human Dignity (Oxford University Press) 393
Labuschagne, JMT. “The European Court of Human Rights and the right to assisted suicide in
international human rights law.” (2004) Vol.17(1) South African Journal of Criminal Justice, 87
McCrudden, C. “Human Dignity and Judicial Interpretation of Human Rights.” (2008) Vol.19(4) The
European Journal of International Law
Meyer, M. “The Simple Dignity of Sentient Life: Speciesism and Human Dignity” (2009) Vol.32(2)
Journal of Social Philosophy, 223
Pridgeon, J.L, “Euthanasia Legislation in the European Union: is a Universal Law Possible?” (2006)
Vol.2(1) Hans Law Review, 45,46
Puppinick. G, and Houge. C, “The ‘Right’ to Assisted Suicide in the case law of the European Court of
Human Rights’ (2014) Vol.18(7-8) The International Journal of Human Rights, 735
Rustin-Petru CIASC, “Euthanasia, National and International Perspectives” (2013) Vol.9(2) Acta
Universitatis Danubius Juridica, 41
Wada, E. “A Pretty Picture: The Margin of Appreciation and the Right to Assisted Suicide” (2005)
Vol.27 Loyola of Los Angeles International and Comparative Law Review, 275
22
Books
Aharon Barak, Human Dignity: The Constitutional Value and the Constitutional Right (Cambridge
University Press 2015)
Catherine Dupre, The Age of Dignity (Hart Publishing 2015)
David Albert Jones, “Is Dignity Language Useful in Bioethical Discussion of Assisted Suicide and
Abortion?” in Christopher McCrudden (eds) Understanding Human Dignity (Oxford University Press)
525
Erin Daly, Dignity Rights: Courts, Constitutions and the Worth of the Human Person (University of
Pennsylvania Press, 2013
Howard Charles Yourow, The Margin of Appreciation Doctrine in the Dynamics of European Human
Rights Jurisprudence (Springer Publishers 1996)
J.Harris, Is Cloning an Attack on Human Dignity? (Nature 1997)
J.Harris, Clones, Genes and Immorality (Oxford University Press 1998)
Jean Paul Costa, “Human Dignity in the Jurisprudence of the European Court of Human Rights” in
Christopher McCrudden (eds) Understanding Human Dignity (Oxford University Press) 393
Ian Cameron and Maja Kirilova Eriksson, An Introduction to the European Convention on Human
Rights (Lustus Förlag 1993)
Karen Reid, A Practitioner’s Guide to the European Convention on Human Rights (Sweet and Maxwell
1998)
Kant, I. Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals (2ND
Revised Edition 1785, Translated by Mary J.
Gregor and Jens Timmermann, Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy, 2012)
Michael Rosen, Dignity: Its History and Meaning (Harvard University Press 2012)
Ronald Dwarkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Harvard University Press, 1978)
R, Dwarkin, Life’s Dominion: An Argument About Abortion, Euthanasia, and Individual Freedom
(Vintage Books 1994)
Howard Charles Yourow, The Margin of Appreciation Doctrine in the Dynamics of European Human
Rights Jurisprudence (Springer Publishers 1996)
Contributions to Edited Books
Gordijn, Bert, Ben Crul and Zbigniew Zylicz ‘Euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide’, in Ten Have,
H. and Clark, D (eds.), The Ethics of Palliative Care: European perspectives (Buckingham, Open
University Press, 2002), 182.
Jones, D.A. “Is Dignity Language Useful in Bioethical Discussion of Assisted Suicide and Abortion?” in
Christopher McCrudden (eds) Understanding Human Dignity (Oxford University Press) 525
23
Jean Paul Costa, “Human Dignity in the Jurisprudence of the European Court of Human Rights” in
Christopher McCrudden (eds) Understanding Human Dignity (Oxford University Press) 393
Factsheets
European Court of Human Rights, “Factsheet- End of life and the ECHR”, July 2015 available at: <
http://echr.coe.int/Pages/home.aspx?p=press/factsheets>
Parliamentary Assembly of the Council of Europe
Recommendation 1418 (1999)
Resolution 1859 (2012), 12 January 2012, Protecting human rights and dignity by taking into account
previously expressed wishes of patients.
Reports
Edeltraud Gatterer, Doc. 8421, Protection of the human rights and dignity in the terminally ill and
dying, Report from Social, Health and Family Affairs Committee, 21/05/1999.
Websites
Derek Huphrey, Assisted Suicide Laws Around the World Last updated October 2015 available at:
http://www.assistedsuicide.org/suicide_laws.html
“Not Dead Yet” <http://notdeadyet.org/about> accessed 17/04/2016
“Not Dead Yet UK” <http://notdeadyetuk.org/> accessed 17/04/2016

Weitere ähnliche Inhalte

Ähnlich wie Essay Type Up No. 13

2395963 aids-to-forensic-medicine-and-toxicology-by-robertson-w-g-aitchison-w...
2395963 aids-to-forensic-medicine-and-toxicology-by-robertson-w-g-aitchison-w...2395963 aids-to-forensic-medicine-and-toxicology-by-robertson-w-g-aitchison-w...
2395963 aids-to-forensic-medicine-and-toxicology-by-robertson-w-g-aitchison-w...Roman Mamun
 
NO ABSOLUTE RECOURSE IN NECESSITY FOR THE INDIVIDUAL WHO RESORTS TO PREVENTIV...
NO ABSOLUTE RECOURSE IN NECESSITY FOR THE INDIVIDUAL WHO RESORTS TO PREVENTIV...NO ABSOLUTE RECOURSE IN NECESSITY FOR THE INDIVIDUAL WHO RESORTS TO PREVENTIV...
NO ABSOLUTE RECOURSE IN NECESSITY FOR THE INDIVIDUAL WHO RESORTS TO PREVENTIV...Frankey Chung
 
State Immunity - Human Rights Violation
State Immunity - Human Rights ViolationState Immunity - Human Rights Violation
State Immunity - Human Rights Violationsurrenderyourthrone
 
Arguments for and against a reform of the law of murder.pdf
Arguments for and against a reform of the law of murder.pdfArguments for and against a reform of the law of murder.pdf
Arguments for and against a reform of the law of murder.pdfKayla Smith
 
Abolition Of The Death Penalty In Indonesia A Conceptual Framework For Action
Abolition Of The Death Penalty In Indonesia  A Conceptual Framework For ActionAbolition Of The Death Penalty In Indonesia  A Conceptual Framework For Action
Abolition Of The Death Penalty In Indonesia A Conceptual Framework For ActionTye Rausch
 
European Coursework Final Draft
European Coursework Final DraftEuropean Coursework Final Draft
European Coursework Final DraftKieran Ierston
 
Presentation on Euthanasia in Bangladesh .slide.pptx
Presentation on Euthanasia in Bangladesh .slide.pptxPresentation on Euthanasia in Bangladesh .slide.pptx
Presentation on Euthanasia in Bangladesh .slide.pptxAbdullahAlHossainJob
 
Introduction to Euthanasia – Medically Assisted Murder or Mercy Killing by Sh...
Introduction to Euthanasia – Medically Assisted Murder or Mercy Killing by Sh...Introduction to Euthanasia – Medically Assisted Murder or Mercy Killing by Sh...
Introduction to Euthanasia – Medically Assisted Murder or Mercy Killing by Sh...SHRADDHA PANDIT
 
ECHR grand chamber judgment s.a.s v. france ban on wearing in public clothin...
ECHR grand chamber judgment s.a.s v. france  ban on wearing in public clothin...ECHR grand chamber judgment s.a.s v. france  ban on wearing in public clothin...
ECHR grand chamber judgment s.a.s v. france ban on wearing in public clothin...REITER LEGAL
 
Reparation for torture in International Law
Reparation for torture in International LawReparation for torture in International Law
Reparation for torture in International LawFAROUQ
 
Solitary confinement and capital punishment
Solitary confinement and capital punishmentSolitary confinement and capital punishment
Solitary confinement and capital punishmentAnirban Mukherjee
 
Human rights act and mental health
Human rights act and mental healthHuman rights act and mental health
Human rights act and mental healthAnselm Eldergill
 
Law commission report 273
Law commission report 273Law commission report 273
Law commission report 273sabrangsabrang
 
EU-LAW-SUMMATIVE-1-Copy
EU-LAW-SUMMATIVE-1-CopyEU-LAW-SUMMATIVE-1-Copy
EU-LAW-SUMMATIVE-1-CopySamuel Akinola
 
A COMMENTARY ON DEATH PENALTY
A COMMENTARY ON DEATH PENALTYA COMMENTARY ON DEATH PENALTY
A COMMENTARY ON DEATH PENALTYAshley Smith
 

Ähnlich wie Essay Type Up No. 13 (20)

EUTHANASIA IN NIGERIA
EUTHANASIA IN NIGERIAEUTHANASIA IN NIGERIA
EUTHANASIA IN NIGERIA
 
14 Critiques on the Interpretation of Genocide by the International Criminal ...
14 Critiques on the Interpretation of Genocide by the International Criminal ...14 Critiques on the Interpretation of Genocide by the International Criminal ...
14 Critiques on the Interpretation of Genocide by the International Criminal ...
 
2395963 aids-to-forensic-medicine-and-toxicology-by-robertson-w-g-aitchison-w...
2395963 aids-to-forensic-medicine-and-toxicology-by-robertson-w-g-aitchison-w...2395963 aids-to-forensic-medicine-and-toxicology-by-robertson-w-g-aitchison-w...
2395963 aids-to-forensic-medicine-and-toxicology-by-robertson-w-g-aitchison-w...
 
NO ABSOLUTE RECOURSE IN NECESSITY FOR THE INDIVIDUAL WHO RESORTS TO PREVENTIV...
NO ABSOLUTE RECOURSE IN NECESSITY FOR THE INDIVIDUAL WHO RESORTS TO PREVENTIV...NO ABSOLUTE RECOURSE IN NECESSITY FOR THE INDIVIDUAL WHO RESORTS TO PREVENTIV...
NO ABSOLUTE RECOURSE IN NECESSITY FOR THE INDIVIDUAL WHO RESORTS TO PREVENTIV...
 
IRE2
IRE2IRE2
IRE2
 
State Immunity - Human Rights Violation
State Immunity - Human Rights ViolationState Immunity - Human Rights Violation
State Immunity - Human Rights Violation
 
Arguments for and against a reform of the law of murder.pdf
Arguments for and against a reform of the law of murder.pdfArguments for and against a reform of the law of murder.pdf
Arguments for and against a reform of the law of murder.pdf
 
Abolition Of The Death Penalty In Indonesia A Conceptual Framework For Action
Abolition Of The Death Penalty In Indonesia  A Conceptual Framework For ActionAbolition Of The Death Penalty In Indonesia  A Conceptual Framework For Action
Abolition Of The Death Penalty In Indonesia A Conceptual Framework For Action
 
European Coursework Final Draft
European Coursework Final DraftEuropean Coursework Final Draft
European Coursework Final Draft
 
Presentation on Euthanasia in Bangladesh .slide.pptx
Presentation on Euthanasia in Bangladesh .slide.pptxPresentation on Euthanasia in Bangladesh .slide.pptx
Presentation on Euthanasia in Bangladesh .slide.pptx
 
Introduction to Euthanasia – Medically Assisted Murder or Mercy Killing by Sh...
Introduction to Euthanasia – Medically Assisted Murder or Mercy Killing by Sh...Introduction to Euthanasia – Medically Assisted Murder or Mercy Killing by Sh...
Introduction to Euthanasia – Medically Assisted Murder or Mercy Killing by Sh...
 
ECHR grand chamber judgment s.a.s v. france ban on wearing in public clothin...
ECHR grand chamber judgment s.a.s v. france  ban on wearing in public clothin...ECHR grand chamber judgment s.a.s v. france  ban on wearing in public clothin...
ECHR grand chamber judgment s.a.s v. france ban on wearing in public clothin...
 
HR_Narayan_067_R1.pptx
HR_Narayan_067_R1.pptxHR_Narayan_067_R1.pptx
HR_Narayan_067_R1.pptx
 
Reparation for torture in International Law
Reparation for torture in International LawReparation for torture in International Law
Reparation for torture in International Law
 
Solitary confinement and capital punishment
Solitary confinement and capital punishmentSolitary confinement and capital punishment
Solitary confinement and capital punishment
 
Death Warrant
Death WarrantDeath Warrant
Death Warrant
 
Human rights act and mental health
Human rights act and mental healthHuman rights act and mental health
Human rights act and mental health
 
Law commission report 273
Law commission report 273Law commission report 273
Law commission report 273
 
EU-LAW-SUMMATIVE-1-Copy
EU-LAW-SUMMATIVE-1-CopyEU-LAW-SUMMATIVE-1-Copy
EU-LAW-SUMMATIVE-1-Copy
 
A COMMENTARY ON DEATH PENALTY
A COMMENTARY ON DEATH PENALTYA COMMENTARY ON DEATH PENALTY
A COMMENTARY ON DEATH PENALTY
 

Essay Type Up No. 13

  • 1. 1 With reference to academic opinion and relevant case law of the European Court of Human Rights, critically assess the position of the European Court of Human Rights relating to euthanasia and assisted suicide. Student Number: 650042321 Module: The European Convention on Human Rights Word Count: 3824 (Within the 5% Limit)
  • 2. 2 With reference to academic opinion and relevant case law of the European Court of Human Rights, critically assess the position of the European Court of Human Rights relating to euthanasia and assisted suicide. Dr Puppinck and Dr Houge observe that: “[T]he case law of the European Court of Human Rights [ECtHR, the Court] clearly leads to the acceptance of a right to assisted suicide [A.S].”1 However, Western States have traditionally disapproved of the practice2 and implemented legislation whereby the acts are criminal offences;3 legally condoned A.S is a recent innovation of Western society.4 Dupre notes: “The time and timing of death have been profoundly transformed […] prompting discussion on euthanasia and assisted suicide.”5 Regarding the Court’s position on A.S and euthanasia, three observations have been deduced. Firstly, Article.2 of the European Convention on Human Rights (ECHR, the Convention),6 the ‘Right to Life,’ does not encompass a ‘Right to Die’.7 Secondly, within Article.8, the ‘Right to Respect for Private Life’, the Court has established a ‘right to A.S’.8 Thirdly, the Court affords member States a wide margin of appreciation (MofA) when restricting the ‘right to A.S’ within their jurisdiction.9 In considering these aspects, the Court’s position regarding a ‘right to A.S’ is held to be unsound. However, it is first appropriate to distinguish between A.S and euthanasia. 1 Gregor Puppinck and Claire de La Houge, “The ‘Right’ to Assisted Suicide in the case law of the European Court of Human Rights’ (2014) Vol.18(7-8) The International Journal of Human Rights, 735, 741 2 Washington v Glucksberg, 521 U.S. 702, 710-12 (1997); Emily Wada, “A Pretty Picture: The Margin of Appreciation and the Right to Assisted Suicide” (2005) Vol.27 Loyola of Los Angeles International and Comparative Law Review 275 3 Rustin-Petru CIASC, “Euthanasia, National and International Perspectives” (2013) Vol.9(2) Acta Universitatis Danubius Juridica, 41 4 Wada (n-2) 283 5 Catherine Dupre, The Age of Dignity, (Hart Publishing, 2015) 146 6 Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms 1950 7 Wada (n-2) 275; JMT Labuschagne, “The European Court of Human Rights and the right to assisted suicide in international human rights law.” (2004) Vol.17(1) South African Journal of Criminal Justice, 87; Puppinck (n-1) 735 8 Puppinck (n-1) 741 9 Wada (n-3) 275; Carmen Draghici, “The blanket ban on assisted suicide: between moral paternalism and utilitarian justice” (2015) European Human Right Law Review 286
  • 3. 3 Defining Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia A.S involves providing the applicant with the means of committing suicide however, the applicant performs the final, death inducing, act.10 Conversely, in voluntary euthanasia11 the assisting person commits the final act at the victim’s request.12 Despite this distinction, the ECtHR exclusively mentions A.S even in situations where the candidate to suicide is unable to execute the lethal act themselves13 possibly because the two acts are not always easily distinguishable.14 Notably, in Pretty v United Kingdom,15 despite the applicant being completely paralysed and unable to perform the lethal act herself, the Court exclusively referred to A.S. Concurrently, at a domestic level, irrespective of whether States permit16 or ban17 euthanasia, the action also includes A.S.18 Indeed, only Switzerland applies a distinction in law.19 Accordingly, the two practised are referred to interchangeably. 10 For instance, self-administering a lethal substance. Puppinck (n-1) 739; Amelia Mihaela Diaconescu, “Euthanasia” (2012) Vol4(2) Contemporary Readings in Law and Social Justice, 474 11 Compared to non-voluntary and involuntary euthanasia. Non-voluntary euthanasia involves an individual ending the life of a person who cannot choose by himself between living and dying. Involuntary euthanasia is performed on a person who is able to provide informed consent, but does not, because he was not asked. For instance, causing death by administering an ever increasing dose by the doctor who does not intend to cause death, but to alleviate pain, but which could produce (involuntarily) the patient’s death. Diaconescu (n-10) 474 J. Lucy Pridgeon, “Euthanasia Legislation in the European Union: is a Universal Law Possible?” (2006) Vol.2(1) Hans Law Review, 45,46 Gordijn, Bert, Ben Crul and Zbigniew Zylicz ‘Euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide’, in Ten Have, H. and Clark, D (eds.), The Ethics of Palliative Care: European perspectives (Buckingham, Open University Press, 2002), 182. 12 Puppinck (n-1) 739 13 ibid 741 14 ibid 750 15 Pretty v United Kingdom (GC), Ap.234/02, 29th April 2002 16 E.g. Belgium. See: Pridgeon (n-11) 45 17 E.g. Germany. See: ibid 18 Puppinck (n-1) 739 19 ibid
  • 4. 4 The ‘Right to Die’: Considering Article.2 and Article.8 In Pretty20 the Court held that the ‘right to life’ does not encompass a negative aspect; a right to die.21 However, the ruling fails to consider the ‘quality of life.’22 Justice Sachs perceives that: “The right to life without a basis quality of life […] is senseless.”23 Accordingly, the Court failed to properly address the interaction between the ‘right to life’ and the “claim to the basic quality of life.”24 Labuschagne notes: “The untenable and vicious effect of these decisions, whatever the technical and interpretational arguments may be, is that a cruel and senseless dying process, which forms part of the living process since the individual is still alive when dying, is sanctioned by legal rules.”25 However, Article.2 is: “[A] provision which not only safeguards the right to life but sets out the circumstances when the deprivation of life may be justified. Article 2 ranks as one of the most fundamental provisions of the convention...”26 Therefore, the Court’s position is commendable for upholding the ‘sanctity of life.’27 Furthermore, Article.2 obliges the State to not only refrain from intentionally and unlawfully depriving its subjects of life, but to also take appropriate steps to safeguard their lives.28 States have notably accomplished 20 Pretty v United Kingdom (GC), Ap.234/02, 29th April 2002 21 ibid Para 39 22 Labuschagne (n-7) 93 23 Justice Sachs in S v Makwanyane and Another (CCT3/94) [1995] ZACC 3 Para 353 24 Labuschagne(n-7) 90-91 25 ibid 93 26 McCann v UK (1995) 21 EHRR 97 Para 146-7. Author emphasis added 27 See Puppinck (n-1) 28 LCB v UK [1998] ECHR 108 See also Osman v UK [1998] ECHR 101 and Keenan v UK 2001 Ap.27229/95, 3rd April 2001 Para 91-92
  • 5. 5 this by “prohibiting murder and [A.S].”29 Critically, Article.2(2) exhaustively lists the exceptions to the right to life that are tolerated30 and Article.15(2) further states that: “No derogation from Article 2, except in respect of deaths resulting from lawful acts of war, […] shall be made under this provision.” Significantly, neither Article.2(2) or Article.15(5) provides that the consent of an individual or their quality of life are justifications for derogation.31 Accordingly, the Court is correct in its assertion that: “[Article.2] is unconcerned with issues to do with the quality of living [….] Article 2 cannot, […], be interpreted as conferring […] a right to die...”32 However, the Court has expanded the scope of Article.8 and obliged States to adopt a liberal position on A.S.33 Accordingly, attention now turns towards its development and interaction with Article.2. As Houge observes: “The recognition of the right to A.S was obtained [not by] the substantive right to [A.S] but the procedural right to know if one is able to legally exercise this right.”34 In Hass v Switzerland,35 Switzerland was obliged “to establish a procedure capable of ensuring that a decision to end one’s life does indeed correspond with the free wish of the individual concerned.”36 Subsequently in Koch v Germany,37 the State was obliged to establish an effective framework to rule 29 Puppinck (n-1) 757 30 Article.2(2) “Deprivation of life shall not be regarded as inflicted in contravention of this article when it results from the use of force which is no more than absolutely necessary: (a) in defence of any person from unlawful violence; (b) in order to effect a lawful arrest or to prevent escape of a person lawfully detained; (c) in action lawfully taken for the purpose of quelling a riot or insurrection” 31 ibid 32 Pretty v United Kingdom (n-15) Para 39 33 Puppinck (n-1) 750 34 ibid. Author emphasis added. 35 Haas v Switzerland, Ap.31322/07, 20 January 2011 36 ibid Para 58 37 Koch v Germany, Ap.497/09, 19 July 2012
  • 6. 6 on the merits of decisions refusing A.S.38 Finally, in Gross v Switzerland,39 Switzerland was held to be obligated to establish a legal framework permitting individuals to claim their right to A.S.40 However, the legal basis of these obligations is unclear.41 A Conventional procedural obligation is an accessory of a principal material right.42 Therefore, the Court’s assertions imply the existence of a material right. Such an obligation derives either directly from the Convention, an autonomous Convectional obligation, and/or domestic law (provided it enters the scope of the Convention).43 As there is no domestic ‘right to A.S’ in the States concerned, one can conclude that the procedural obligation derives from an autonomous Convention right. However, the Court fails to affirm the existence of this right in either Haas, Koch or Gross.44 Rather, it references Schneider v Germany45 stressing that: “[Article.8] may encompass a right to judicial review even in a case which the substantive right in question had yet to be established.”46 However, in Schneider a relevant domestic right already existed while in Koch the legislator had intentionally omitted the right.47 Therefore, the Court’s reference is inappropriate.48 The Court has failed to dispel the doubt as to the actual existence of an independent Convention right. Therefore, “the legal basis [of the] right to A.S is dubious.”49 Accordingly, the Court’s reasoning in finding a right to A.S under Article.8 needs to be addressed. 38 ibid Para 71 39 Gross v Switzerland, Ap. 67810/10, 14 May 2013 40 Puppinck (n-1) 751 41 ibid 42 Tysiac v Poland Ap.5410/03 20 March 2007 para 113; A procedural right is not an independent right but rather a right requiring a State to guarantee the means of access to enjoyment of a right. 43 Puppinck (n-1) 751 44 ibid 45 Schneider v Germany Ap.17080/07 15 September 2011 Para 100. The Court noted the possibility of establishing a procedural obligation without first having recognised a principal material right 46 Koch v Germany (n-37) Para 53 47 Puppinck (n-1) 753 48 ibid 49 ibid 758 “the legal basis on which the Court has [built] the right to [A.S] is dubious.”
  • 7. 7 Article.8 and a ‘Right to Assisted Suicide’ Since Pretty the Court has increasingly ignored Article.2.50 In Hass, it was considered only in terms of its procedural obligation to verify the subjective will of the suicide candidate51 to prevent: “an individual from taking his or her own life if the decision has not been taken freely and with the full understanding of what is involved”52 [ensuring the] “decision [..]correspond[s] with the free wish of the individual concerned.”53 Thus, the obligation to ‘guarantee and respect the right to life’ under Article.2 is not realised by the ‘mere’ respect of life but by respecting the autonomy of the individual. Moreover, in Koch and Gross, whilst the Court recalled the sacredness of life it was presented in a negative formulation, the ‘quality of life’ taking ‘priority’: “Without in any way negating the principle of the sanctity of life protected under the Convention, the Court Considers that it is under Article.8 that notions of the quality of life take on significance.”54 Hence, the principal consideration regarding A.S is the subjective right to a ‘quality of life’ rather than the objective ‘right to life’; the autonomy of an individual being both the basis and the condition of the ‘right to A.S’.55 Critically, the objectivity of Article.2 has been absorbed into the subjectivity of Article.856 thereby diminishing the assertion that Article.2 “constitutes an inalienable attribute of the human person and that is form[s] the supreme value in the scale of human rights.” 57 50 ibid 754 51 ibid 750-53 52 Haas v Switzerland (n-35) Para 54 53 ibid Para 58 54 Pretty v United Kingdom (n-15) Para 65; See Koch v Germany (n-37) Para 51 and Gross v Switzerland (n-39) Para 58 55 See: Puppinck (n-1) 753-759 56 ibid 758 57 Pretty v United Kingdom (n-15) Para 65
  • 8. 8 The ‘supreme value’ is now personal autonomy. The Court has established this notion of ‘quality of life’ on an individualistic conception of human dignity (H.D):58 “[I]n an era of growing medical sophistication, many people are concerned that they should not be forced to linger on in old age or in states of advanced physical or mental decrepitude which conflict with strongly held ideals of self and personal identity.” 59 Therefore, one’s autonomy is constrained if forced to live in a state that conflicts with one’s such “ideals.”60 Accordingly, these ‘ideals’ are individualistic resulting in a subjective measurement of the quality of life.61 Consequently, this concept of H.D is not inherent but self-determined.62 Therefore, in Koch and Gross the invalidity of one applicant and the old age of the other was held to impeded the quality of their lives. As Houge reasons: “their dignity as human beings could therefore occur preferentially choosing to wave existence rather than suffer a decline. The value of life is thus bound to its quality.”63 The shift from life to the ‘quality of life’, leads to the demands for self-determination and finally to a right to the quality of death as falling within the Scope of Article.8.64 However, the Court’s application of H.D and in particular a ‘subjective’ H.D is contestable. Despite its notable presence “in terms of quantity and quality”65 and as a “foundation [in] the legal reasoning of the Strasbourg Court in its rulings”66 the ECHR makes no reference to H.D.67 Accordingly, its use as an interpretive tool is questionable.68 58 Puppinck (n-1) 755 59 Gross v Switzerland (n-39) Para 58 60 Puppinck (n-1) 755 61 ibid 62 ibid 63 ibid 64 ibid 65 Dupre (n-5) 85 66 Jean Paul Costa, “Human Dignity in the Jurisprudence of the European Court of Human Rights” in Christopher McCrudden (eds) Understanding Human Dignity (Oxford University Press) 393 67 Diaconescu, (n-10) 481; Costa (ibid) 393 68 Costa (n-66) 393
  • 9. 9 Given that the Convention is inspired by, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR),69 which is founded on the “recognition of the inherent dignity of all members of the human family” and speaks of the “inherent dignity of the person,”70 its absence is arguably the deliberate act of its drafters to exclude it as an interpretative tool.71 Furthermore, Michael Rosen72 and John Harris73 have attacked the concept as “comprehensively vague”, with modern conceptions inheriting several distinct strands of meaning74 thereby obscuring the Convention’s interpretation. McCrudden further notes: “[F]or some, it is only a ‘smoke screen’ to hide the emptiness or disagreement on which human rights are funded.”75 Accordingly, H.D should be excluded from the interpretation of the Convention.76 However, in SW v U.K.77 the Court formulated its commitment to protecting H.D as being the “essence” of the ECHR78 and has subsequently referred to its “inviolability” to give greater normative strength to H.D over even Article.2.79 Furthermore, Daly considers the inherency of H.D within all human rights,80 Costa submits that notions of H.D were in the drafters’ minds81 and Dupree applauds how: 69 The Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR) is a declaration adopted by the United Nations General Assembly on 10 December 1948; Puppinck (n-1) 755 70 Costa (n-66) 394 71 ibid 393 72 Michael Rosen, Dignity: Its History and Meaning (Harvard University Press 2012) 73 J.Harris, Is Cloning an Attack on Human Dignity? (Nature 1997); Harris, Clones, Genes and Immorality (Oxford University Press 1998) 74 J.Harris, Clones, Genes and Immorality (Oxford University Press 1998) 31; David Albert Jones, “Is Dignity Language Useful in Bioethical Discussion of Assisted Suicide and Abortion?” in Christopher McCrudden (eds) Understanding Human Dignity (Oxford University Press) 525 75 Christopher McCrudden, “Human Dignity and Judicial Interpretation of Human Rights.” (2008) Vol.19(4) The European Journal of International Law, 22 76 Costa, (n-66); Puppinck (n-1) 756-7 77 SW v The United Kingdom 1995 ECHR 52 78 SW v The United Kingdom (ibid) Para 101; See Dupre (n-5) 174 79 See Dupre (n-5) 174 80 Erin Daly, Dignity Rights: Courts, Constitutions and the Worth of the Human Person (University of Pennsylvania Press, 2013); Dupre (n-5) 85: “[A]lmost every aspect of human interaction and identity [can] be, in one way or another, translated and adjudicated in terms of human dignity.” 81 Costa (n-66) 394:“[E]specially because the very establishment of the Council of Europe in 1949 and the elaboration of the Convention […] The founding fathers of the European system of protection of right and freedoms shared the same philosophy as the authors of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights.”
  • 10. 10 “[R]eliance on human dignity makes discursive space to consider alternative and new ways of interpreting the law, and […] therefore, provided judges with the key to unlock a difficult situation and open un a new path in human rights protection.”82 Furthermore, Meyer asserts that the potential variations in meaning do not result in equivocation but are “a family of concepts clustered around the practice of moral evaluation.”83 Moreover, Dupre praises the concept’s flexibility and its use when resolving complex, present day situations: “In practice, [H.D’s] transformative function arguably explains why it has been a key judicial instrument for departing from established case law and precedent, opening up a new path in an unchartered territory.” 84 Overall, reference to H.D has played an instrumental role in expanding the Convention’s scope of protection.85 As Costa concludes, “the concept of human dignity in the Court’s jurisprudence expresses a deliberate intention of building a bridge between the universal instruments and the silent European text, filling the vacuum created by the authors of the Convention.”86 Therefore, H.D should not be excluded from the Court’s interpretation of the Convention. The issue now lies in its appropriate application. According to Dwarkin: “[H.D] supposes that there are ways of treating a man that are inconsistent with recognising him as a full member of the human community, and holds that such treatment is profoundly unjust.”87 Regarding A.S: 82 Dupre (n-5) 159 83 M. Meyer, “The Simple Dignity of Sentient Life: Speciesism and Human Dignity” (2009) Vol.32(2) Journal of Social Philosophy 223, 240. 84 Dupre (n-5) 271-2 85 See for example: SW v The United Kingdom (n-77); Keenen v UK [2001] ECHR 239; Rasnstev v Cyprus and the Russian Federation App.25965/04 07 January 2010; Dordevic v Coratia [2012] ECHR 1640, Goodwin and I v UK Ap. 28957/95 11 July 2002. 86 Costa (n-66) 401 87 Ronald Dwarkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Harvard University Press, 1978) 198
  • 11. 11 “[H.D] has been in these debates, prompting those who want to maintain a ‘natural timing’ of death and dying, and those who want to make use of their last opportunity to be free and control their life by controlling their death too.”88 According to Diaconescu: “[H.D] is based on the human being’s right to dignity and the right and respect for his or her autonomy, self-determination of the subject with regard to his or her own body.”89 Therefore, in adopting a ‘subjective’ perception of H.D, the Court’s position can be praised as liberating those who no longer wish to endure life: “If a person [suffering from a terminal illness or extreme disability] does not have access to assisted suicide, then he or she is forced to endure the indignity of what is considered a subhuman condition of life”90 However, proponents of A.S have generally restricted their efforts to “those suffering from terminal and/or disabling conditions.”91 Yet, in Gross the applicant’s old age, as opposed to invalidity in Koch, was viewed as interfering with her ‘quality of life.’92 Accordingly, the Court’s use of an individualistic perception of H.D is perhaps a step too far.93 Furthermore, the Court’s adoption of a subjective, rather than inherent, notion of H.D is contestable. As noted by Gatterer, an ‘inherent’ dignity is not subjective94 and therefore, the Court is not adhering to same dignity as envisioned in the UDHR and which inspired the ECHR.95 Arguably: 88 Dupre (n-5) 146 89 Diaconescu (n-10) 477 90 David Albert Jones. “Is Dignity Language Useful in Bioethical Discussion of Assisted Suicide and Abortion?” in Christopher McCrudden (eds) Understanding Human Dignity (Oxford University Press) 525, 530-31 91 ibid 92 See Puppinck (n-1) 93 However, see Ketreb v France Ap.38447/09 19th July 2012 where the Court considered that being young and healthy prevented Mr Ketreb’s desire to die from being accepted and instead reiterated the State’s obligation to “take necessary measures to protect the lives of those within its jurisdiction.” 94 Edeltraud Gatterer, Doc. 8421, Protection of the human rights and dignity in the terminally ill and dying, Report from Social, Health and Family Affairs Committee, 21/05/1999. This report led to the Parliamentary Assembly of the Council of Europe Recommendation 1418 (1999) which affirmed that the right to life of the sick and dying must be guaranteed even when they express the desire to die. 95 Puppinck (n-1)755
  • 12. 12 “in substituting the ‘inherent dignity’ for a relative dignity […] the Court radically modified the ontological foundations of the Convention, that of universal to particular. The Court removes from rights their objectivity by rendering them subjective, and therefore relevant to their subject. [Therefore], the measure of human rights is no longer the human, but each individual.”96 Furthermore, the Court’s position arguably fails to respect the dignity of each human life.97 This ‘Dignity as Life’ concept holds that killing contradicts the intrinsic dignity of human existence both in respect of life itself and what life makes possible all individuals.98 Kant, for example, considers suicide as the failure to respect the worth or dignity of human life in one’s own case.99 Accordingly, the Court’s position directly contradicts these views. Additionally, disability rights movements caution that: “The desire for euthanasia is inseparable from the fear of dependence and loss of control, of incontinence and dementia, in short, from the fear of disability. While this desire is expressed as a wish ‘to die with dignity’, it implies that living in certain conditions is, per se, indignity.”100 Therefore, the very act of judging a life with an impairment as being ‘undignified’ and therefore, “a life unworthy to be lived”101 is not only discriminatory but humiliating towards those who live with an impairment.102 Arguably, the Court’s position actually debases the very individuals it seeks to liberate. 96 ibid 756 97 Jones (n-90) 529 98 ibid 99 Immanuel Kant, Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals (2ND Revised Edition 1785, Translated by Mary J. Gregor and Jens Timmermann, Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy, 2012) 54, 67; Jones. (n-90) 530 100 Jones. (n-90) 531; See organisations “Not Dead Yet” and “Not Dead Yet UK”, a national, grassroots disability rights movement that opposes legalization of assisted suicide and euthanasia as deadly forms of discrimination. <http://notdeadyet.org/about> accessed 17/04/2016 <http://notdeadyetuk.org/> accessed 17/04/2016 101 Jones (n-90) 538 102 ibid
  • 13. 13 Overall, whilst opinions on the Court’s position are divided, “[H.D’s] role is […] to guide judges as they venture into new territories.”103 Society’s understanding of death and dignity is evolving. As such, the application of H.D within the Convention must evolve too, even if contentious.104 Nevertheless, the Court’s assertion of a ‘right to A.S’ is confronted with a further hurdle. Article.2 does not contain a negative right to die and its exceptions interpreted restrictively. Furthermore, Article.17 states that: “Nothing in this Convention may be interpreted as implying […] any right to engage in any activity or perform any act aimed at the destruction on any of the rights and freedoms set forth herein or at their limitation to a greater extent than is provided for in the Convention.” Therefore, Aritcle.8 cannot be interpreted as implying a new right that aims at the destruction of Article.2.105 Ultimately, even when jurisprudentially absorbed in Article.8 the wording of Article.2 remains “no one shall be deprived on their life intentionally” and therefore, cannot be tolerated. Despite adopting a ‘subjective’ H.D to broaden the scope of Article.8 and asserting that a ‘right to A.S’ does not “[negate] the principle of the sanctity of life”106 one cannot accept the position of the Court. However, “What if Article.2 […] also meant the right to live with dignity until, and including the very end of one’s life, and not just the sanctity of life.”107 Overall, the issue is unresolved and the Court’s position is contestable. Nevertheless, States must guarantee “access to the effective enjoyment of the right”108 or justify its restriction.109 This is the final aspect of the Court’s positon to be discussed. 103 Dupre (n-5) 159 104 ibid 105 Puppinck (n-1) 753-759 106 Pretty v United Kingdom (n-15) Para 65; See Koch v Germany (n-37) Para 51 and Gross v Switzerland (n-39) Para 58; Puppinck (n-1) 735 107 Dupre (n-5) 159 108 Puppinck (n-1) 751 109 Airey v Ireland Apl. 6289/73 9 October 1979 para 24
  • 14. 14 Controlling the ‘Right to Assisted Suicide’: A State’s Margin of Appreciation The MofA is a “core principle controlling the ECtHR”.110 It is the “degree of discretion” afforded to States that is invoked when there is “difficulty in identifying uniform European conceptions to the extent of rights restrictions”111 ; the wider the MofA the greater the level of discretion afforded.112 A lack of consensus suggests to the Court that the matter is likely best left to individual states:113 “[T]he absence of a consensus is probably a decisive factor in finding that there is a wide margin of appreciation.” 114 Regarding A.S the Court considers that: “State Parties to the Convention are far from reaching a consensus […], which points towards a considerable margin of appreciation.” 115 On the one hand, a wide MofA is warranted. While “Switzerland, Belgium and the Netherlands each have some form of permitted A.S”116 they nevertheless, approach its regulation and accessibility differently.117 Likewise, “although there is a strong and deeply rooted consensus against the legality of assisted suicide, each country […] deals with the issue differently, or chooses not to address it at all.”118 Furthermore, as Pridgeon notes, “[M]any states are divided internally on whether or not such 110 Howard Charles Yourow, The Margin of Appreciation Doctrine in the Dynamics of European Human Rights Jurisprudence (Springer Publishers 1996) 13 111 Wada (n-2) 275 112 Karen Reid, A Practitioner’s Guide to the European Convention on Human Rights (Sweet and Maxwell 1998) 33 113 Ian Cameron and Maja Kirilova Eriksson, An Introduction to the European Convention on Human Rights (Lustus Förlag 1993) 45 and 74; Wada (n-2) 275 114 Cameron (n-113) 72-73 115 Koch v Germany (n-37) Para 70 116 Derek Huphrey, Assisted Suicide Laws Around the World Last updated October 2015 available at: http://www.assistedsuicide.org/suicide_laws.html 117 ibid 118 Wada (n-2) 287
  • 15. 15 procedures should be legalised.”119 Therefore, owing to the lack of consensus the Court correctly affords a wide MofA on the issue.120 On the other hand, the Court’s position can be criticised. As acknowledged by the Parliamentary Assembly of the Council of Europe in 1999121 and again in 2012,122 a broad consensus exists in the prohibition of A.S.123 Questionably, the Court, omitting both documents, instead finds a lack of consensus as to its legalisation.124 Therefore, States must now justify restriction of the ‘right to A.S’ under Article.8(2) as being: “[i]n accordance with the law and is necessary in a democratic society in the interests of national security, public safety or the economic well-being of the country, for the prevention of disorder or crime, for the protection of health or morals, or for the protection of the rights and freedoms of others.”125 Article.8(2) is considered “in accordance with the nature of the issues and the importance of the interests at stake.”126 One such interest is “the risk of abuse inherent in a system that facilitates access to assisted suicide.”127 Regarding the U.K.’s absolute prohibition of A.S the Court observes that: “The more serious the harm involved the more heavily will weigh in the balance considerations of public health and safety against the countervailing principle of public autonomy. The law […] was designed to safeguard life by protecting the weak and vulnerable […] it is the vulnerability of the class which provides the rational for the law in question. It is 119 Pridgeon (n-11) 45 120 Cameron (n-113) 72-73 121 See Recommendation 1418 (1999) of the Parliamentary Assembly of the Council of Europe. 122 See Resolution 1859 (2012) of the Parliamentary Assembly of the Council of Europe. 123 See Resolution 1859 (2012) of the Parliamentary Assembly of the Council of Europe. 124 Puppinck (n-1) 760 125 European Convention on Human Rights 1950 Article.8(2) 126 Labuschagne (n-7) 96 127 Haas v Switzerland (n-35) Para 58
  • 16. 16 primarily for States to assess the risk and the likely incidence of abuse [if] exceptions were created.”128 Therefore, the U.K.’s legislative interference with Article.8 is considered proportionate to the aim pursued129 and within its MofA.130 Indeed, instances of abuse have been reported in Belgium, Switzerland and the Netherlands.131 Accordingly: “One individual’s ‘fundamental right to a dignified life and a dignified death should not outweigh the risk of many lives”132 and the Court’s position is warranted. However, the weight afforded to this ‘fear of abuse’ is contestable. In the U.K. domestic case Nicklinson v Ministry of Justice,133 Lady Hale’s dissenting opinion criticised the UK’s ‘blanket ban’134 on A.S: “It would not be beyond the wit of the legal [and medical] system to devise a process for identifying these people […] It fails to strike a fair balance between the rights of those who have freely chosen to commit suicide but are unable to do so without some assistance and the interests of the community as a whole.”135 From this perspective, the Court has afforded the State too much discretion. However, Lord Neuberger, considers it: “impossible, at least on present material, to say with confidence in advance that any such scheme could satisfactorily and appropriately be fashioned.”136 Therefore, the potential for abuse should remain a critical factor when considering Article.8(2). 128 Pretty v United Kingdom (n-15) Para 74. Author emphasis added 129 The protection of individuals who would be vulnerable to abuse should A.S be permitted. 130 Pretty v United Kingdom (n-15) Para 74-78; See Draghici (n-9) 289 131 Final observations of the UN Human Rights Committee on the reports presented by the Netherlands, 25 August 2009, CCPR/C/NLD/CO/4 para 7; See also Puppinck (n-1) 739 132 Wada (n-2) 283 133 Nicklinson v Ministry of Justice [2014] UKSC 38 134 See: Draghici (n-9) 286 135 Nicklinson v Ministry of Justice (n-133) Para 314 and 317 136 ibid Para 186 and 188
  • 17. 17 Nevertheless, the Court’s acceptance of ‘blanket bans’ is further disputed. Dr Draghici has observed how many other ‘blanket bans’ have been found incompatible with human-right guarantees including:137 irreducible life sentences;138 the prohibition of prisoners’ right to vote;139 and prisoners’ lack of access to assisted reproductive facilities.140 Criticised as inflexible, they fail to take into account the individual circumstances of an applicant and therefore, cannot be considered proportionate to the legitimate aim pursued.141 Overall: “The underlying tenant is transferable to [A.S.]; the law must be capable of responding fairly to different individual circumstances, and public interest consideration cannot remove the need to assess each case on its own merits.”142 Accordingly, A.S ‘blanket bans’ should be prohibited. However, a greater European consensus existed regarding other bans thus enabling the Court to reduce the States’ MofA. Consequently, ‘blanket bans’ are permissible when there is a lack of consensus. Under this reasoning, the Court’s acceptance of the UK’s A.S. ‘blanket ban’ is justified. Finally, Lady Hale holds the U.K.’s failure to make allowances for exceptional cases, not its ‘blanket ban’, as breaching Article.8: “It seems to me that […], the prohibition is justified. It is the lack of any exception to meet the particular circumstances of the sorts of cases before us that is incompatible.”143 Moreover, whilst “interference is necessary to prevent abuse to the detriment of vulnerable people […] the assumption that a mentally competent, but bodily disabled, individual is to be treated as a vulnerable person, whose personal autonomy must be restricted in the name of 137 Draghici (n-9) 286 138 Vinter v United Kingdom [2012] ECHR 61 139 See: http://www.echr.coe.int/Documents/FS_Prisoners_vote_ENG.pdf Firth and Others v United Kingdom [2014] ECHR 874; McHugh and Others v United Kingdom Ap.51987/08 10 February 2015 140 Draghici (n-9) 293 141 ibid 142 ibid 292-293 143 Nicklinson v Ministry of Justice (n-133) Para 186
  • 18. 18 protecting them, arguably amounts to moral paternalism.”144 In the U.K. suicide is legal yet,145 individuals who are physically unable to take charge of their bodies and perform the necessary actions are prevented from its realisation. Thus the law discriminates against them. In Thlimmenos v Greece146 the Court accepted Article.14147 as also covering reverse discrimination; treating individuals whose situations are significantly different in the same way.148 However, having regard to the State’s MofA “in assessing whether and to what extent differences in otherwise similar situations justify a different treatment,”149 the Court considers that: “[C]ogent reasons exist […] for not […] distinguish[ing] between those who are able and those who are unable to commit suicide unaided. The borderline between the two categories will often be very a very fine one and to seek to build into new law an exception […] would seriously undermine protection of life.”150 Alternatively, as per Dickson v U.K.:151 “the possibility of justifying the restriction on applicants’ Convention rights by the minimal number of persons adversely affected is unacceptable.”152 Nevertheless, reiterating Lord Neuberger’s position,: “The most persuasive case [is that] those capable of forming a free and informed decision to commit suicide and distinguish them from those who might be vulnerable; [However] it is impossible […] to say […] that any such scheme could satisfactorily and appropriately be fashioned.”153 The fear of abuse remains paramount. 144 Draghici (n-9) 296 145 The Suicide Act 1961 Section.1: “Suicide to cease to be a crime. The rule of law whereby it is a crime for a person to commit suicide is hereby abrogated” 146 Thlimmenos v Greece (2001) Ap.34369/97 31 E.H.R.R. 147 Article.14: “The enjoyment of the rights and freedoms set forth in this Convention shall be secured without discrimination on any ground such as sex, race, colour, language, religion, political or other opinion, national or social origin, association with a national minority, property, birth or other status.” 148 Thlimmenos v Greece (n-146) Para 411 149 Pretty v United Kingdom (n-15) Para 89 150 Pretty v United Kingdom (n-15) Para 89 151 Dickson v United Kingdom (2007) 44 E.H.R.R 21 152 ibid 153 Nicklinson v Ministry of Justice (n-133)Para 186 and 188
  • 19. 19 Overall, ‘blanket bans’ fail to consider the induvial circumstances of a case and are discriminatory. However, without expunging fears of abuse or establishing a consensus on the issue, the Court correctly asserts a wide MofA and permits States to implement “the safer- but certain to generate injustice- blanket prohibition.”154 However, owing to the questionable foundations upon which the ‘right to A.S’ has been developed, the overall position of the Court is problematic. The only thing clear about the Court’s ‘right to A.S’ is its legal ambiguity. 154 Draghici (n-9) 297
  • 20. 20 Bibliography Cases Airey v Ireland App.6289/73 9 October 1979 Dickson v U.K. App.00044362/04 4 December 2007; [2007] 44 E.H.R.R 21 Dordevic v Croatia App.41526/10 24 July 2012; [2012] ECHR 1640 Firth and Others v U.K. App.47784/09 12 August 2014; [2014] ECHR 874 Goodwin and I v U.K. App.28957/95 11 July 2002. Gross v Switzerland App.67810/10 14 May 2013 Haas v Switzerland App.31322/07, 20 January 2011 Keenan v U.K. App.27229/95 3 April 2001; [2001] ECHR 239 Ketreb v France App.38447/09 19 July 2012 Koch v Germany App.497/09, 19 July 2012 Laskey, Jaggard, and Brown v. U.K App.21826/93, 21627/93, 21974/93 19 February 1997; 24 Eur. H.R. Rep. 39 (1997) LCB v UK App. 23413/94 9 June 1998; [1998] ECHR 108 McCann v UK App.18984/91 6 October 1995; [1995] 21 EHRR 97 McHugh and Others v United Kingdom App.51987/08 10 February 2015 Nicklinson v Ministry of Justice [2014] UKSC 38 Osman v UK App.23452/94 28 October 1998; [1998] ECHR 101 Pretty v United Kingdom (GC) App.234/02 29th April 2002 Rasnstev v Cypris and the Russian Federation App.25965/04 07 January 2010 Rodriguez v British Columbia (AG) [1993] 3 S.C.R. 519 S v Makwanyane and Another (CCT3/94) [1995] ZACC 3 Schneider v Germany App.17080/07 15 September 2011 SW v The United Kingdom App.20166/92 22 November 1995; [1995] ECHR 52 Thlimmenos v Greece App.34369/97 6 April 2000 Tremblay v France App.37194/02 11 December 2007 Tysiac v Poland App.5410/03 20 March 2007 Vinter v United Kingdom App.66069/09, 130/10 and 3896/10 9 July 2013;
  • 21. 21 Washington v Glucksberg 521 U.S. 702, 710-12 (1997) Legislation and Declarations International Universal Declaration of Human Rights 1948 Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms 1950 Domestic Germany: German Penal Code Section 216 Switzerland: Swiss Penal Code Article 114 and 115 UK: Suicide Act 1961 (1961 CHAPTER 60 9 and 10 Eliz 2) 3 August 1961 Journals Diaconescu, A.M, “Euthanasia” (2012) Vo.4(2) Contemporary Readings in Law and Social Justice, 474 Draghici, C. “The blanket ban on assisted suicide: between moral paternalism and utilitarian justice” (2015) European Human Right Law Review 286 Dupre, C. “Dignity, Democracy, Civilisation” (2012) Vol.33(3) Liverpool Law Review, 263 Jean Paul Costa, “Human Dignity in the Jurisprudence of the European Court of Human Rights” in Christopher McCrudden (eds) Understanding Human Dignity (Oxford University Press) 393 Labuschagne, JMT. “The European Court of Human Rights and the right to assisted suicide in international human rights law.” (2004) Vol.17(1) South African Journal of Criminal Justice, 87 McCrudden, C. “Human Dignity and Judicial Interpretation of Human Rights.” (2008) Vol.19(4) The European Journal of International Law Meyer, M. “The Simple Dignity of Sentient Life: Speciesism and Human Dignity” (2009) Vol.32(2) Journal of Social Philosophy, 223 Pridgeon, J.L, “Euthanasia Legislation in the European Union: is a Universal Law Possible?” (2006) Vol.2(1) Hans Law Review, 45,46 Puppinick. G, and Houge. C, “The ‘Right’ to Assisted Suicide in the case law of the European Court of Human Rights’ (2014) Vol.18(7-8) The International Journal of Human Rights, 735 Rustin-Petru CIASC, “Euthanasia, National and International Perspectives” (2013) Vol.9(2) Acta Universitatis Danubius Juridica, 41 Wada, E. “A Pretty Picture: The Margin of Appreciation and the Right to Assisted Suicide” (2005) Vol.27 Loyola of Los Angeles International and Comparative Law Review, 275
  • 22. 22 Books Aharon Barak, Human Dignity: The Constitutional Value and the Constitutional Right (Cambridge University Press 2015) Catherine Dupre, The Age of Dignity (Hart Publishing 2015) David Albert Jones, “Is Dignity Language Useful in Bioethical Discussion of Assisted Suicide and Abortion?” in Christopher McCrudden (eds) Understanding Human Dignity (Oxford University Press) 525 Erin Daly, Dignity Rights: Courts, Constitutions and the Worth of the Human Person (University of Pennsylvania Press, 2013 Howard Charles Yourow, The Margin of Appreciation Doctrine in the Dynamics of European Human Rights Jurisprudence (Springer Publishers 1996) J.Harris, Is Cloning an Attack on Human Dignity? (Nature 1997) J.Harris, Clones, Genes and Immorality (Oxford University Press 1998) Jean Paul Costa, “Human Dignity in the Jurisprudence of the European Court of Human Rights” in Christopher McCrudden (eds) Understanding Human Dignity (Oxford University Press) 393 Ian Cameron and Maja Kirilova Eriksson, An Introduction to the European Convention on Human Rights (Lustus Förlag 1993) Karen Reid, A Practitioner’s Guide to the European Convention on Human Rights (Sweet and Maxwell 1998) Kant, I. Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals (2ND Revised Edition 1785, Translated by Mary J. Gregor and Jens Timmermann, Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy, 2012) Michael Rosen, Dignity: Its History and Meaning (Harvard University Press 2012) Ronald Dwarkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Harvard University Press, 1978) R, Dwarkin, Life’s Dominion: An Argument About Abortion, Euthanasia, and Individual Freedom (Vintage Books 1994) Howard Charles Yourow, The Margin of Appreciation Doctrine in the Dynamics of European Human Rights Jurisprudence (Springer Publishers 1996) Contributions to Edited Books Gordijn, Bert, Ben Crul and Zbigniew Zylicz ‘Euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide’, in Ten Have, H. and Clark, D (eds.), The Ethics of Palliative Care: European perspectives (Buckingham, Open University Press, 2002), 182. Jones, D.A. “Is Dignity Language Useful in Bioethical Discussion of Assisted Suicide and Abortion?” in Christopher McCrudden (eds) Understanding Human Dignity (Oxford University Press) 525
  • 23. 23 Jean Paul Costa, “Human Dignity in the Jurisprudence of the European Court of Human Rights” in Christopher McCrudden (eds) Understanding Human Dignity (Oxford University Press) 393 Factsheets European Court of Human Rights, “Factsheet- End of life and the ECHR”, July 2015 available at: < http://echr.coe.int/Pages/home.aspx?p=press/factsheets> Parliamentary Assembly of the Council of Europe Recommendation 1418 (1999) Resolution 1859 (2012), 12 January 2012, Protecting human rights and dignity by taking into account previously expressed wishes of patients. Reports Edeltraud Gatterer, Doc. 8421, Protection of the human rights and dignity in the terminally ill and dying, Report from Social, Health and Family Affairs Committee, 21/05/1999. Websites Derek Huphrey, Assisted Suicide Laws Around the World Last updated October 2015 available at: http://www.assistedsuicide.org/suicide_laws.html “Not Dead Yet” <http://notdeadyet.org/about> accessed 17/04/2016 “Not Dead Yet UK” <http://notdeadyetuk.org/> accessed 17/04/2016